Misplaced Pages

Problem of time: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 14:05, 15 October 2022 editOwais Al Qarni (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, File movers, IP block exemptions, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers19,718 edits The thermal time hypothesisTags: Mobile edit Mobile web edit Advanced mobile edit← Previous edit Latest revision as of 09:29, 27 November 2024 edit undoWilliam M. Connolley (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers66,026 edits Time in general relativity: make grammar even more conventional. no comment on the content 
(47 intermediate revisions by 26 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{short description|Conceptual conflict between general relativity and quantum mechanics}} {{short description|Conceptual conflict between general relativity and quantum mechanics}}
{{expert needed|1=Physics|date=June 2015|reason=his article has some interesting ideas in it, but some of it is wrong, and a lot of it reads like an attempt by someone without deep expertise to summarize half-understood stuff that they've read}}


In ], the '''problem of time''' is a conceptual conflict between ] and ] in that quantum mechanics regards the flow of time as universal and absolute, whereas general relativity regards the flow of time as malleable and relative.<ref>{{Citation|last=Isham|first=C. J.|title=Canonical Quantum Gravity and the Problem of Time|date=1993|url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6|work=Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories|pages=157–287|editor-last=Ibort|editor-first=L. A.|series=NATO ASI Series|place=Dordrecht|publisher=Springer Netherlands|language=en|doi=10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6|isbn=978-94-011-1980-1|access-date=2021-01-04|editor2-last=Rodríguez|editor2-first=M. A.|arxiv=gr-qc/9210011}}; http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9210011</ref><ref>{{cite magazine | title=Quantum Gravity's Time Problem | author=Wolchover, Natalie | date=December 1, 2016 | magazine=Quanta Magazine | url=https://www.quantamagazine.org/quantum-gravitys-time-problem-20161201/}}</ref> This problem raises the question of what ] really is in a physical sense and whether it is truly a real, distinct phenomenon. It also involves the related question of why time seems to flow in a single direction, despite the fact that no known physical laws at the microscopic level seem to require a single direction.<ref>{{cite magazine | title=Newsflash: Time May Not Exist | author=Folger, Tim | date=June 12, 2007 | magazine=Discover | url=https://www.discovermagazine.com/the-sciences/newsflash-time-may-not-exist}}</ref> For macroscopic systems the ] of time is directly linked to ] such as the ]. In ], the '''problem of time''' is a conceptual conflict between ] and ]. Quantum mechanics regards the flow of time as universal and absolute, whereas general relativity regards the flow of time as malleable and relative.<ref>{{Citation |last=Isham |first=C. J. |title=Canonical Quantum Gravity and the Problem of Time |date=1993 |url=https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |work=Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories |pages=157–287 |editor-last=Ibort |editor-first=L. A. |series=NATO ASI Series |place=Dordrecht |publisher=Springer Netherlands |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |isbn=978-94-011-1980-1 |access-date=2021-01-04 |editor2-last=Rodríguez |editor2-first=M. A. |arxiv=gr-qc/9210011 |s2cid=116947742 }}</ref><ref>{{cite magazine | title=Quantum Gravity's Time Problem | author=Wolchover, Natalie | date=December 1, 2016 | magazine=Quanta Magazine | url=https://www.quantamagazine.org/quantum-gravitys-time-problem-20161201/}}</ref> This problem raises the question of what ] really is in a physical sense and whether it is truly a real, distinct phenomenon. It also involves the related question of why time seems to flow in a single direction, despite the fact that no known physical laws at the microscopic level seem to require a single direction.<ref>{{cite magazine | title=Newsflash: Time May Not Exist | author=Folger, Tim | date=June 12, 2007 | magazine=Discover | url=https://www.discovermagazine.com/the-sciences/newsflash-time-may-not-exist}}</ref>


== Time in quantum mechanics == == Time in quantum mechanics ==
In ], a special status is assigned to time in the sense that it is treated as a classical background parameter, external to the system itself. This special role is seen in the standard formulation of quantum mechanics. It is regarded as part of an a priori given classical background with a well defined value. In fact, the classical treatment of time is deeply intertwined with the ] of quantum mechanics, and, thus, with the conceptual foundations of quantum theory: all measurements of observables are made at certain instants of time and probabilities are only assigned to such measurements. In ], a special status is assigned to time in the sense that it is treated as a classical background parameter, external to the system itself. This special role is seen in the standard ] of quantum mechanics: all measurements of observables are made at certain instants of time and probabilities are only assigned to such measurements. Furthermore, the ] used in quantum theory relies on a complete set of ] which commute at a specific time.<ref name=AndersonReview2012>{{Cite journal |last=Anderson |first=E. |date=2012-12-15 |title=Problem of time in quantum gravity |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/andp.201200147 |journal=Annalen der Physik |language=en |volume=524 |issue=12 |pages=757–786 |doi=10.1002/andp.201200147 |issn=0003-3804|arxiv=1009.2157 |bibcode=2012AnP...524..757A }}</ref>{{rp|759}}


== Time in general relativity ==
] has modified the notion of time. But from a fixed ] observer's viewpoint time remains a distinguished, absolute, external, global parameter. The Newtonian notion of ] essentially carries over to special relativistic systems, hidden in the ] structure.


In ] time is no longer a unique background parameter, but a general coordinate. The field equations of general relativity are not parameterized by time but formulated in terms of spacetime. Many of the issues related to the problem of time exist within general relativity. At the cosmic scale, general relativity shows a closed universe with no external time. These two very different roles of time are incompatible.<ref name=AndersonReview2012/>
== Overturning of absolute time in general relativity ==
Though classically ] appears to be an absolute background, ] reveals that spacetime is actually dynamical; gravity is a manifestation of spacetime geometry. Matter reacts with spacetime: {{Quote|text=Spacetime tells matter how to move; matter tells spacetime how to curve.|author=]|source=''Geons, Black Holes, and Quantum Foam'', p. 235<ref name="Wheeler2010">{{cite book|author=John Archibald Wheeler|title=Geons, Black Holes, and Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zGFkK2tTXPsC|date=18 June 2010|publisher=W. W. Norton|isbn=978-0-393-07948-7|page=235}}</ref>}}


