Revision as of 14:35, 27 July 2004 editRmhermen (talk | contribs)Administrators62,561 edits restore article from Suspected Copyright Violation -original author posted this text← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 23:06, 10 September 2024 edit undoGreenC bot (talk | contribs)Bots2,555,703 edits Move 1 url. Wayback Medic 2.5 per WP:URLREQ#articles.chicagotribune.com | ||
(222 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{short description|American medical controversy}} | |||
'''Baby K – A Case Study in Futile Medical Care''' | |||
{{about|the baby|the rapper and model|Baby K (artist)}} | |||
{{Infobox person | |||
| name = Baby K | |||
| caption = Anencephalic | |||
| image = Anencephaly_front.jpg | |||
| birth_name = Stephanie Keene | |||
| birth_date = {{birth date|1992|10|13}} | |||
| birth_place = ] | |||
| death_date = {{dda|1995|4|5|1992|10|13}} | |||
| death_place = Falls Church, Virginia | |||
| known_for = Legal ramifications with life and being ] | |||
}} | |||
'''Stephanie Keene''' (October 13, 1992 – April 5, 1995), better known by the pseudonym '''Baby K''', was an ] baby who became the center of a major American ] and a debate among ]. | |||
Baby K was born in an anencephalic state on October 13, 1992, at Fairfax Hospital in Virginia. This is, she was born missing almost all of her brain. In fact, all that remained of her brain was the “brainstem”, that primitive part of the brain responsible (in part) for autonomic and regulatory function, such as the control of respiration, the heart beat and blood pressure . | |||
==History== | |||
About 1000 anencephalic infants are born annually in the United States. The condition, a form of neural tube defect, can often be diagnosed prenatally, for instance by ultrasonography. About 95% of women who learn that they will have an anencephalic baby choose to have an abortion. Of the remaining 5%, about 55% are stillborn. The rest—the remaining 1000—are said to be "born dying" . | |||
===Prenatal assessment=== | |||
The maternal serum alpha-fetoprotein (MSAFP) is useful for screening for neural tube defects such as spina bifida or anencephaly, but the gestational age of the fetus must be known for proper interpretation. The frequency of neural tube defects has been shown to be reduced if women supplement their diet with folic acid, especially during pregnancy . | |||
Stephanie Keene<ref name=rtd95 /> was born at ] in ], a hospital in the ]. At the time of her birth, she was missing most of her brain, including the cortex; only the ], the portion of the brain responsible for ] and regulatory functions, such as the control of ], the ] and ], had developed.<ref>{{Cite news |url=https://www.nytimes.com/1994/02/12/us/hospital-fights-parents-wish-to-keep-life-support-for-a-brain-dead-child.html?pagewanted=2&src=pm |title=Ruling in Virginia |location=Richmond |work=] |agency=] |date=February 11, 1994 |access-date=2017-02-14 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140201234120/http://www.nytimes.com/1994/02/12/us/hospital-fights-parents-wish-to-keep-life-support-for-a-brain-dead-child.html?pagewanted=2 |archive-date=2014-02-01 |url-status=live }}</ref> | |||
===Opposing viewpoints=== | |||
In more technical terms, anencephaly is an extreme neurological condition where the victim suffers from the congenital absence of any cerebral cortex or cerebellum, and consequently has only a reflexive, unconscious, brainstem existence. Lacking all cortical function, the victim lacks awareness and consciousness, cannot feel, see or perceive, and can neither suffer nor feel pain. Some clinicians would describe the situation as a form of permanent, irreversible, general anesthesia, and, in fact, it is generally supposed that anencephalic babies would not ordinarily need anesthetic drugs to allow surgery to take place . | |||
Keene's mother had been notified of her condition following ],<ref name=rtd95 /> and was advised to ] by her ] and ]<ref name="Flannery">{{cite journal| last=Flannery|first=Ellen J.| title=One advocate's viewpoint: conflict and tensions in the Baby K case| journal=The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics| publisher=American Society of Law, Medicine & Ethics| volume=23| issue=1| pages=7–12| doi=10.1111/j.1748-720X.1995.tb01323.x|pmid=7627307| date=2010-09-04}}</ref> but chose to carry the child to term because of "a firm ] faith that all life should be protected".