== Impact on quantum gravity ==
Also, spacetime can interact with itself (e.g. gravitational waves). The dynamical nature of spacetime has a vast array of consequences.
] describes theories that attempt to reconcile or unify ] and ], the current theory of gravity.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |date=2008-05-23 |title=Quantum gravity |journal=Scholarpedia |volume=3 |issue=5 |page=7117 |language=en |doi=10.4249/scholarpedia.7117|doi-access=free |bibcode=2008SchpJ...3.7117R }}</ref> The problem of time is central to these theoretical attempts. It remains unclear how time is related to quantum probability, whether time is fundamental or a consequence of processes, and whether time is approximate, among other issues. Different theories try different answers to the questions but no clear solution has emerged.<ref name="Isham1993">{{Cite book |last=Isham |first=C. J. |url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |title=Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories |date=1993 |publisher=Springer Netherlands |isbn=978-94-011-1980-1 |editor-last=Ibort |editor-first=L. A. |location=Dordrecht |pages=157–287 |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |editor-last2=Rodríguez |editor-first2=M. A.}}</ref>


== The Frozen Formalism Problem ==
{{confusing section|reason=vocabulary needs to be explained: diffeomorphism, Hamiltonian, ], perennials, partial observables. Need to illustrate with example|date=September 2014}}
The most commonly discussed aspect of the problem of time is the '''Frozen Formalism Problem'''. The ] includes time evolution:
The dynamical nature of spacetime, via the ], implies that the theory is ] invariant. The constraints are the imprint in the canonical theory of the diffeomorphism invariance of the four-dimensional theory. They also contain the dynamics of the theory, since the Hamiltonian is zero (identically vanishes). The quantum theory has no explicit dynamics; wavefunctions are annihilated by the constraints and Dirac observables commute with the constraints and hence are constants of motion. Kuchar introduces the idea of "perennials" and Rovelli the idea of "partial observables". The expectation is that in physical situations some of the variables of the theory will play the role of a "time" with respect to which other variables would evolve and define dynamics in a relational way. This runs into difficulties and is a version of the "problem of time" in the canonical quantization.<ref>K. Kuchar, in "Proceedings of the 4th Canadian meeting on Relativity and Relativistic Astrophysics", editors G. Kunstatter, D. Vincent, J. Williams, World Scientific, Singapore (1992).</ref>
<math display="block">i\hbar {\frac {\partial}{\partial t}} \psi (t) =H \psi (t), </math>
where <math>H</math> is an ] characterizing the system and the wave function <math>\psi (t)</math> over space evolves in time, {{mvar|t}}.
In general relativity the energy operator becomes a constraint in the ]:
<math display="block">\hat{H}(x) |\psi\rangle = 0,</math>
where the operator varies throughout space, but the wavefunction here, called the wavefunction of the universe, is constant. Consequently this cosmic universal wavefunction is frozen and does not evolve. Somehow, at a smaller scale, the laws of physics, including a concept of time, apply within the universe while the cosmic level is static.<ref name=AndersonReview2012/>{{rp|762}}


== Proposed solutions to the problem of time == == Proposed solutions to the problem of time ==
The quantum concept of time first emerged from early research on quantum gravity, in particular from the work of ] in the 1960s:<ref name="Deutsch2011">{{cite book|author=David Deutsch|title=The Fabric of Reality|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Z7uFxViR19oC&pg=PT240|date=14 April 2011|publisher=Penguin Books Limited|isbn=978-0-14-196961-9|page=240}}</ref>


Work started by ] and ]<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Page |first1=Don N. |last2=Wootters |first2=William K. |date=1983-06-15 |title=Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=27 |issue=12 |pages=2885–2892 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885|bibcode=1983PhRvD..27.2885P }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |date=1990-10-15 |title=Quantum mechanics without time: A model |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.42.2638 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=42 |issue=8 |pages=2638–2646 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.42.2638|pmid=10013133 |bibcode=1990PhRvD..42.2638R }}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Giovannetti |first1=Vittorio |last2=Lloyd |first2=Seth |last3=Maccone |first3=Lorenzo |date=2015-08-26 |title=Quantum time |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.92.045033 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=92 |issue=4 |pages=045033 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.92.045033|arxiv=1504.04215 |bibcode=2015PhRvD..92d5033G |hdl=1721.1/98287 |s2cid=85537706 }}</ref> suggests that the universe appears to evolve for observers on the inside because of energy entanglement between
{{Quote|text=''"Other times are just special cases of other universes."''}}
an evolving system and a clock system, both within the universe.<ref name=Moreva2014/> In this way the overall system can remain timeless while parts experience time via entanglement. The issue remains an open question closely related to attempted theories of quantum gravity.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Altaie |first1=M. Basil |last2=Hodgson |first2=Daniel |last3=Beige |first3=Almut |date=2022-06-03 |title=Time and Quantum Clocks: A Review of Recent Developments |journal=Frontiers in Physics |language=English |volume=10 |doi=10.3389/fphy.2022.897305 |doi-access=free |arxiv=2203.12564 |bibcode=2022FrP....10.7305A |issn=2296-424X}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last=Isham |first=C. J. |url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |title=Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories |date=1993 |publisher=Springer Netherlands |isbn=978-94-011-1980-1 |editor-last=Ibort |editor-first=L. A. |location=Dordrecht |pages=157–287 |language=en |doi=10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6 |editor-last2=Rodríguez |editor-first2=M. A.}}</ref>
In other words, time is an ] phenomenon, which places all equal clock readings (of correctly prepared clocks – or any objects usable as clocks) into the same history.