<ref name=nyt93>{{cite news| last=Greenhouse| first=Linda| title=Hospital Appeals Ruling on Treating Baby with Most of Brain Gone| work=The New York Times| date=September 24, 1993| accessdate=May 25, 2009| page=A10| url=https://www.nytimes.com/1993/09/24/us/hospital-appeals-ruling-on-treating-baby-born-with-most-of-brain-gone.html?scp=4&sq=Baby%20K&st=nyt&pagewanted=1| archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220622114255/http://www.nytimes.com/1993/09/24/us/hospital-appeals-ruling-on-treating-baby-born-with-most-of-brain-gone.html?scp=4| archive-date=2022-06-22| url-status=live}}</ref> The hospital believed that care provided to the baby would be ],<ref name=nyt93 /> while the mother believed mechanical breathing support must be provided during the baby's periodic respiratory crises.<ref>{{cite news| last=Greenhouse| first=Linda| title=Court Order to Treat Baby With Partial Brain Prompts Debate on Costs and Ethics| work=The New York Times| date=February 20, 1994| accessdate=May 25, 2009| url=https://www.nytimes.com/1994/02/20/us/court-order-to-treat-baby-with-partial-brain-prompts-debate-on-costs-and-ethics.html?scp=5&sq=Baby+K&st=nyt| page=A20| archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220608052106/https://www.nytimes.com/1994/02/20/us/court-order-to-treat-baby-with-partial-brain-prompts-debate-on-costs-and-ethics.html?scp=5| archive-date=2022-06-08| url-status=live}}</ref> Fairfax Hospital doctors strongly advised a "]" order for the child, which the mother refused. Stephanie remained on ] support for six weeks while Fairfax searched for another hospital to transfer her to, but no other hospital would accept her. After the baby was weaned off constant ventilator support, the mother agreed to move the child to a nursing facility, but the baby returned to the hospital many times for respiratory problems. | |||
===Legal proceedings=== | |||
The diagnosis of anencephaly is almost always obvious on initial clinical examination of the neonate, because the skull is so small and misshapen, not having had the usually amount of internal brain substance to influence normal in utero skull development. Still, confirmation of the diagnosis by MRI or CT imaging studies can occasionally be helpful. | |||
When baby Keene was admitted to the hospital at six months of age for severe respiratory problems, the hospital filed a legal motion to appoint a guardian for the child's care and sought a court order that the hospital did not need to provide any services beyond ]. At trial, several experts testified that providing ventilator support to an anencephalic infant went beyond the accepted standard of medical care.<ref name="4th Circuit">''Matter of Baby K.'', 16 ] 590 (] 1994).</ref> In contrast, the baby's mother argued her case on the grounds of religious freedom and the ]. In a controversial ruling, the ] decided that the hospital caring for Keene must put her on a mechanical ventilator whenever she had trouble breathing. The court interpreted the ] (EMTALA) to require continued ventilation for the infant. The wording of this act requires that patients who present with a ] must get "such treatment as may be required to stabilize the medical condition" before the patient is transferred to another facility. The court refused to take a ] or ] position on the issue, insisting that it was only interpreting the laws as they existed. As a result of the decision, Keene was kept on the ventilator much longer than most anencephalic babies.<ref name=nyt93 /> It has been suggested by the dissenting judge in the case that the court should have used the condition anencephaly as the basis of the case, not the recurring subsidiary symptoms of respiratory distress. As the irreversibility of anencephaly is widely understood in the medical community, he argued that the decision to continue futile care only resulted in the repetitive diversion of medical equipment.<ref name="4th Circuit" /> | |||
Keene's cardiac death occurred on April 5, 1995, at Fairfax Hospital, at age of 2 years 174 days.<ref name=rtd95>{{cite news|work=]| title='Baby K' Dies at 2½ in Fairfax Hospital| date=1995-04-07| page=B.6| id={{ProQuest|423565783}}}} (Registration required)</ref> | |||
'''Management of Anencephalic Infants''' | |||
==Significance== | |||
In almost all cases anencephalic infants are not aggressively resuscitated since there is zero chance of the infant ever achieving a conscious existence. Instead, the usual clinical practice is to offer hydration, nutrition and comfort measures and to “let nature take its course.” Artificial ventilation, surgery (to fix any co-existing congenital defects), and drug therapy (such as antibiotics) are usually regarded as being pointless. | |||
The case of Baby K is of particular importance to the field of ] because of the issues it raises: the definition of death, the nature of ], the concept of ], and many issues relating to the allocation of scarce resources. Some commentators, including ] and ], have argued that the ruling effectively undermined the right of physicians to make sound medical decisions.<ref name="huffington-deathpanels">{{Cite news |url=http://www.huffingtonpost.com/jacob-m-appel/whats-so-wrong-with-death_b_366804.html |title=What's So Wrong with "Death Panels"? |first=Jacob M. |last=Appel |date=November 22, 2009 |work=] |access-date=2015-08-31 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150924231220/http://www.huffingtonpost.com/jacob-m-appel/whats-so-wrong-with-death_b_366804.html |archive-date=2015-09-24 |url-status=live }}</ref><ref>{{Cite news |url=https://www.chicagotribune.com/1994/02/20/court-says-doctors-must-treat-baby-k/ |title=Court Says Doctors Must Treat Baby K |author=New York Times News Service |date=February 20, 1994 |location=on |newspaper=Chicago Tribune] |access-date=2015-08-31 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304091839/http://articles.chicagotribune.com/1994-02-20/news/9402200448_1_periodic-respiratory-crises-anencephalic-babies-active-labor-act |archive-date=2016-03-04 |url-status=live }}</ref> | |||
==See also== | |||
Some clinicians see no point in even providing nutrition and hydration, arguing that withdrawal of nutrition and hydration is morally and clinically appropriate in such cases, as is sometimes done in the case of adults in a persistent vegetative state (e.g., the well-known case of Paul Brophy ). | |||
*] | |||
==References== | |||
One should understand that anencephalic babies are technically not brain dead, as they usually have intact brainstem reflexes. Yet there is strong clinical consensus that valiant efforts should not be employed to keep these infants alive. In fact, anencephaly and brain death may be the only two clinical situations that all virtually knowledgeable clinicians agree are futile to treat (except possibly to the extent necessary to allow organ harvesting). | |||
{{reflist}} | |||
==External links== | |||
Occasionally parents want clinicians to use all available means to keep anencephalic infants alive as long as possible. However, in most of these cases parents eventually come to realize that there is no possibility of a good outcome from such efforts, and end up agreeing with the clinical team. | |||
* at ] | |||
{{EthicsCases}} | |||
But not always. In the case of Baby K., Ms. H., the mother, wanted the hospital to continue with advanced supportive care (primarily ventilatory support) against the wishes of the clinical team, and sought legal support for her position. Ms. H. knew of her baby's condition from the second trimester of her pregnancy, but, motivated by a strong religious conviction that "all life is precious" and that God alone should decide how long the baby would live, she remained adamant that Baby K. be kept alive as long as possible. | |||
{{DEFAULTSORT:Baby K}} | |||
The hospital’s position was that such care would be futile. At the trial , expert testimony was given to demonstrate that provision of ventilator support for anencephalic infants goes beyond the accepted standard of care . The legal team for Baby K's mother adhered to a religious sanctity-of-life principle as the basis for their case. In the end, in a particularly controversial decision, the U. S. District Court ruled that the hospital caring for Baby K must put her on a mechanical ventilator whenever she had trouble breathing. In particular, the court interpreted the Emergency Medical Treatment and Active Labor Act (EMTALA) to require continued ventilation for the infant. The wording of this act requires that patients who present with a medical emergency must get "such treatment as may be required to stabilize the medical condition" before the patient is transferred to another facility. The court took the position that "it is beyond the limits of our judicial function to address the moral or ethical propriety of providing emergency stabilizing medical treatment to anencephalic infants. We are bound to interpret federal statutes in accordance with their plain language..." As a result of the decision, Baby K was kept alive much longer than most anencephalic babies, living to age 2 ½ . | |||
] | |||
] | |||
The court decision had more than mere clinical implications – as noted by Ronald M. Perkin , the decision stripped away the treating doctor’s prerogative to act as a “moral agent” and turned the health care team into mere “instruments of technology”. | |||
] | |||
] | |||
'''The Case Against Futile Medical Care''' | |||
] | |||
Arguments against futile care generally center on two issues. First, futile care has no possibility of achieving a good outcome and serves only to prolong death. No physical or spiritual benefit comes from such care. Futile care also prolongs the grieving process and frequently raises false hope. Also, futile care can be very difficult on caregivers, who may see themselves as forced to act against the best interests of their patient . | |||