In 2013, at the Istituto Nazionale di Ricerca Metrologica (INRIM) in Turin, Italy, Ekaterina Moreva, together with Giorgio Brida, Marco Gramegna, Vittorio Giovannetti, Lorenzo Maccone, and Marco Genovese performed the first experimental test of Page and Wootters' ideas. They confirmed for photons that time is an emergent phenomenon for internal observers but absent for external observers of the universe just as the ] predicts.<ref name=Moreva2014>{{cite web |title=Quantum Experiment Shows How Time 'Emerges' from Entanglement |url=https://medium.com/the-physics-arxiv-blog/quantum-experiment-shows-how-time-emerges-from-entanglement-d5d3dc850933 |website=The Physics arXiv Blog |date=Oct 23, 2013 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170603063357/https://medium.com/the-physics-arxiv-blog/quantum-experiment-shows-how-time-emerges-from-entanglement-d5d3dc850933 |archive-date=2017-06-03}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Moreva |first1=Ekaterina |last2=Brida |first2=Giorgio |last3=Gramegna |first3=Marco |last4=Giovannetti |first4=Vittorio |last5=Maccone |first5=Lorenzo |last6=Genovese |first6=Marco |title=Time from quantum entanglement: An experimental illustration |journal=Physical Review A |date=20 May 2014 |volume=89 |issue=5 |page=052122 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.89.052122 |arxiv=1310.4691 |bibcode=2014PhRvA..89e2122M |s2cid=118638346 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Moreva |first1=Ekaterina |last2=Gramegna |first2=Marco |last3=Brida |first3=Giorgio |last4=Maccone |first4=Lorenzo |last5=Genovese |first5=Marco |title=Quantum time: Experimental multitime correlations |journal=Physical Review D |date=16 November 2017 |volume=96 |issue=5 |page=102005 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.96.102005 |arxiv=1710.00707 |bibcode=2017PhRvD..96j2005M |s2cid=119431509 }}</ref>
In other words, time is an ] phenomenon, which places all equal clock readings (of correctly prepared clocks – or of any objects usable as clocks) into the same history. This was first understood by physicists ] and ] in 1983.<ref>{{cite book|first = David|last = Deutsch|title= The Beginning of Infinity: Explanations that Transform The World| page= 299|date = 2011|publisher = Penguin UK|url = https://books.google.com/books?id=ex5xge75SR4C|isbn = 9780141969695}}</ref> They made a proposal to address the problem of time in systems like general relativity called conditional probabilities interpretation.<ref>{{cite journal|last1 = Page|first1 = Don N.|last2 = Wootters|first2 = William K.|date = 15 June 1983|journal = Phys. Rev. D|volume = 27|page = 2885|title = Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables|issue = 12|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885|bibcode =1983PhRvD..27.2885P}}</ref> It consists in promoting all variables to quantum operators, one of them as a clock, and asking conditional probability questions with respect to other variables. They arrived at a solution based on the quantum phenomenon of entanglement. Page and Wootters showed how ] can be used to measure time.<ref>{{cite web|last1=Aron|first1=Jacob|title=Entangled toy universe shows time may be an illusion|url=https://www.newscientist.com//article/dn24473-entangled-toy-universe-shows-time-may-be-an-illusion|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20161018065554/http://www.newscientist.com//article/dn24473-entangled-toy-universe-shows-time-may-be-an-illusion|archive-date=2016-10-18|date=October 25, 2013}}</ref>


Consistent discretizations approach developed by ] and ] have no constraints. These are lattice approximation techniques for quantum gravity. In the canonical approach, if one discretizes the constraints and equations of motion, the resulting discrete equations are inconsistent: they cannot be solved simultaneously. To address this problem, one uses a technique based on discretizing the action of the theory and working with the discrete equations of motion. These are automatically guaranteed to be consistent. Most of the hard conceptual questions of quantum gravity are related to the presence of constraints in the theory. Consistent discretized theories are free of these conceptual problems and can be straightforwardly quantized, providing a solution to the problem of time. It is a bit more subtle than this. Although without constraints and having "general evolution", the latter is only in terms of a discrete parameter that isn't physically accessible. The way out is addressed in a way similar to the Page–Wooters approach. The idea is to pick one of the physical variables to be a clock and ask relational questions. These ideas, where the clock is also quantum mechanical, have actually led to a new interpretation of quantum mechanics — the ] of quantum mechanics.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gambini |first1=Rodolfo |last2=Pullin |first2=Jorge |title=The Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics: frequently asked questions |journal=Journal of Physics: Conference Series |date=1 June 2009 |volume=174 |issue=1 |pages=012003 |doi=10.1088/1742-6596/174/1/012003 |arxiv=0905.4402 |bibcode=2009JPhCS.174a2003G |s2cid=250680865 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gambini| first1=Rodolfo |last2=Garc?a-Pintos |first2=Luis Pedro |last3=Pullin |first3=Jorge |title=An axiomatic formulation of the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics |date=November 2011 |volume=42 |issue=4 |pages=256–263 |doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.10.002 |arxiv=1002.4209 |url=http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9927/ |bibcode=2011SHPMP..42..256G |s2cid=993508 }}</ref> This new interpretation solves the problems of the use of environmental decoherence as a solution to the ] in quantum mechanics by invoking fundamental limitations, due to the quantum mechanical nature of clocks, in the process of measurement. These limitations are very natural in the context of generally covariant theories as quantum gravity where the clock must be taken as one of the degrees of freedom of the system itself. They have also put forward this fundamental decoherence as a way to resolve the ].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gambini |first1=Rodolfo |last2=Porto |first2=Rafael A. |last3=Pullin |first3=Jorge |title=No Black Hole Information Puzzle In A Relational Universe |journal=International Journal of Modern Physics D |date=December 2004 |volume=13 |issue=10 |pages=2315–2320 |doi=10.1142/S0218271804006383 |arxiv=hep-th/0405183 |bibcode=2004IJMPD..13.2315G |s2cid=119424485 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gambini |first1=Rodolfo |last2=Porto |first2=Rafael A. |last3=Pullin |first3=Jorge |title=Realistic Clocks, Universal Decoherence, and the Black Hole Information Paradox |journal=Physical Review Letters |date=6 December 2004 |volume=93 |issue=24 |page=240401 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.93.240401 |pmid=15697783 |arxiv=hep-th/0406260 |bibcode=2004PhRvL..93x0401G |s2cid=25174047 }}</ref> In certain circumstances, a matter field is used to de-parametrize the theory and introduce a physical Hamiltonian. This generates physical time evolution, not a constraint.
In 2013, at the Istituto Nazionale di Ricerca Metrologica (INRIM) in Turin, Italy, Ekaterina Moreva, together with Giorgio Brida, Marco Gramegna, Vittorio Giovannetti, Lorenzo Maccone, and Marco Genovese performed the first experimental test of Page and Wootters' ideas. They confirmed that time is an emergent phenomenon for internal observers but absent for external observers of the universe just as the ] predicts.<ref>{{cite web|title=Quantum Experiment Shows How Time 'Emerges' from Entanglement|url=https://medium.com/the-physics-arxiv-blog/quantum-experiment-shows-how-time-emerges-from-entanglement-d5d3dc850933|website=The Physics arXiv Blog|date=Oct 23, 2013|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170603063357/https://medium.com/the-physics-arxiv-blog/quantum-experiment-shows-how-time-emerges-from-entanglement-d5d3dc850933|archive-date=2017-06-03}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Moreva|first1=Ekaterina|last2=Brida|first2=Giorgio|last3=Gramegna|first3=Marco|last4=Giovannetti|first4=Vittorio|last5=Maccone|first5=Lorenzo|last6=Genovese|first6=Marco|title=Time from quantum entanglement: An experimental illustration|journal=Physical Review A|date=20 May 2014|volume=89|issue=5|page=052122|doi=10.1103/PhysRevA.89.052122|arxiv=1310.4691|bibcode=2014PhRvA..89e2122M}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Moreva|first1=Ekaterina|last2=Gramegna|first2=Marco|last3=Brida|first3=Giorgio|last4=Maccone|first4=Lorenzo|last5=Genovese|first5=Marco|title=Quantum time: Experimental multitime correlations|journal=Physical Review D|date=16 November 2017|volume=96 |issue=5|page=102005|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.96.102005|arxiv=1710.00707|bibcode=2017PhRvD..96j2005M}}</ref>