Secondly, in a setting of limited resources, futile care involves the expenditure of resources that could be used by other patients with a good likelihood of achieving a positive outcome. For instance, in the case of Baby K, attempts to transfer the infant to other centers were unsuccessful because there were apparently no unoccupied pediatric ICU beds in the region . Note also that the medical costs for Baby K.’s care has been pegged at $500,000 . Such an amount of money might have been better spent, some ethicists would argue, on prenatal care aimed at preventing such neural tube defects (for instance, by encouraging the wide spread use of folic acid supplements in women). | |||
The issue of futile care in clinical medicine generally involves two issues. The first issue concerns the identification of those clinical scenarios where the care would be futile. The second issue concerns the range of ethical options when care is determined to be futile. | |||
Let us consider the first issue. While scenarios like providing ICU care to the brain dead patient or the anencephalic patient when organ harvesting is not possible or practical are easily identifiable as being completely futile, many other situations are less clear. For instance, should surgeons attempt a heroic clinical rescue in a 99 year old unconscious patient with a ruptured abdominal aortic aneurysm, even though survival with a good outcome would be so very unlikely as to warrant publication of the case as a clinical case report? What is actually true is that various bleak clinical scenarios will vary in their degree of futility. Another example: when elderly patients sustain large third degree burns, mortality can be very high. This is similarly true for elderly patients sustaining massive trauma. | |||
The last four decades has seen the clinical community make impressive efforts at improving the quality of their prognostic efforts. As a result, simple but imprecise rules of thumb like “percent mortality = age + percent burn” have now given way to very sophisticated algorithms based on multiple linear regression and other advanced statistical techniques . These are complex clinical algorithms that have been scientifically validated and have considerable clinical predictive value, particularly in the case of patients suffering severe burns . | |||
While one intent of such algorithms is to provide high-quality prognostic information to aid patients and families in making difficult decisions, it takes little imagination to see how they could be used to guide resource allocation in a setting of limited resources . | |||
Usually such prognostic algorithms produce an estimate of the probability of the patient surviving. While clinicians faced with difficult clinical scenarios where the probability of survival is, say, 30% might be expected to mount a valiant effort, when the chance of survival falls well below 1%, most clinicians would be expected to focus on palliative and comfort measures rather than attempting aggressive clinical measures. In a study of patients so severely burned that survival was clinically unprecedented , during the initial lucid period (before sepsis and other complications set in) patients were told that survival was extremely unlikely (i.e., that death was essentially inevitable) and were asked to choose between palliative care and aggressive clinical measures. Most chose aggressive clinical measures. This suggests that the will to live in patients can be very strong even in hopeless situations. | |||
As another practical clinical example that occurs very frequently in large hospitals, it can sometimes be problematic to decide whether or not to continue resuscitation when the resuscitation efforts following an in-hospital cardiac arrest have been prolonged. Clinicians often want to know when continuing resuscitation in such settings is futile. A recent study in JAMA has validated an algorithm developed for these purposes. | |||
The second issue in futile care theory concerns the range of ethical options when care is determined to be futile. Some people argue that futile clinical care should be a market commodity that should be able to be purchased just like cruise vacations or luxury automobiles, as long as the purchaser of the clinical services has the necessary funds and as long as other patients are not being denied access to clinical resources as a result. In this model, Baby K. would be able to get ICU care (primarily ventilatory care) until funding vanished. | |||
However, this market-oriented viewpoint is naïve in several respects. First, in almost all such cases the funding comes from insurance carriers, who must avoid “wasting” funds to ensure that adequate funds are available for other clients. Secondly, competition for ICU resources can be intense, and providing ICU resources to patients who will not benefit from them only makes access more difficult for patients for which ICU care would prove to be clinically beneficial. Finally, to view clinical care is a mere market commodity or service is to detach it from its underlying dignity and humanity, akin to those who would view sexual liaisons from a purely physiological perspective. (My apologies to those commercial sex workers who might disagree). | |||