Reduced phase-space quantization constraints are solved first and then quantized. This approach was considered for some time to be impossible, as it seems to require first finding the general solution to Einstein's equations. However, with the use of ideas involved in Dittrich's approximation scheme (built on ideas of ]) a way to explicitly implement, at least in principle, a reduced phase-space quantization was made viable.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Thiemann |first1=T. |title=Reduced phase space quantization and Dirac observables |journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity |date=21 February 2006 |volume=23 |issue=4 |pages=1163–1180 |doi=10.1088/0264-9381/23/4/006 |arxiv=gr-qc/0411031 |bibcode=2006CQGra..23.1163T |s2cid=17230218}}</ref>
Consistent discretizations approach developed by ] and ] have no constraints. These are lattice approximation techniques for quantum gravity. In the canonical approach if one discretizes the constraints and equations of motion, the resulting discrete equations are inconsistent: they cannot be solved simultaneously. To address this problem one uses a technique based on discretizing the action of the theory and working with the discrete equations of motion. These are automatically guaranteed to be consistent. Most of the hard conceptual questions of quantum gravity are related to the presence of constraints in the theory. Consistent discretized theories are free of these conceptual problems and can be straightforwardly quantized, providing a solution to the problem of time. It is a bit more subtle than this. Although without constraints and having "general evolution", the latter is only in terms of a discrete parameter that isn't physically accessible. The way out is addressed in a way similar to the Page–Wooters approach. The idea is to pick one of the physical variables to be a clock and asks relational questions. These ideas, where the clock is also quantum mechanical, have actually led to a new interpretation of quantum mechanics — the ] of quantum mechanics.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Gambini|first1=Rodolfo|last2=Pullin|first2=Jorge|title=The Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics: frequently asked questions|journal=Journal of Physics: Conference Series|date=1 June 2009|volume=174|issue=1|pages=012003|doi=10.1088/1742-6596/174/1/012003|arxiv=0905.4402|bibcode=2009JPhCS.174a2003G}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Gambini|first1=Rodolfo|last2=Garc?a-Pintos|first2=Luis Pedro|last3=Pullin|first3=Jorge|title=An axiomatic formulation of the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics|journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics|date=November 2011|volume=42|issue=4|pages=256–263|doi=10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.10.002|arxiv=1002.4209|url=http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9927/|bibcode=2011SHPMP..42..256G}}</ref> This new interpretation solves the problems of the use of environmental decoherence as a solution to the ] in quantum mechanics by invoking fundamental limitations, due to the quantum mechanical nature of clocks, in the process of measurement in quantum mechanics. These limitations are very natural in the context of generally covariant theories as quantum gravity where the clock must be taken as one of the degrees of freedom of the system itself. They have also put forward this fundamental decoherence as a way to resolve the ].<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Gambini|first1=Rodolfo|last2=Porto|first2=Rafael A.|last3=Pullin|first3=Jorge|title=No Black Hole Information Puzzle In A Relational Universe|journal=International Journal of Modern Physics D|date=December 2004|volume=13|issue=10|pages=2315–2320|doi=10.1142/S0218271804006383|arxiv=hep-th/0405183|bibcode=2004IJMPD..13.2315G}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Gambini|first1=Rodolfo|last2=Porto|first2=Rafael A.|last3=Pullin|first3=Jorge|title=Realistic Clocks, Universal Decoherence, and the Black Hole Information Paradox|journal=Physical Review Letters|date=6 December 2004|volume=93|issue=24|page=240401|doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.93.240401|pmid=15697783|arxiv=hep-th/0406260|bibcode=2004PhRvL..93x0401G}}</ref> In certain circumstances, a matter field is used to de-parametrize the theory and introduce a physical Hamiltonian. This generates physical time evolution, not a constraint.


] and Shahar Dolev argue that quantum-mechanical experiments such as the "quantum liar"<ref>Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2005). . In Quo vadis quantum mechanics? (pp.&nbsp;325–349). Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg.</ref> provide evidence of inconsistent histories, and that spacetime itself may therefore be subject to change affecting entire histories.<ref>Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2003). . In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception (pp.&nbsp;297–306). Springer, Dordrecht.</ref> Elitzur and Dolev also believe that an objective passage of time and relativity can be reconciled and that it would resolve many of the issues with the block universe and the conflict between relativity and quantum mechanics.<ref>Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2005). . In Endophysics, Time, Quantum And The Subjective: (With CD-ROM) (pp.&nbsp;589–606).</ref>
Reduced phase space quantization constraints are solved first then quantized. This approach was considered for some time to be impossible as it seems to require first finding the general solution to Einstein's equations. However, with use of ideas involved in Dittrich's approximation scheme (built on ideas of Rovelli) a way to explicitly implement, at least in principle, a reduced phase space quantization was made viable.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Thiemann|first1=T|title=Reduced phase space quantization and Dirac observables|journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity|date=21 February 2006|volume=23|issue=4|pages=1163–1180|doi=10.1088/0264-9381/23/4/006|arxiv=gr-qc/0411031|bibcode=2006CQGra..23.1163T}}</ref>