'''Organ Harvesting from Anencephalic Infants''' | |||
Sometimes the parents of an anencephalic infant want clinicians to harvest their infant's organs to donate to other infants in need of new organs. This way, their grief can lead to another family's joy. This is especially important given that at the moment the only suitable organs for most infants are those from other infants. | |||
However, as noted earlier, anencephalics are not brain-dead. While debates have raged about whether it is appropriate to make an exception in such cases, this has not occurred to date. For instance, in 1992 the parents of an anencephalic baby called Baby Theresa wanted to donate her organs to a needy infant. However, the Florida Supreme Court would not declare her dead. When she died 10 days later, her organs were not suitable for transplantation. That day Baby Theresa's parents and a transplant surgeon appeared on the Phil Donahue Show to talk about the need to change the law . | |||
Perhaps some day the law will change. Some philosophers such as Joseph Fletcher and Peter Singer regard the possibility of a conscious existence as a prerequisite for attaining “personhood”. By such criteria Baby K was never a person and would not be granted the same moral standing as normally granted to conscious, self-aware, sentient persons. In such a setting anencephalic infants as well as patients in a persistent vegetative state would be suitable as organ donors even though they are not brain-dead . | |||
For more information on the varied issues involved in organ harvesting from anencephalic babies, the interested reader is referred to discussions from the Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics , the Bioethics Committee, Canadian Paediatric Society (CPS) and The Standing Committee on Ethical Aspects of Human Reproduction of the International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics (FIGO) . | |||
It is of interest to note the extent to which these authoritative bodies disagree. For instance, the Bioethics Committee of Canadian Paediatric Society takes a very cautious stand on the matter. Referring to the problems associated with waiting for anencephalic infants to meet formal brain death criteria, they note : | |||
"An alternative approach that has been suggested would be to allow the removal of organs before the anencephalic infant reaches a stage equivalent to conventional brain death. However, we strongly oppose this proposal on the following grounds. | |||
• It might be extended to other groups of "near-dead" patients, including those in a persistent vegetative state, those with other major abnormalities of the central nervous system and those who are chronically comatose. | |||
• It would lead to negative effects on people's confidence and trust in physicians in general and pediatricians in intensive care units in particular. | |||
• It would have negative effects on staff otherwise committed to caring for these patients. | |||
• It would be a further step toward the consideration of anencephalic infants simply as a means to an end." | |||
Compare this stand to that of the FIGO Standing Committee on Ethical Aspects of Human Reproduction : | |||
"There have been reports on the use of organs from anencephalic infants for transplantation. It is recognized that the ethical principles of beneficence and protection of the vulnerable can conflict. On the one hand, the principle of beneficence, the imperative of doing good, can apply to a person in need of organs. On the other hand, the principle of protection of the vulnerable newborn might apply in that an anencephalic infant might need protection against being treated as a means to another's advantage. | |||
In view of the potential ethical issue the following guidelines have been developed by the Committee. | |||
1. It is recognized that the purpose of organ donation constitutes an ethical ground for a woman to choose to maintain an anencephalic pregnancy, provided she is fully informed and counseled. | |||
2. When an infant is born with signs of life but has no forebrain (anencephaly) and hence has no prospect of survival, this infant may be declared brain dead, and with parental permission may be placed on a ventilator for the purpose of organ donation. Local legal definitions of death are binding but it is felt that these have to be reviewed to catch up with scientific development. " | |||
'''Conclusion''' | |||
The case of Baby K. is of particular importance to clinical bioethics because of the rich variety of issues it raises: defining death, the nature of personhood, the notion of moral stranding, medical futility concerns, caregiver issues, resource allocation concerns and much more. | |||
At a personal level, I cannot escape the feeling that in the case of Baby K., the court got it all wrong. Apparently, others share my opinion. In this respect, perhaps Ronald M. Perkin stated it best : | |||
“Prolonging the dying of Baby K was wrong. This was not a case of factual uncertainty, conceptual ambiguity or moral perplexity. The certainty of the fate of Baby K was so great among health care providers that there was no room for compromise. The decision to continue to provide care for this child was at the expense of the nurses' and other health care providers' integrity, and resulted in great suffering.” | |||
“The moral crisis in contemporary medicine is not the explosion of technology, but our failure, as a society, to have a sufficient sense of the physical and moral limits involved in any attempt to help and care for one another. Society is not providing medicine with guidance, and this lack of moral consensus to guide medical care intensifies its tragic character. The tragedy involved in the case of Baby K extended far beyond her birth defects.” | |||
'''Notes, Sources and References''' | |||
The brainstem is sometimes described by neuroscientists as “primitive” or “reptilian”, in part because it occurs early in evolutionary terms. However, note that the brainstem is not believed to be responsible for so-called “primitive” urges, emotions or drives – other brain structures such as the limbic system are generally taken to be the responsible entities. More information is available at http://thalamus.wustl.edu/course/brstem.html | |||
Source: http://www.georgetown.edu/research/nrcbl/ hsbioethics/ unit1_3.htm | |||
Source: http://www.cdc.gov/ncbddd/folicacid/default.htm | |||
This question has not been systematically addressed in the clinical literature, since few clinicians see any point in performing surgery in anencephalic babies. When we say that anencephalic babies would not ordinarily need anesthetic drugs for surgery, we means that drugs like propofol that eliminate consciousness would not be necessary; however, drugs to prevent reflex movements (mediated via intact brainstem nuclei and spinal reflexes) would likely still be needed for many surgical procedures. | |||
Brophy v. New England Sinai Hospital, Inc. 298 Mass. 417, 497 N.E.2d 626 (1986). | |||
Paul Brophy was an energetic middle-aged fireman in Massachusetts who sustained a devastating basilar artery aneurysm rupture with tragic neurologic consequences. Following the rupture he entered a persistent vegetative state with no chance of recovery. As he was unable to chew or swallow, a gastrostomy tube was eventually placed to allow for nutrition and hydration. Later, when it was obvious that there was no hope for even a modest degree of recovery, his family requested that his gastrostomy feedings be terminated, a request based on the fact that Mr. Brophy had verbally indicated that he would not want to exist in such a degraded state. However, the request for discontinuation of the gastrostomy tube was refused by the hospital treating Brophy, leading to a series of legal actions. While the first court to hear the case agreed that Mr. Brophy would have wanted the gastrostomy tube removed, it refused to authorize its removal, principally because he was not terminally ill. However, when the case went on further to the Supreme Judicial Court of Massachusetts, transfer of Mr. Brophy to another hospital facility that was agreeable to removal of the gastrostomy tube was authorized. Mr. Brophy died a number of days later, making him the first American to die after court-authorized discontinuation of artificially supplied nutrition and hydration to a comatose patient. | |||
Stephen G. Post, "Baby K: Medical Futility and the Free Exercise of Religion" Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 23, no. 1 (1995): 20-26. | |||
Ronald M. Perkin, MD. Stress and Distress in Pediatric Nurses: The Hidden Tragedy of Baby K. http://www.llu.edu/llu/bioethics/update12_2.htm | |||
For a somewhat different view from that of Perkins (above) consider the perspective of Dagi. Dagi argues against making the emotional needs of the caregiver an overriding consideration in clinical ethics, arguing that the claim of health care workers to be a professional “places legitimate constraints on the extent to which they may be permitted to have their needs and wants influence the ethical dialectic.” T. F. Dagi, "Compassion, Consensus, and Conflict: Should Caregivers' Needs Influence the Ethical Dialectic?" The Journal of Clinical Ethics 3 (1992): 214-18. | |||