One solution to the problem of time proposed by ] is that there exists a "thick present" of events, in which two events in the present can be causally related to each other, but in contrast to the block-universe view of time in which all time exists ].<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Smolin | first1 = L. | year = 2015 | title = Temporal naturalism | arxiv = 1805.12468 | journal = Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics | volume = 52 | pages = 86–102 | doi = 10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.03.005 | bibcode = 2015SHPMP..52...86S | s2cid = 8344858 }}</ref> Marina Cortês and Lee Smolin argue that certain classes of discrete dynamical systems demonstrate time asymmetry and irreversibility, which is consistent with an objective passage of time.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Cortês | first1 = M. | last2 = Smolin | first2 = L. | year = 2018 | title = Reversing the irreversible: from limit cycles to emergent time symmetry | arxiv=1703.09696 | journal = Physical Review D | volume = 97 | issue = 2 | page = 026004 | doi = 10.1103/physrevd.97.026004 | bibcode = 2018PhRvD..97b6004C | s2cid = 119067096 }}</ref>
] and Shahar Dolev argue that quantum mechanical experiments such as the Quantum Liar<ref>Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2005). . In Quo vadis quantum mechanics? (pp. 325-349). Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg.</ref> provide evidence of inconsistent histories, and that spacetime itself may therefore be subject to change affecting entire histories.<ref>Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2003). . In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception (pp. 297-306). Springer, Dordrecht.</ref> Elitzur and Dolev also believe that an objective passage of time and relativity can be reconciled, and that it would resolve many of the issues with the block universe and the conflict between relativity and quantum mechanics.<ref>Elitzur, A. C., & Dolev, S. (2005). . In Endophysics, Time, Quantum And The Subjective: (With CD-ROM) (pp. 589-606).</ref>

One solution to the problem of time proposed by ] is that there exists a "thick present" of events, in which two events in the present can be causally related to each other, but in contrast to the block universe view of time in which all time exists ].<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Smolin | first1 = L | year = 2015 | title = Temporal naturalism | arxiv = 1805.12468 | journal = Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics | volume = 52 | pages = 86–102 | doi = 10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.03.005 }}</ref> Marina Cortês and Lee Smolin argue that certain classes of discrete dynamical systems demonstrate time asymmetry and irreversibility, which is consistent with an objective passage of time.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Cortês | first1 = M. | last2 = Smolin | first2 = L. | year = 2018 | title = Reversing the irreversible: from limit cycles to emergent time symmetry | arxiv=1703.09696 | journal = Physical Review D | volume = 97 | issue = 2| page = 026004 | doi = 10.1103/physrevd.97.026004 }}</ref>


== Weyl time in scale-invariant quantum gravity == == Weyl time in scale-invariant quantum gravity ==
Motivated by the ] in ] and the near conformal invariance of the standard model of elementary particles,<ref>{{Cite journal|date=2007-05-10|title=Conformal symmetry and the Standard Model|url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0370269307003486|journal=Physics Letters B|language=en|volume=648|issue=4|pages=312–317|doi=10.1016/j.physletb.2007.03.023| arxiv=hep-th/0612165|issn=0370-2693|doi-access=free|last1=Meissner|first1=Krzysztof A.|last2=Nicolai|first2=Hermann}}</ref> ] and co-workers have argued that the problem of time may be related to an underlying ] of gravity-matter systems.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal|last1=Wang|first1=Charles H.-T.|last2=Stankiewicz|first2=Marcin|date=2020-01-10|title=Quantization of time and the big bang via scale-invariant loop gravity|url=https://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0370269319308287|journal=Physics Letters B|language=en|volume=800|pages=135106|doi=10.1016/j.physletb.2019.135106|arxiv=1910.03300|issn=0370-2693|doi-access=free}}</ref><ref name=":1">{{Cite journal|last1=Wang|first1=Charles H.-T.|last2=Rodrigues|first2=Daniel P. F.|date=2018-12-28|title=Closing the gaps in quantum space and time: Conformally augmented gauge structure of gravitation|url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041|journal=Physical Review D|volume=98|issue=12|pages=124041|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041|hdl=2164/11713|hdl-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Wang|first=Charles H.-T.|date=2005-10-06|title=Unambiguous spin-gauge formulation of canonical general relativity with conformorphism invariance|url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501|journal=Physical Review D|volume=72|issue=8|pages=087501|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501|arxiv=gr-qc/0507044}}</ref> Scale invariance has also been proposed to resolve the hierarchy problem of fundamental couplings.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Shaposhnikov|first1=Mikhail|last2=Shkerin|first2=Andrey|date=2018-10-03|title=Gravity, scale invariance and the hierarchy problem|journal=Journal of High Energy Physics|language=en|volume=2018|issue=10|pages=24|doi=10.1007/JHEP10(2018)024|issn=1029-8479|doi-access=free}}</ref> As a global continuous symmetry, scale invariance generates a conversed Weyl current<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":1" /> according to ]. In scale-invariant cosmological models, this Weyl current naturally gives rise to a harmonic time.<ref>{{Cite journal|last1=Ferreira|first1=Pedro G.|last2=Hill|first2=Christopher T.|last3=Ross|first3=Graham G.|date=2017-02-08|title=Weyl current, scale-invariant inflation, and Planck scale generation|url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043507|journal=Physical Review D|volume=95|issue=4|pages=043507|doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043507|doi-access=free}}</ref> In the context of loop quantum gravity, Charles Wang et al suggest that scale invariance may lead to the existence of a quantized time.<ref name=":0" /> Motivated by the ] in ] and the near-conformal invariance of the standard model of elementary particles,<ref>{{Cite journal |date=2007-05-10 |title=Conformal symmetry and the Standard Model |journal=Physics Letters B |language=en |volume=648 |issue=4 |pages=312–317 |doi=10.1016/j.physletb.2007.03.023 |arxiv=hep-th/0612165 |issn=0370-2693 |doi-access=free |last1=Meissner |first1=Krzysztof A. |last2=Nicolai |first2=Hermann |bibcode=2007PhLB..648..312M }}</ref> ] and co-workers have argued that the problem of time may be related to an underlying ] of gravity–matter systems.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal |last1=Wang |first1=Charles H.-T. |last2=Stankiewicz |first2=Marcin |date=2020-01-10 |title=Quantization of time and the big bang via scale-invariant loop gravity |journal=Physics Letters B |language=en |volume=800 |pages=135106 |doi=10.1016/j.physletb.2019.135106 |arxiv=1910.03300 |bibcode=2020PhLB..80035106W |issn=0370-2693 |doi-access=free}}</ref><ref name=":1">{{Cite journal |last1=Wang |first1=Charles H.-T. |last2=Rodrigues |first2=Daniel P. F. |date=2018-12-28 |title=Closing the gaps in quantum space and time: Conformally augmented gauge structure of gravitation |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=98 |issue=12 |pages=124041 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041 |arxiv=1810.01232 |bibcode=2018PhRvD..98l4041W |hdl=2164/11713 |s2cid=118961037 |hdl-access=free}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Wang |first=Charles H.-T. |date=2005-10-06 |title=Unambiguous spin-gauge formulation of canonical general relativity with conformorphism invariance |url=https://link.aps.org/doi/10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501 |journal=Physical Review D |volume=72 |issue=8 |pages=087501 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501 |arxiv=gr-qc/0507044 |bibcode=2005PhRvD..72h7501W |s2cid=34995566 }}</ref> Scale invariance has also been proposed to resolve the hierarchy problem of fundamental couplings.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Shaposhnikov |first1=Mikhail |last2=Shkerin |first2=Andrey |date=2018-10-03 |title=Gravity, scale invariance and the hierarchy problem |journal=Journal of High Energy Physics |language=en |volume=2018 |issue=10 |pages=24 |doi=10.1007/JHEP10(2018)024 |issn=1029-8479 |doi-access=free |arxiv=1804.06376 |bibcode=2018JHEP...10..024S }}</ref> As a global continuous symmetry, scale invariance generates a conserved Weyl current<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":1" /> according to ]. In scale-invariant cosmological models, this Weyl current naturally gives rise to a harmonic time.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Ferreira |first1=Pedro G. |last2=Hill |first2=Christopher T. |last3=Ross |first3=Graham G. |date=2017-02-08 |title=Weyl current, scale-invariant inflation, and Planck scale generation |journal=Physical Review D |volume=95 |issue=4 |pages=043507 |doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043507 |doi-access=free |arxiv=1610.09243 |bibcode=2017PhRvD..95d3507F }}</ref> In the context of loop quantum gravity, Charles Wang et al. suggest that scale invariance may lead to the existence of a quantized time.<ref name=":0" />