Another possible scenario is that a few pediatric ICU beds were actually available in the region, but that the clinical ICU directors refused to accept Baby K. so as to avoid the inevitable legal tangles, as well as to avoid “squandering” valuable clinical resources. The simplest way to do this is to respond that all ICU beds are occupied when asked about the possibility of a transfer. This form of clinical white lie, while apparently quite common, does not appear to have been systematically studied by bioethicists. | |||
Hosmer DW Jr, Lemeshow S. Applied logistic regression. New York: John Wiley, 1989. | |||
. Ryan CM, Schoenfeld DA, Thorpe WP, Sheridan RL, Cassem EH, Tompkins RG. Objective estimates of the probability of death from burn injuries. N Engl J Med 1998;338:362-6 | |||
. Smith DL, Cairns BA, Ramadan F, et al. Effect of inhalation injury, burn size and age on mortality: a study of 1447 consecutive burn patients. J Trauma 1994;37:655-9. | |||
. Knaus WA, Wagner DP, Lynn J. Short-term mortality predictions for critically ill hospitalized adults: science and ethics. Science 1991;254:389-94. | |||
Imbus SH. Zawacki BE. Autonomy for burned patients when survival is unprecedented. New England Journal of Medicine. 297:308-11, 1977 | |||
van Walraven C, Forster AJ, Parish DC, et al. Validation of a clinical decision aid to discontinue in-hospital arrest resuscitations. JAMA 2001; 285:1602-1606. | |||
A book by Peter Singer discusses these issues at length: Peter A. Singer. Rethinking Life and Death: The Collapse of Our Traditional Values. St. Martin's Griffin (New York) 1994 | |||
Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics. Infants with Anencephaly as Organ Sources: Ethical Considerations. Pediatrics. Volume 89, Number 6 June Part 1, 1992, p 1116-1119. | |||
Bioethics Committee, Canadian Paediatric Society (CPS) Transplantation of organs from newborns with anencephaly. Canadian Medical Association Journal 1990; 142(7): 715-717 | |||
http://www.md.huji.ac.il/figo/figo5.htm | |||
'''Abbreviations Used''' | |||
CPS - Canadian Paediatric Society | |||
CT – Computed Tomography | |||
FIGO - International Federation of Gynecology and Obstetrics | |||
ICU – Intensive Care Unit | |||
JAMA – Journal of the American Medical Association | |||
MSAFP - Maternal Serum Alpha-Fetoprotein | |||
MR – Magnetic Resonance | |||
MRI – Magnetic Resonance Imaging | |||
'''Additional Resources''' | |||
• Post SG. Baby K: medical futility and the free exercise of religion. J Law Med Ethics. 1995;23:20-6. | |||
• Medical Task Force on Anencephaly, "The Infant with Anencephaly," New England Journal of Medicine 322 (1990): 669-74. | |||
• G. J. Annas, "Asking the Courts to Set the Standard of Emergency Care--The Case of Baby K," New England Journal of Medicine 330 (1994): 1542-45. | |||
• Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, American Medical Association. "The Use of Anencephalic Neonates as Organ Donors" The Journal of the American Medical Association 273.20 (1995): 1614-1618. | |||
• Schneiderman LJ, Jecker NS, Jonsen AR. Medical futility: its meaning and ethical implications. Ann Intern Med. 1990;112:949-54. | |||
• Jecker NS, Schneiderman LJ. Medical futility: the duty not to treat. Camb Q Healthc Ethics. 1993;2:151-9. | |||
• Prendergast TJ. Futility and the common cold. How requests for antibiotics can illuminate care at the end of life. Chest. 1996;107:836-44. | |||
• Schneiderman LJ, Jecker NS. Wrong Medicine: Doctors, Patients, and Futile Treatment. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Univ Pr; 1995. | |||
• Jecker NS. Medical futility and care of dying patients. West J Med. 1995;163;287-91. | |||
• Veatch RM, Spicer CM. Medically futile care: the role of the physician in setting limits. Am J Law Med. 1992;18:15-36. | |||
• Truog RD, Brett AS, Frader J. The problem with futility. N Engl J Med. 1992;326;1560-4. | |||
• Jecker NS, Schneiderman LJ. Ceasing futile resuscitation in the field: ethical considerations. Arch Intern Med. 1992;152:2392-7. | |||
• Brody BA, Halevy A. Is futility a futile concept? J Med Philos. 1995;20:123-44. | |||
• Brody H. The physician's role in determining futility. J Am Geriatr Soc. 1994;42:875-8. | |||
D. John Doyle MD PhD | |||
July 2004 | |||
djdoyle@hotmail.com |
Latest revision as of 23:06, 10 September 2024
American medical controversy This article is about the baby. For the rapper and model, see Baby K (artist).Baby K | |
---|---|
Anencephalic | |
Born | Stephanie Keene (1992-10-13)October 13, 1992 Falls Church, Virginia |
Died | April 5, 1995(1995-04-05) (aged 2) Falls Church, Virginia |
Known for | Legal ramifications with life and being anencephalic |
Stephanie Keene (October 13, 1992 – April 5, 1995), better known by the pseudonym Baby K, was an anencephalic baby who became the center of a major American court case and a debate among bioethicists.
History
Prenatal assessment
Stephanie Keene was born at Fairfax Hospital in Falls Church, Virginia, a hospital in the Washington metropolitan area. At the time of her birth, she was missing most of her brain, including the cortex; only the brainstem, the portion of the brain responsible for autonomic and regulatory functions, such as the control of respiration, the heartbeat and blood pressure, had developed.
Opposing viewpoints
Keene's mother had been notified of her condition following ultrasonography, and was advised to terminate the pregnancy by her obstetrician and neonatologist but chose to carry the child to term because of "a firm Christian faith that all life should be protected". The hospital believed that care provided to the baby would be futile, while the mother believed mechanical breathing support must be provided during the baby's periodic respiratory crises. Fairfax Hospital doctors strongly advised a "do not resuscitate" order for the child, which the mother refused. Stephanie remained on ventilator support for six weeks while Fairfax searched for another hospital to transfer her to, but no other hospital would accept her. After the baby was weaned off constant ventilator support, the mother agreed to move the child to a nursing facility, but the baby returned to the hospital many times for respiratory problems.
Legal proceedings
When baby Keene was admitted to the hospital at six months of age for severe respiratory problems, the hospital filed a legal motion to appoint a guardian for the child's care and sought a court order that the hospital did not need to provide any services beyond palliative care. At trial, several experts testified that providing ventilator support to an anencephalic infant went beyond the accepted standard of medical care. In contrast, the baby's mother argued her case on the grounds of religious freedom and the sanctity of life. In a controversial ruling, the United States District Court for the Eastern District of Virginia decided that the hospital caring for Keene must put her on a mechanical ventilator whenever she had trouble breathing. The court interpreted the Emergency Medical Treatment and Active Labor Act (EMTALA) to require continued ventilation for the infant. The wording of this act requires that patients who present with a medical emergency must get "such treatment as may be required to stabilize the medical condition" before the patient is transferred to another facility. The court refused to take a moral or ethical position on the issue, insisting that it was only interpreting the laws as they existed. As a result of the decision, Keene was kept on the ventilator much longer than most anencephalic babies. It has been suggested by the dissenting judge in the case that the court should have used the condition anencephaly as the basis of the case, not the recurring subsidiary symptoms of respiratory distress. As the irreversibility of anencephaly is widely understood in the medical community, he argued that the decision to continue futile care only resulted in the repetitive diversion of medical equipment.
Keene's cardiac death occurred on April 5, 1995, at Fairfax Hospital, at age of 2 years 174 days.
Significance
The case of Baby K is of particular importance to the field of bioethics because of the issues it raises: the definition of death, the nature of personhood, the concept of futile medical care, and many issues relating to the allocation of scarce resources. Some commentators, including Arthur Kohrman and Jacob Appel, have argued that the ruling effectively undermined the right of physicians to make sound medical decisions.
See also
References
- ^ "'Baby K' Dies at 2½ in Fairfax Hospital". Richmond Times-Dispatch. 1995-04-07. p. B.6. ProQuest 423565783. (Registration required)
- "Ruling in Virginia". The New York Times. Richmond. Associated Press. February 11, 1994. Archived from the original on 2014-02-01. Retrieved 2017-02-14.
- Flannery, Ellen J. (2010-09-04). "One advocate's viewpoint: conflict and tensions in the Baby K case". The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics. 23 (1). American Society of Law, Medicine & Ethics: 7–12. doi:10.1111/j.1748-720X.1995.tb01323.x. PMID 7627307.
- ^ Greenhouse, Linda (September 24, 1993). "Hospital Appeals Ruling on Treating Baby with Most of Brain Gone". The New York Times. p. A10. Archived from the original on 2022-06-22. Retrieved May 25, 2009.
- Greenhouse, Linda (February 20, 1994). "Court Order to Treat Baby With Partial Brain Prompts Debate on Costs and Ethics". The New York Times. p. A20. Archived from the original on 2022-06-08. Retrieved May 25, 2009.
- ^ Matter of Baby K., 16 F. 3d 590 (4th Cir. 1994).
- Appel, Jacob M. (November 22, 2009). "What's So Wrong with "Death Panels"?". The Huffington Post. Archived from the original on 2015-09-24. Retrieved 2015-08-31.
- New York Times News Service (February 20, 1994). "Court Says Doctors Must Treat Baby K". Chicago Tribune]. on. Archived from the original on 2016-03-04. Retrieved 2015-08-31.