== The thermal time hypothesis == ==Thermal time hypothesis ==
The ''thermal time hypothesis'' is a possible solution to the ] in classical and quantum theory as has been put forward by ] and ]. Physical time flow is modeled as a fundamental property of the theory, a macroscopic feature of ].<ref>{{cite journal | last=Rovelli | first=C | title=Statistical mechanics of gravity and the thermodynamical origin of time | journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity | publisher=IOP Publishing | volume=10 | date=1993 | issue=8 | doi=10.1088/0264-9381/10/8/015 | pages=1549–1566| bibcode=1993CQGra..10.1549R }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1=Connes | first1=A | last2=Rovelli | first2=C | title=Von Neumann algebra automorphisms and time-thermodynamics relation in generally covariant quantum theories | journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity | publisher=IOP Publishing | volume=11 | issue=12 | date=1994-12-01 | issn=0264-9381 | doi=10.1088/0264-9381/11/12/007 | pages=2899–2917|arxiv=gr-qc/9406019| bibcode=1994CQGra..11.2899C }}</ref>
{{main|Thermal time hypothesis|thermodynamics}}


== See also ==
] theories do not have a notion of a distinguished physical time with respect to which everything evolves. However, it is not needed for the full formulation and interpretation of the theory. The dynamical laws are determined by correlations which are sufficient to make predictions. But then a mechanism is needed which explains how the familiar notion of time eventually emerges from the timeless structure to become such an important ingredient of the macroscopic world we live in as well as of our conscious experience.


* ]
The ''thermal time hypothesis'' has been put forward as a possible solution to this problem by ] and ], both in classical and quantum theory. It postulates that physical time flow is not an a priori given fundamental property of the theory, but is a macroscopic feature of thermodynamical origin.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Connes|first1=A|last2=Rovelli|first2=C|title=Von Neumann algebra automorphisms and time-thermodynamics relation in generally covariant quantum theories|journal=Classical and Quantum Gravity|date=1 December 1994|volume=11|issue=12|pages=2899–2917|doi=10.1088/0264-9381/11/12/007|url=http://www.alainconnes.org/docs/carlotime.pdf|arxiv=gr-qc/9406019|bibcode=1994CQGra..11.2899C}}</ref>
* ]
== See also ==
*]


== References == == References ==

Latest revision as of 09:29, 27 November 2024

Conceptual conflict between general relativity and quantum mechanics

In theoretical physics, the problem of time is a conceptual conflict between quantum mechanics and general relativity. Quantum mechanics regards the flow of time as universal and absolute, whereas general relativity regards the flow of time as malleable and relative. This problem raises the question of what time really is in a physical sense and whether it is truly a real, distinct phenomenon. It also involves the related question of why time seems to flow in a single direction, despite the fact that no known physical laws at the microscopic level seem to require a single direction.

Time in quantum mechanics

In classical mechanics, a special status is assigned to time in the sense that it is treated as a classical background parameter, external to the system itself. This special role is seen in the standard Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics: all measurements of observables are made at certain instants of time and probabilities are only assigned to such measurements. Furthermore, the Hilbert space used in quantum theory relies on a complete set of observables which commute at a specific time.

Time in general relativity

In general relativity time is no longer a unique background parameter, but a general coordinate. The field equations of general relativity are not parameterized by time but formulated in terms of spacetime. Many of the issues related to the problem of time exist within general relativity. At the cosmic scale, general relativity shows a closed universe with no external time. These two very different roles of time are incompatible.

Impact on quantum gravity

Quantum gravity describes theories that attempt to reconcile or unify quantum mechanics and general relativity, the current theory of gravity. The problem of time is central to these theoretical attempts. It remains unclear how time is related to quantum probability, whether time is fundamental or a consequence of processes, and whether time is approximate, among other issues. Different theories try different answers to the questions but no clear solution has emerged.

The Frozen Formalism Problem

The most commonly discussed aspect of the problem of time is the Frozen Formalism Problem. The non-relativistic equation of quantum mechanics includes time evolution: i t ψ ( t ) = H ψ ( t ) , {\displaystyle i\hbar {\frac {\partial }{\partial t}}\psi (t)=H\psi (t),} where H {\displaystyle H} is an energy operator characterizing the system and the wave function ψ ( t ) {\displaystyle \psi (t)} over space evolves in time, t. In general relativity the energy operator becomes a constraint in the Wheeler–DeWitt equation: H ^ ( x ) | ψ = 0 , {\displaystyle {\hat {H}}(x)|\psi \rangle =0,} where the operator varies throughout space, but the wavefunction here, called the wavefunction of the universe, is constant. Consequently this cosmic universal wavefunction is frozen and does not evolve. Somehow, at a smaller scale, the laws of physics, including a concept of time, apply within the universe while the cosmic level is static.

Proposed solutions to the problem of time

Work started by Don Page and William Wootters suggests that the universe appears to evolve for observers on the inside because of energy entanglement between an evolving system and a clock system, both within the universe. In this way the overall system can remain timeless while parts experience time via entanglement. The issue remains an open question closely related to attempted theories of quantum gravity. In other words, time is an entanglement phenomenon, which places all equal clock readings (of correctly prepared clocks – or any objects usable as clocks) into the same history.

In 2013, at the Istituto Nazionale di Ricerca Metrologica (INRIM) in Turin, Italy, Ekaterina Moreva, together with Giorgio Brida, Marco Gramegna, Vittorio Giovannetti, Lorenzo Maccone, and Marco Genovese performed the first experimental test of Page and Wootters' ideas. They confirmed for photons that time is an emergent phenomenon for internal observers but absent for external observers of the universe just as the Wheeler–DeWitt equation predicts.

Consistent discretizations approach developed by Jorge Pullin and Rodolfo Gambini have no constraints. These are lattice approximation techniques for quantum gravity. In the canonical approach, if one discretizes the constraints and equations of motion, the resulting discrete equations are inconsistent: they cannot be solved simultaneously. To address this problem, one uses a technique based on discretizing the action of the theory and working with the discrete equations of motion. These are automatically guaranteed to be consistent. Most of the hard conceptual questions of quantum gravity are related to the presence of constraints in the theory. Consistent discretized theories are free of these conceptual problems and can be straightforwardly quantized, providing a solution to the problem of time. It is a bit more subtle than this. Although without constraints and having "general evolution", the latter is only in terms of a discrete parameter that isn't physically accessible. The way out is addressed in a way similar to the Page–Wooters approach. The idea is to pick one of the physical variables to be a clock and ask relational questions. These ideas, where the clock is also quantum mechanical, have actually led to a new interpretation of quantum mechanics — the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics. This new interpretation solves the problems of the use of environmental decoherence as a solution to the problem of measurement in quantum mechanics by invoking fundamental limitations, due to the quantum mechanical nature of clocks, in the process of measurement. These limitations are very natural in the context of generally covariant theories as quantum gravity where the clock must be taken as one of the degrees of freedom of the system itself. They have also put forward this fundamental decoherence as a way to resolve the black hole information paradox. In certain circumstances, a matter field is used to de-parametrize the theory and introduce a physical Hamiltonian. This generates physical time evolution, not a constraint.

Reduced phase-space quantization constraints are solved first and then quantized. This approach was considered for some time to be impossible, as it seems to require first finding the general solution to Einstein's equations. However, with the use of ideas involved in Dittrich's approximation scheme (built on ideas of Carlo Rovelli) a way to explicitly implement, at least in principle, a reduced phase-space quantization was made viable.

Avshalom Elitzur and Shahar Dolev argue that quantum-mechanical experiments such as the "quantum liar" provide evidence of inconsistent histories, and that spacetime itself may therefore be subject to change affecting entire histories. Elitzur and Dolev also believe that an objective passage of time and relativity can be reconciled and that it would resolve many of the issues with the block universe and the conflict between relativity and quantum mechanics.

One solution to the problem of time proposed by Lee Smolin is that there exists a "thick present" of events, in which two events in the present can be causally related to each other, but in contrast to the block-universe view of time in which all time exists eternally. Marina Cortês and Lee Smolin argue that certain classes of discrete dynamical systems demonstrate time asymmetry and irreversibility, which is consistent with an objective passage of time.

Weyl time in scale-invariant quantum gravity

Motivated by the Immirzi ambiguity in loop quantum gravity and the near-conformal invariance of the standard model of elementary particles, Charles Wang and co-workers have argued that the problem of time may be related to an underlying scale invariance of gravity–matter systems. Scale invariance has also been proposed to resolve the hierarchy problem of fundamental couplings. As a global continuous symmetry, scale invariance generates a conserved Weyl current according to Noether’s theorem. In scale-invariant cosmological models, this Weyl current naturally gives rise to a harmonic time. In the context of loop quantum gravity, Charles Wang et al. suggest that scale invariance may lead to the existence of a quantized time.

Thermal time hypothesis

The thermal time hypothesis is a possible solution to the problem of time in classical and quantum theory as has been put forward by Carlo Rovelli and Alain Connes. Physical time flow is modeled as a fundamental property of the theory, a macroscopic feature of thermodynamical origin.

See also

References

  1. Isham, C. J. (1993), Ibort, L. A.; Rodríguez, M. A. (eds.), "Canonical Quantum Gravity and the Problem of Time", Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories, NATO ASI Series, Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, pp. 157–287, arXiv:gr-qc/9210011, doi:10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6, ISBN 978-94-011-1980-1, S2CID 116947742, retrieved 2021-01-04
  2. Wolchover, Natalie (December 1, 2016). "Quantum Gravity's Time Problem". Quanta Magazine.
  3. Folger, Tim (June 12, 2007). "Newsflash: Time May Not Exist". Discover.
  4. ^ Anderson, E. (2012-12-15). "Problem of time in quantum gravity". Annalen der Physik. 524 (12): 757–786. arXiv:1009.2157. Bibcode:2012AnP...524..757A. doi:10.1002/andp.201200147. ISSN 0003-3804.
  5. Rovelli, Carlo (2008-05-23). "Quantum gravity". Scholarpedia. 3 (5): 7117. Bibcode:2008SchpJ...3.7117R. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.7117.
  6. Isham, C. J. (1993). Ibort, L. A.; Rodríguez, M. A. (eds.). Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. pp. 157–287. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6. ISBN 978-94-011-1980-1.
  7. Page, Don N.; Wootters, William K. (1983-06-15). "Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables". Physical Review D. 27 (12): 2885–2892. Bibcode:1983PhRvD..27.2885P. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885.
  8. Rovelli, Carlo (1990-10-15). "Quantum mechanics without time: A model". Physical Review D. 42 (8): 2638–2646. Bibcode:1990PhRvD..42.2638R. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.42.2638. PMID 10013133.
  9. Giovannetti, Vittorio; Lloyd, Seth; Maccone, Lorenzo (2015-08-26). "Quantum time". Physical Review D. 92 (4): 045033. arXiv:1504.04215. Bibcode:2015PhRvD..92d5033G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.92.045033. hdl:1721.1/98287. S2CID 85537706.
  10. ^ "Quantum Experiment Shows How Time 'Emerges' from Entanglement". The Physics arXiv Blog. Oct 23, 2013. Archived from the original on 2017-06-03.
  11. Altaie, M. Basil; Hodgson, Daniel; Beige, Almut (2022-06-03). "Time and Quantum Clocks: A Review of Recent Developments". Frontiers in Physics. 10. arXiv:2203.12564. Bibcode:2022FrP....10.7305A. doi:10.3389/fphy.2022.897305. ISSN 2296-424X.
  12. Isham, C. J. (1993). Ibort, L. A.; Rodríguez, M. A. (eds.). Integrable Systems, Quantum Groups, and Quantum Field Theories. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. pp. 157–287. doi:10.1007/978-94-011-1980-1_6. ISBN 978-94-011-1980-1.
  13. Moreva, Ekaterina; Brida, Giorgio; Gramegna, Marco; Giovannetti, Vittorio; Maccone, Lorenzo; Genovese, Marco (20 May 2014). "Time from quantum entanglement: An experimental illustration". Physical Review A. 89 (5): 052122. arXiv:1310.4691. Bibcode:2014PhRvA..89e2122M. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.89.052122. S2CID 118638346.
  14. Moreva, Ekaterina; Gramegna, Marco; Brida, Giorgio; Maccone, Lorenzo; Genovese, Marco (16 November 2017). "Quantum time: Experimental multitime correlations". Physical Review D. 96 (5): 102005. arXiv:1710.00707. Bibcode:2017PhRvD..96j2005M. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.96.102005. S2CID 119431509.
  15. Gambini, Rodolfo; Pullin, Jorge (1 June 2009). "The Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics: frequently asked questions". Journal of Physics: Conference Series. 174 (1): 012003. arXiv:0905.4402. Bibcode:2009JPhCS.174a2003G. doi:10.1088/1742-6596/174/1/012003. S2CID 250680865.
  16. Gambini, Rodolfo; Garc?a-Pintos, Luis Pedro; Pullin, Jorge (November 2011). "An axiomatic formulation of the Montevideo interpretation of quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 42 (4): 256–263. arXiv:1002.4209. Bibcode:2011SHPMP..42..256G. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.10.002. S2CID 993508.
  17. Gambini, Rodolfo; Porto, Rafael A.; Pullin, Jorge (December 2004). "No Black Hole Information Puzzle In A Relational Universe". International Journal of Modern Physics D. 13 (10): 2315–2320. arXiv:hep-th/0405183. Bibcode:2004IJMPD..13.2315G. doi:10.1142/S0218271804006383. S2CID 119424485.
  18. Gambini, Rodolfo; Porto, Rafael A.; Pullin, Jorge (6 December 2004). "Realistic Clocks, Universal Decoherence, and the Black Hole Information Paradox". Physical Review Letters. 93 (24): 240401. arXiv:hep-th/0406260. Bibcode:2004PhRvL..93x0401G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.93.240401. PMID 15697783. S2CID 25174047.
  19. Thiemann, T. (21 February 2006). "Reduced phase space quantization and Dirac observables". Classical and Quantum Gravity. 23 (4): 1163–1180. arXiv:gr-qc/0411031. Bibcode:2006CQGra..23.1163T. doi:10.1088/0264-9381/23/4/006. S2CID 17230218.
  20. Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2005). "Quantum phenomena within a new theory of time". In Quo vadis quantum mechanics? (pp. 325–349). Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg.
  21. Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2003). "Is there more to T?". In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception (pp. 297–306). Springer, Dordrecht.
  22. Elitzur, A. C.; Dolev, S. (2005). "Becoming as a bridge between quantum mechanics and relativity". In Endophysics, Time, Quantum And The Subjective: (With CD-ROM) (pp. 589–606).
  23. Smolin, L. (2015). "Temporal naturalism". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 52: 86–102. arXiv:1805.12468. Bibcode:2015SHPMP..52...86S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.03.005. S2CID 8344858.
  24. Cortês, M.; Smolin, L. (2018). "Reversing the irreversible: from limit cycles to emergent time symmetry". Physical Review D. 97 (2): 026004. arXiv:1703.09696. Bibcode:2018PhRvD..97b6004C. doi:10.1103/physrevd.97.026004. S2CID 119067096.
  25. Meissner, Krzysztof A.; Nicolai, Hermann (2007-05-10). "Conformal symmetry and the Standard Model". Physics Letters B. 648 (4): 312–317. arXiv:hep-th/0612165. Bibcode:2007PhLB..648..312M. doi:10.1016/j.physletb.2007.03.023. ISSN 0370-2693.
  26. ^ Wang, Charles H.-T.; Stankiewicz, Marcin (2020-01-10). "Quantization of time and the big bang via scale-invariant loop gravity". Physics Letters B. 800: 135106. arXiv:1910.03300. Bibcode:2020PhLB..80035106W. doi:10.1016/j.physletb.2019.135106. ISSN 0370-2693.
  27. ^ Wang, Charles H.-T.; Rodrigues, Daniel P. F. (2018-12-28). "Closing the gaps in quantum space and time: Conformally augmented gauge structure of gravitation". Physical Review D. 98 (12): 124041. arXiv:1810.01232. Bibcode:2018PhRvD..98l4041W. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.98.124041. hdl:2164/11713. S2CID 118961037.
  28. Wang, Charles H.-T. (2005-10-06). "Unambiguous spin-gauge formulation of canonical general relativity with conformorphism invariance". Physical Review D. 72 (8): 087501. arXiv:gr-qc/0507044. Bibcode:2005PhRvD..72h7501W. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.72.087501. S2CID 34995566.
  29. Shaposhnikov, Mikhail; Shkerin, Andrey (2018-10-03). "Gravity, scale invariance and the hierarchy problem". Journal of High Energy Physics. 2018 (10): 24. arXiv:1804.06376. Bibcode:2018JHEP...10..024S. doi:10.1007/JHEP10(2018)024. ISSN 1029-8479.
  30. Ferreira, Pedro G.; Hill, Christopher T.; Ross, Graham G. (2017-02-08). "Weyl current, scale-invariant inflation, and Planck scale generation". Physical Review D. 95 (4): 043507. arXiv:1610.09243. Bibcode:2017PhRvD..95d3507F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043507.
  31. Rovelli, C (1993). "Statistical mechanics of gravity and the thermodynamical origin of time". Classical and Quantum Gravity. 10 (8). IOP Publishing: 1549–1566. Bibcode:1993CQGra..10.1549R. doi:10.1088/0264-9381/10/8/015.
  32. Connes, A; Rovelli, C (1994-12-01). "Von Neumann algebra automorphisms and time-thermodynamics relation in generally covariant quantum theories". Classical and Quantum Gravity. 11 (12). IOP Publishing: 2899–2917. arXiv:gr-qc/9406019. Bibcode:1994CQGra..11.2899C. doi:10.1088/0264-9381/11/12/007. ISSN 0264-9381.

Further reading

Categories: