Revision as of 06:43, 12 April 2022 edit67.42.69.240 (talk) →Prescientific protoscience: more ;clean-cut'Tags: Reverted Visual edit← Previous edit | Latest revision as of 21:04, 22 December 2024 edit undoKMaster888 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users12,260 edits fix footnote | ||
(42 intermediate revisions by 23 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description| |
{{Short description|Research field with some scientific qualities}} | ||
In the ], '''protoscience''' is a research field that has the characteristics of an undeveloped ] that may ultimately develop into an established science. Philosophers use protoscience to understand the history of science and distinguish protoscience from science and ].{{sfn|Tuomela|1987}} The word “protoscience” is a ] of the roots '']'' + '']'', meaning a first or primeval rational knowledge. | |||
__NOTOC__ | |||
==History== | |||
In the ], there are several definitions of '''protoscience'''. Its simplest meaning (most closely reflecting its roots of '']'' + '']'') involves the earliest eras of the ], when the ] was still nascent. The term can also be applied to modern emerging fields of study.<blockquote> | |||
Protoscience as a research field with the characteristics of an undeveloped science appeared in the early 20th century.{{sfn|Jones|1910|p=94}}{{sfn|Hobhouse|1915|p=41}} In 1910, Jones described economics: | |||
: ''"In any case, there are many fields - I shall call them'' '''proto-sciences''' ''- in which practice <u>does generate testable conclusions</u> but which nevertheless resemble philosophy and the arts rather than the establish sciences in their developmental patterns. I think, for example, of fields like chemistry and electricity before the mid-eighteenth century, of the study of heredity and phylogeny before the mid-nineteenth, or of many of the social sciences today. In these fields, too, though they staisfy Sir Kral's demarcation criterion, incessant critism and continual striving for a fresh start are primary forces, and need to be. No more than in philosophy and the arts, <u>however, do they result in clear-cut progress.</u>'' | |||
: I confess to a personal predilection for some term such as proto-science, pre-science, or nas-science, to give expression to what I conceive to be the true state of affairs, which I take to be this, that economics and kindred subjects are not sciences, but are on the way to become sciences.{{sfn|Jones|1910}} | |||
: | |||
: ''"I conclude, in short, that the '''proto-sciences''', like the arts and philosophy, <u>lack some element which, in the mature sciences, permits the more obvious forms of progress.</u> It is not, however, anything that a methodological prescription can provide. "'' <ref>{{Citation |last=Kuhn |first=T. S. |title=Reflections on my Critics |date=1970-09-02 |url=http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/cbo9781139171434.011 |work=Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge |pages=231–278 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |access-date=2022-04-12}}</ref> | |||
] later provided a more precise description, protoscience as a field that generates testable conclusions, faces “incessant criticism and continually strive for a fresh start,” but currently, like ] and ], appears to have failed to progress in a way similar to the progress seen in the established sciences.{{sfn|Kuhn|1970|p=244}} He applies protoscience to the fields of ], ] and the ]s in the past that ultimately became established sciences.{{sfn|Kuhn|1970|p=245}} Philosophers later developed more precise criteria to identify protoscience using the <em>cognitive field</em> concept.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|pp=202–203}}{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|pp=89–90}} | |||
</blockquote> | |||
==Thought collective== | |||
==Prescientific protoscience== | |||
{{main|Thought collective}} | |||
The term ''prescientific'' means at root "relating to an era before science existed". For example, ] existed for thousands of years before medical science did, and thus many aspects of it can be described as prescientific. In a related sense, protoscientific topics (such as the alchemy of Newton's day) can be called prescientific, in which case the ''proto-'' and ''pre-'' labels can function more or less ]ously (the latter focusing more sharply on the idea that nothing but science is science).{{cn|date=February 2022|reason=it is not obvious that proto- and pre- are to be treated as synonyms}} | |||
:''This material is from ]'' | |||
] later discovered that Fleck 1935 had voiced concepts that predated Kuhn's own work. That is, | |||
Fleck wrote that the development of ] in scientific research was an unattainable ideal as different researchers were locked into thought collectives (or thought-styles). This means "that a pure and direct observation cannot exist: in the act of perceiving objects the observer, i.e. the epistemological subject, is always influenced by the epoch and the environment to which he belongs, that is by what Fleck calls the thought style".{{sfn|Siwecka|2011}} Thought style throughout Fleck's work is closely associated with representational style. A "fact" was a relative value, expressed in the language or symbolism of the thought collective in which it belonged, and subject to the social and temporal structure of this collective. He argued, however, that within the active cultural style of a thought collective, knowledge claims or facts were constrained by passive elements arising from the observations and experience of the natural world. This passive resistance of natural experience represented within the stylized means of the thought collective could be verified by anyone adhering to the culture of the thought collective, and thus facts could be agreed upon within any particular thought style.{{sfn|Fleck|1979|pp=101-102}} Thus while a fact may be verifiable within its own collective, it may be unverifiable in others. He felt that the development of scientific facts and concepts was not unidirectional and does not consist of just accumulating new pieces of information, but at times required changing older concepts, methods of observations, and forms of representation. This changing of prior knowledge is difficult because a collective attains over time a specific way of investigating, bringing with it a blindness to alternative ways of observing and conceptualization. Change was especially possible when members of two thought collectives met and cooperated in observing, formulating hypothesis and ideas. He strongly advocated comparative epistemology. He also notes some features of the culture of modern natural sciences that recognize provisionality and evolution of knowledge along the value of pursuit of passive resistances.{{sfn|Fleck|1979|pp=118-120, 142-145}} This approach anticipated later developments in ], and especially the development of critical ]. | |||
==Conceptual framework== | |||
Compared to ], which is considered highly speculative or even strongly refuted,<ref>{{cite journal |author=Dutch, Steven I |title=Notes on the nature of fringe science |journal=]|volume=30 |issue=1 |pages=6–13 |date=January 1982 |doi=10.5408/0022-1368-30.1.6 |bibcode=1982JGeoE..30....6D}}</ref> some protosciences go on to become accepted parts of ].{{cn|date=February 2022|reason=previously cited ref was unreliable}} The historical basis of much of modern chemistry is based on the discoveries of ], a proto-chemistry using some of the modern techniques and processes of modern proven chemistry.{{cn|date=February 2022|reason=protoscience not mentioned in previously cited ref}} | |||
===Cognitive field=== | |||
Philosophers describe protoscience using the <em>cognitive field</em> concept.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|pp=175, 202–03}}{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=88}} In every society, there are fields of ] (cognitive fields).{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=175}} The cognitive field consists of a community of individuals within a society with a domain of inquiry, a philosophical worldview, logical/mathematical tools, specific background knowledge from neighboring fields, a set of problems investigated, accumulated knowledge from the community, aims and methods.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|pp=202–03}} Cognitive fields are either <em>belief fields</em> or <em>research fields</em>.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|pp=202–03}} A cognitive research field invariably changes over time due to research; research fields include natural sciences, applied sciences, mathematics, technology, medicine, jurisprudence, social sciences and the humanities.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=91}}{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=175}} A belief field (faith field) is "a cognitive field which either does not change at all or changes due to factors other than research (such as economic interest, political or religious pressure, or brute violence)."{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=91}}{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=175}} Belief fields include political ideology, religion, pseudodoctrines and pseudoscience.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=92}} | |||
===Science field=== | |||
==Modern protoscience== | |||
A <em>science field</em> is a research field that satisfies 12 conditions: 1) all components of the science field invariably change over time from research in the field, especially logical/mathematical tools and specific background/presuppositions from other fields; 2) the research community has special training, “hold strong information links”, initiates or continues the “tradition of inquiry”; 3) researchers have autonomy to pursue research and receive support from the host society; 4) the researchers worldview is the real world as contains “lawfully changing concrete” objects, an adequate view of the scientific method, a vision of organized science achieving truthfull descriptions and explanations, ethical principles for conducting research, and the free search for truthful, deep and systematic understanding; 5) up-to-date logical/mathematical tools precisely determine and process information; | |||
Another meaning extends this idea into the present, with protoscience being an emerging field of study which is still not completely scientific, but later becomes a proper science.<ref name=Bunge>{{cite magazine | last=Bunge | first=Mario | title=What is pseudoscience?| year=1984 | magazine=The Skeptical Inquirer |volume=9 | pages=36–46}} (. Bunge defines protosciences as "emerging sciences" which "advance and end up by becoming sciences". (p.44)</ref> ] Jaap Brakel defines it as "the study of '']'' criteria for the use of experimental technology in science."<ref>Brakel, Jaap, "", Philosophy of chemistry: between the manifest and the scientific image, Leuven Univ Pr, December 2000</ref> | |||
6) the domain of research are real objects/entities; 7) specific background knowledge is up-to-date, confirmed data, hypotheses and theories from relevant neighboring fields; 8) the set of problems investigated are from the domain of inquiry or within the research field; 9) the accumulated knowledge includes worldview-compatible, up-to-date testworthy/testable theories, hypotheses and data, and special knowledge previously accumlated in the research field; 10) the aims are find and apply laws and theories in the domain of inquiry, systemize acquired knonwledge, generalized information into theories, and improve research methods; 11) appropriate scientific methods are “subject to test, correction and justification”; 12) the research field is connected with a wider research field with similar capable researchers capable of “scientific inference, action and discussion”, similar hosting society, a domain of inquiry containing the domain of inquiry of the narrower field, and shared worldview, logical/mathematical tools, background knowledge, accumulated knowledge, aims and methods.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|pp=89–90}} | |||
===Protoscience=== | |||
An example of it is the ], which started as a protoscience (a ] work which had not been tested), but later was ] verified and became fully scientific.{{cn|date=February 2022|reason=Who says Relativity started as a protoscience?}} Protoscience in this sense is distinguished from ] by a genuine willingness to be changed through new ], as opposed to having a theory that can be used to ] a predetermined belief (i.e., ]){{cn|date=February 2022|reason=Why waste time debunking pseudoscience here? Who identifies the distinction from protoscience?}} | |||
Philosophers define protoscience as an undeveloped science field, undeveloped meaning an incomplete or approximate science field. ] defined a protoscience as a research field that approximately satisfies a similar set of the 12 science conditions.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|pp=202–03}} A protoscience that is evolving to ultimately satisfy all 12 conditions is an <em>emerging</em> or <em>developing</em> science.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=203}} Bunge states, "The difference between protoscience and pseudoscience parallels that between error and deception."{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=203}} A protoscience may not survive or evolve to a science or ].{{sfn|Bunge|2010|p=253}} Kuhn was skeptical about any remedy that would reliably transform a protoscience to a science stating, “I claim no therapy to assist the transformation of a proto-science to a science, nor do I suppose anything of this sort is to be had.”{{sfn|Kuhn|1970|p=245}} | |||
] defined a protoscience as a research field that satisfies 9 of the 12 science conditions; a protoscience fails to satisfy the up-to-date conditions for logic/mathematical tools, specific background knowledge from neighboring fields, and accumulated knowledge (5, 7, 9), and there is reason to believe the protoscience will ultimately satisfy all 12 conditions.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=92}} Protosciences and belief fields are both non-science fields, but only a protoscience can become a science field.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=92}} Tuomela emphasizes that the cognitive field concept refers to "ideal types" and there may be some persons within a science field with non-scientific "attitudes, thinking and actions"; therefore, it may be better to apply scientific and non-scientific to "attitudes, thinking and actions" rather than directly to cognitive fields.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=92}} | |||
] said that protosciences "generate ] conclusions but ... nevertheless resemble ] and ] rather than the established sciences in their developmental patterns. I think, for example, of fields like ] and ] before the mid-18th century, of the study of ] and ] before the mid-nineteenth, or of many of the ] today." While noting that they meet the demarcation criteria of ] from ], he questions whether the discussion in protoscience fields "result in clear-cut progress". Kuhn concluded that protosciences, "like the arts and philosophy, lack some element which, in the mature sciences, permits the more obvious forms of progress. It is not, however, anything that a methodological prescription can provide. ... I claim no therapy to assist the transformation of a proto-science to a science, nor do I suppose anything of this sort is to be had".<ref>{{cite book |last=Kuhn |first=Thomas |editor1=Imre Lakatos |editor2=Alan Musgrave |chapter=Reflections on my critics |title=Criticism and the growth of knowledge: Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science |year=1970 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge |isbn=0521096235 |edition=Reprint |pages= |chapter-url-access=registration |chapter-url=https://archive.org/details/criticismgrowth00laka/page/244 }}</ref> | |||
==Developmental stages of science== | |||
Bunge stated that protoscience may occur as the second stage of a five-stage process in the development of science.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} Each stage has a theoretical and empirical aspect:{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
# <em>Prescience</em> has unchecked speculation theory and unchecked data.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
# <em>Protoscience</em> has hypotheses without theory accompanied by observation and occasional measurement, but no experiment.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
# <em>Deuteroscience</em> has hypotheses formulated mathematically without theory accompanied by systematic measurement, and experiment on perceptible traits of perceptible objects.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
# <em>Tritoscience</em> has mathematical models accompanied by systematic measurements and experiments on perceptible and imperceptible traits of perceptible and imperceptible objects.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
# <em>Tetartoscience</em> has mathematical models and comprehensive theories accompanied by precise systematic measurements and experiments on perceptible and imperceptible traits of perceptible and imperceptible objects.{{sfn|Bunge|1983|p=160}} | |||
==Origin of protoscience== | |||
Protoscience may arise from the philosophical inquiry that anticipates science.{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} Philosophers anticipated the development of ], ], ] and ].{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} The Greek philosopher ] (610–546 BC) viewed the earth as a non-moving free-floating cylinder in space.{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} The atomist doctrine of ] (460–370 BC) to ] (341–270 BC) was that objects were composed of non-visible small particles.{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} Anaximander had anticipated that humans may have developed from more primitive organisms.{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} ] study of language preceded the linguistic studies of ] and ].{{sfn|Costa|2014|p=12}} ] describes how scientific theory arises from myths such as atomism and the corpuscular theory of light.{{sfn|Popper|2002|p=347}} Popper states that the Copernican system was "inspired by a Neo-Platonic worship of the light of the Sun who had to occupy the center because of his nobility", leading to "testable components" that ultimately became "fruitful and important."{{sfn|Popper|2002|p=347}} | |||
Some scholars use the term <em>"primitive protoscience"</em> to describe ancient myths that help explain natural phenomena at a time prior to the development of the scientific method.{{sfn|Johnson|2021|p=42}} | |||
==Protoscience examples== | |||
===Physical science=== | |||
* Ancient astronomical protoscience was recorded as astronomical images and records inscribed on stones, bones and cave walls.{{sfn|Owens|2014}} | |||
* Luigi Ferdinando Marsili (1658–1730) contributed to protoscience ], describing the ocean currents of the ] and ], and ] contributed by identifying the currents of the ].{{sfn|Owens|2014}} | |||
* Philosophers consider ] before ] and ], ] before ], medicine before ] and ], ] before the mid-eighteenth century, and the study of ] and ] before the mid-nineteenth century as protosciences that eventually became established science.{{sfn|Bunge|2010|p=253}}{{sfn|Kuhn|1970|p=244}} | |||
* Prior to 1905, leading scientists, ] and ], viewed atomic and molecular-kinetic theory as a protoscience, a theory indirectly supported by ] and ]; however, ] theory of ], and ] experimental verification led to widespread acceptance of atomic and molecular-kinetic theory as established science.{{sfn|Bunge|2010|p=253}}{{sfn|Newburgh|Peidle|Rueckner|2006}} | |||
* The early stage of ], beginning with ] theory of ], was a protoscience until experimental research confirmed the theory many years later.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=100}} The initial widespread rejection of Wegener's theory is an example of the importance of not dismissing a protoscience.{{sfn|Tuomela|1987|p=100}}{{sfn|Oreskes|Le Grand|2001|p=7}} | |||
===Psychology=== | |||
Critics state that ] is a protoscience because some practices occur that prevent falsification of research hypotheses.{{sfn|Heene|Ferguson|2017|p=37}} <em>]</em> and <em>coaching psychology</em> are protosciences.{{sfn|Sehon|1997}}{{sfn|Grant|Cavanagh|2007}} | |||
===Medicine=== | |||
The use of scientifically invalid ] to identify adverse outcomes is a protoscience practice in medicine.{{sfn|Grimes|Schulz|Raymond|2010}} The process for reporting adverse medical events is a protoscience because it relies on uncorroborated data and unsystematic methods.{{sfn|Kaplan|Barach|2002}} | |||
===Technology=== | |||
Hatleback describes ] as a protoscience that lacks transparency in experimentation, scientific laws, and sound experimental design in some cases; however cybersecurity has the potential to become a science.{{sfn|Hatleback|2018}} | |||
==See also== | ==See also== | ||
Line 29: | Line 66: | ||
*] | *] | ||
*] | *] | ||
==Notes== | |||
{{notelist}} | |||
{{reflist}} | |||
==References== | ==References== | ||
{{ |
{{Refbegin|2}} | ||
*{{cite book |last1=Bullivant |first1=Stephen |last2=Ruse |first2=Michael |title=The Cambridge history of atheism |date=2021 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge |isbn=978-1-108-68899-4}} | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Bunge |first1=Mario |title=Epistemology & Methodology II: Understanding the World |series=Treatise on Basic Philosophy |volume=6 |year=1983 |publisher=Reidel |location=Dordrecht |isbn=90-277-1634-X |oclc=9759870 |url=https://archive.org/details/understandingwor0000bung |url-access=registration |doi=10.1007/978-94-015-6921-7}} | |||
==Further reading== | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Bunge |first1=Mario |title=Matter and Mind: a philosophical inquiry |year=2010 |series=Boston studies in the philosophy of science |volume=287 |publisher=Springer Verlag |location=Dordrecht, the Netherlands |isbn=9789048192243 |doi=10.1007/978-90-481-9225-0}} | |||
{{Wiktionary|protoscience}} | |||
*{{cite magazine |last=Bunge | first=Mario | title=What is pseudoscience?| year=1984 | magazine=The Skeptical Inquirer |volume=9 | pages=36–46 |url=https://cdn.centerforinquiry.org/wp-content/uploads/sites/29/1984/10/22165343/p38.pdf }} | |||
*J.A. Campbell, ''On artificial intelligence''. Artificial Intelligence Review, 1986. | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Costa |first1=Claudio F. |title=Lines of thought : rethinking philosophical assumptions |year=2014 |publisher=Cambridge Scholars Publishing |location=Newcastle upon Tyne |isbn=978-1-4438-5349-1}} | |||
*D. Hartmann, ''Protoscience and Reconstruction''. Journal of General Philosophy of Science, 1996. | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Grant |first1=Anthony M. |last2=Cavanagh |first2=Michael J. |title=Evidence-based coaching: Flourishing or languishing? |journal=Australian Psychologist |year=2007 |volume=42 |issue=4 |pages=239–254 |doi=10.1080/00050060701648175}} | |||
*H. Holcomb, ''Moving Beyond Just-So Stories: Evolutionary Psychology as Protoscience''. Skeptic Magazine, 1996. | |||
*{{cite book | |||
*G. Kennedy, ''Psychoanalysis: Protoscience and Metapsychology''. 1959. | |||
|last=Fleck | |||
*A.C. Maffei, ''Psychoanalysis: Protoscience or Science?'' 1969. | |||
|first=Ludwik | |||
*N. Psarros, ''The Constructive Approach to the Philosophy of Chemistry''. Epistemologia, 1995. | |||
|author-link=Ludwik Fleck | |||
*R. Tuomela, ''Science, Protoscience and Pseudoscience''. In Joseph C. Pitt, Marcello Pera (eds.), ''Rational Changes in Science: Essays on Scientific Reasoning'', Dordrecht, Reidel, 1987. | |||
|date=1935 | |||
|title=Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache - Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv | |||
|publisher=Schwabe und Co., Verlagsbuchhandlung | |||
|location=Basel | |||
|language=de | |||
|oclc=257469753 | |||
}} | |||
* {{Citation|first=Ludwik |last=Fleck|author-link=Ludwik Fleck|year=1979|title=]|publisher=Univ. of Chicago|isbn=978-0-226-25325-1}}. (written in German, 1935, ''Entstehung und Entwickelung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollectiv'') {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230406020601/https://books.google.com/books?id=0KAGUpaUaGYC&q=Ludwik+Fleck |date=2023-04-06 }} Edited by Thaddeus J. Trenn and Robert K. Merton. Foreword by Robert K. Merton | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Grimes |first1=David A. |last2=Schulz |first2=Kenneth F. |last3=Raymond |first3=Elizabeth G. |title=Surrogate end points in women's health research: science, protoscience, and pseudoscience |journal=Fertility and Sterility |year=2010 |volume=93 |issue=6 |pages=1731–1734 |doi=10.1016/j.fertnstert.2009.12.054|pmid=20153470 |doi-access=free }} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Hatleback |first1=Eric N |title=The protoscience of cybersecurity |journal=The Journal of Defense Modeling and Simulation: Applications, Methodology, Technology |year=2018 |volume=15 |issue=1 |pages=5–12 |doi=10.1177/1548512917737635|s2cid=64688425 |doi-access=free }} | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Hobhouse |first1=Leonard Trelawny |title=Morals in Evolution: A Study in Comparative Ethics |date=1915 |publisher=Chapman & Hall |location=New York |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=s31YAAAAMAAJ&dq=proto-science+morals+in+evolution&pg=PA41 |language=en}} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Johnson |first1=Carl Garth |title=The Nlhaykapmx Oral Tradition of the Three Bears: Interpretations Old And New |journal=Canadian Journal of Native Education |year=2021 |volume=25 |issue=1 |pages=Vol. 25 No. 1 (2001) |doi=10.14288/cjne.v25i1.195901}} | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Jones |first1=Robert |title=The Clare Market Review. The students magazine of the London school of economics and political science. |date=1910 |chapter=Dualism in economics |publisher=Students union |location=London |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=exRYAAAAYAAJ&dq=%22proto-science%22&pg=PA94}} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Kaplan |first1=H. |last2=Barach |first2=P. |title=Incident reporting: science or protoscience? Ten years later |journal=BMJ Quality & Safety |year=2002 |volume=11 |issue=2 |pages=144–145 |doi=10.1136/qhc.11.2.144|pmid=12448806 |s2cid=22816124 |doi-access=free |pmc=1743593 }} | |||
*{{cite book |editor-last1=Lakatos |editor-first1=Imre |editor-last2=Musgrave |editor-first2=Alan |chapter=Reflections on my critics |last1=Kuhn |first1=Thomas Samuel |title=Criticism and the growth of knowledge; |year=1970 |publisher=University Press |location=Cambridge |isbn=0521096235}} | |||
*{{cite book |editor-last1=Lilienfeld |editor-first1=Scott O. |editor-last2=Waldman |editor-first2=Irwin D. |last1=Heene |first1=Moritz |last2=Ferguson |first2=Christopher J. |title=Psychological science under scrutiny : recent challenges and proposed solutions |chapter=Psychological Science’s Aversion to the Null, and Why Many of the Things You Think Are True, Aren’t|year=2017 |publisher=Wiley Blackwell |location=Chichester, West Sussex, UK |pages=34–52 |isbn=978-1118661079 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=VMbXDQAAQBAJ&dq=Psychological+Science+Under+Scrutiny:+Recent+Challenges+and+Proposed+Solutions&pg=PR3}} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Newburgh |first1=Ronald |last2=Peidle |first2=Joseph |last3=Rueckner |first3=Wolfgang |title=Einstein, Perrin, and the reality of atoms: 1905 revisited |journal=American Journal of Physics |year=2006 |volume=74 |issue=6 |pages=478–481 |doi=10.1119/1.2188962|bibcode=2006AmJPh..74..478N }} | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Oreskes |first1=Naomi |last2=Le Grand |first2=Homer |title=Plate tectonics : an insider's history of the modern theory of the Earth |year=2001 |publisher=Westview Press |location=Boulder, Colo. |isbn=0-8133-3981-2}} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Owens |first1=Nicholas J. P. |title=Sustained UK marine observations. Where have we been? Where are we now? Where are we going? |journal=Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences |year=2014 |volume=372 |issue=2025 |pages=20130332 |doi=10.1098/rsta.2013.0332|pmid=25157193 |s2cid=34909909 |doi-access=free |pmc=4150290 |bibcode=2014RSPTA.37230332O }} | |||
*{{cite book |editor-last1=Pitt |editor-first1=Joseph C. |editor-last2=Pera |editor-first2=Marcello |title=Rational Changes in Science : Essays on Scientific Reasoning |chapter=Science, Protoscience, and Pseudoscience |last1=Tuomela |first1=Raimo |series=Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science |pages=83–102 |year=1987 |volume=98 |publisher=Springer Netherlands |location=Dordrecht |doi=10.1007/978-94-009-3779-6 |isbn=978-9400937802 |url=https://link.springer.com/book/10.1007/978-94-009-3779-6}} | |||
*{{cite book |last1=Popper |first1=Karl R. |title=Conjectures and refutations : the growth of scientific knowledge |year=2002 |publisher=Routledge |location=London |isbn=0-415-28593-3}} | |||
*{{cite journal |last1=Sehon |first1=Scott R. |title=Natural-Kind Terms and the Status of Folk Psychology |journal=American Philosophical Quarterly |year=1997 |volume=34 |issue=3 |pages=333–344 |jstor=20009903 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009903 |issn=0003-0481}} | |||
{{Refend}} | |||
==External links== | ==External links== | ||
* |
*{{cite web |title=Questions to help distinguish a pseudoscience from a protoscience |url=http://www.phy.syr.edu/courses/modules/PSEUDO/moller.html |date=7 January 2012|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120107043502/http://www.phy.syr.edu/courses/modules/PSEUDO/moller.html |archive-date=2012-01-07 }} | ||
{{Wiktionary|protoscience}} | |||
{{Philosophy of science}} | |||
] | ] | ||
] | ] |
Latest revision as of 21:04, 22 December 2024
Research field with some scientific qualitiesIn the philosophy of science, protoscience is a research field that has the characteristics of an undeveloped science that may ultimately develop into an established science. Philosophers use protoscience to understand the history of science and distinguish protoscience from science and pseudoscience. The word “protoscience” is a hybrid Greek-Latin compound of the roots proto- + scientia, meaning a first or primeval rational knowledge.
History
Protoscience as a research field with the characteristics of an undeveloped science appeared in the early 20th century. In 1910, Jones described economics:
- I confess to a personal predilection for some term such as proto-science, pre-science, or nas-science, to give expression to what I conceive to be the true state of affairs, which I take to be this, that economics and kindred subjects are not sciences, but are on the way to become sciences.
Thomas Kuhn later provided a more precise description, protoscience as a field that generates testable conclusions, faces “incessant criticism and continually strive for a fresh start,” but currently, like art and philosophy, appears to have failed to progress in a way similar to the progress seen in the established sciences. He applies protoscience to the fields of natural philosophy, medicine and the crafts in the past that ultimately became established sciences. Philosophers later developed more precise criteria to identify protoscience using the cognitive field concept.
Thought collective
Main article: Thought collective- This material is from Ludwik Fleck § Thought collective
Thomas Kuhn later discovered that Fleck 1935 had voiced concepts that predated Kuhn's own work. That is, Fleck wrote that the development of truth in scientific research was an unattainable ideal as different researchers were locked into thought collectives (or thought-styles). This means "that a pure and direct observation cannot exist: in the act of perceiving objects the observer, i.e. the epistemological subject, is always influenced by the epoch and the environment to which he belongs, that is by what Fleck calls the thought style". Thought style throughout Fleck's work is closely associated with representational style. A "fact" was a relative value, expressed in the language or symbolism of the thought collective in which it belonged, and subject to the social and temporal structure of this collective. He argued, however, that within the active cultural style of a thought collective, knowledge claims or facts were constrained by passive elements arising from the observations and experience of the natural world. This passive resistance of natural experience represented within the stylized means of the thought collective could be verified by anyone adhering to the culture of the thought collective, and thus facts could be agreed upon within any particular thought style. Thus while a fact may be verifiable within its own collective, it may be unverifiable in others. He felt that the development of scientific facts and concepts was not unidirectional and does not consist of just accumulating new pieces of information, but at times required changing older concepts, methods of observations, and forms of representation. This changing of prior knowledge is difficult because a collective attains over time a specific way of investigating, bringing with it a blindness to alternative ways of observing and conceptualization. Change was especially possible when members of two thought collectives met and cooperated in observing, formulating hypothesis and ideas. He strongly advocated comparative epistemology. He also notes some features of the culture of modern natural sciences that recognize provisionality and evolution of knowledge along the value of pursuit of passive resistances. This approach anticipated later developments in social constructionism, and especially the development of critical science and technology studies.
Conceptual framework
Cognitive field
Philosophers describe protoscience using the cognitive field concept. In every society, there are fields of knowledge (cognitive fields). The cognitive field consists of a community of individuals within a society with a domain of inquiry, a philosophical worldview, logical/mathematical tools, specific background knowledge from neighboring fields, a set of problems investigated, accumulated knowledge from the community, aims and methods. Cognitive fields are either belief fields or research fields. A cognitive research field invariably changes over time due to research; research fields include natural sciences, applied sciences, mathematics, technology, medicine, jurisprudence, social sciences and the humanities. A belief field (faith field) is "a cognitive field which either does not change at all or changes due to factors other than research (such as economic interest, political or religious pressure, or brute violence)." Belief fields include political ideology, religion, pseudodoctrines and pseudoscience.
Science field
A science field is a research field that satisfies 12 conditions: 1) all components of the science field invariably change over time from research in the field, especially logical/mathematical tools and specific background/presuppositions from other fields; 2) the research community has special training, “hold strong information links”, initiates or continues the “tradition of inquiry”; 3) researchers have autonomy to pursue research and receive support from the host society; 4) the researchers worldview is the real world as contains “lawfully changing concrete” objects, an adequate view of the scientific method, a vision of organized science achieving truthfull descriptions and explanations, ethical principles for conducting research, and the free search for truthful, deep and systematic understanding; 5) up-to-date logical/mathematical tools precisely determine and process information; 6) the domain of research are real objects/entities; 7) specific background knowledge is up-to-date, confirmed data, hypotheses and theories from relevant neighboring fields; 8) the set of problems investigated are from the domain of inquiry or within the research field; 9) the accumulated knowledge includes worldview-compatible, up-to-date testworthy/testable theories, hypotheses and data, and special knowledge previously accumlated in the research field; 10) the aims are find and apply laws and theories in the domain of inquiry, systemize acquired knonwledge, generalized information into theories, and improve research methods; 11) appropriate scientific methods are “subject to test, correction and justification”; 12) the research field is connected with a wider research field with similar capable researchers capable of “scientific inference, action and discussion”, similar hosting society, a domain of inquiry containing the domain of inquiry of the narrower field, and shared worldview, logical/mathematical tools, background knowledge, accumulated knowledge, aims and methods.
Protoscience
Philosophers define protoscience as an undeveloped science field, undeveloped meaning an incomplete or approximate science field. Mario Bunge defined a protoscience as a research field that approximately satisfies a similar set of the 12 science conditions. A protoscience that is evolving to ultimately satisfy all 12 conditions is an emerging or developing science. Bunge states, "The difference between protoscience and pseudoscience parallels that between error and deception." A protoscience may not survive or evolve to a science or pseudoscience. Kuhn was skeptical about any remedy that would reliably transform a protoscience to a science stating, “I claim no therapy to assist the transformation of a proto-science to a science, nor do I suppose anything of this sort is to be had.”
Raimo Tuomela defined a protoscience as a research field that satisfies 9 of the 12 science conditions; a protoscience fails to satisfy the up-to-date conditions for logic/mathematical tools, specific background knowledge from neighboring fields, and accumulated knowledge (5, 7, 9), and there is reason to believe the protoscience will ultimately satisfy all 12 conditions. Protosciences and belief fields are both non-science fields, but only a protoscience can become a science field. Tuomela emphasizes that the cognitive field concept refers to "ideal types" and there may be some persons within a science field with non-scientific "attitudes, thinking and actions"; therefore, it may be better to apply scientific and non-scientific to "attitudes, thinking and actions" rather than directly to cognitive fields.
Developmental stages of science
Bunge stated that protoscience may occur as the second stage of a five-stage process in the development of science. Each stage has a theoretical and empirical aspect:
- Prescience has unchecked speculation theory and unchecked data.
- Protoscience has hypotheses without theory accompanied by observation and occasional measurement, but no experiment.
- Deuteroscience has hypotheses formulated mathematically without theory accompanied by systematic measurement, and experiment on perceptible traits of perceptible objects.
- Tritoscience has mathematical models accompanied by systematic measurements and experiments on perceptible and imperceptible traits of perceptible and imperceptible objects.
- Tetartoscience has mathematical models and comprehensive theories accompanied by precise systematic measurements and experiments on perceptible and imperceptible traits of perceptible and imperceptible objects.
Origin of protoscience
Protoscience may arise from the philosophical inquiry that anticipates science. Philosophers anticipated the development of astronomy, atomic theory, evolution and linguistics. The Greek philosopher Anaximander (610–546 BC) viewed the earth as a non-moving free-floating cylinder in space. The atomist doctrine of Democritus (460–370 BC) to Epicurus (341–270 BC) was that objects were composed of non-visible small particles. Anaximander had anticipated that humans may have developed from more primitive organisms. Wittgenstein’s study of language preceded the linguistic studies of J. L. Austin and John Searle. Popper describes how scientific theory arises from myths such as atomism and the corpuscular theory of light. Popper states that the Copernican system was "inspired by a Neo-Platonic worship of the light of the Sun who had to occupy the center because of his nobility", leading to "testable components" that ultimately became "fruitful and important."
Some scholars use the term "primitive protoscience" to describe ancient myths that help explain natural phenomena at a time prior to the development of the scientific method.
Protoscience examples
Physical science
- Ancient astronomical protoscience was recorded as astronomical images and records inscribed on stones, bones and cave walls.
- Luigi Ferdinando Marsili (1658–1730) contributed to protoscience oceanography, describing the ocean currents of the Bosporus and physical oceanography, and Benjamin Franklin contributed by identifying the currents of the Gulf Stream.
- Philosophers consider physics before Galileo and Huygens, chemistry before Lavoisier, medicine before Virchow and Bernard, electricity before the mid-eighteenth century, and the study of heredity and phylogeny before the mid-nineteenth century as protosciences that eventually became established science.
- Prior to 1905, leading scientists, Ostwald and Mach, viewed atomic and molecular-kinetic theory as a protoscience, a theory indirectly supported by chemistry and statistical thermodynamics; however, Einstein's theory of Brownian motion, and Perrin's experimental verification led to widespread acceptance of atomic and molecular-kinetic theory as established science.
- The early stage of plate tectonics, beginning with Wegener's theory of continental drift, was a protoscience until experimental research confirmed the theory many years later. The initial widespread rejection of Wegener's theory is an example of the importance of not dismissing a protoscience.
Psychology
Critics state that psychology is a protoscience because some practices occur that prevent falsification of research hypotheses. Folk psychology and coaching psychology are protosciences.
Medicine
The use of scientifically invalid biomarkers to identify adverse outcomes is a protoscience practice in medicine. The process for reporting adverse medical events is a protoscience because it relies on uncorroborated data and unsystematic methods.
Technology
Hatleback describes cybersecurity as a protoscience that lacks transparency in experimentation, scientific laws, and sound experimental design in some cases; however cybersecurity has the potential to become a science.
See also
- History of science
- Hypothesis
- Pseudoscience
- Methodical culturalism
- Natural philosophy
- Obsolete scientific theories
- Pathological science
Notes
- Tuomela 1987.
- Jones 1910, p. 94.
- Hobhouse 1915, p. 41.
- Jones 1910.
- ^ Kuhn 1970, p. 244.
- ^ Kuhn 1970, p. 245.
- Bunge 1983, pp. 202–203.
- ^ Tuomela 1987, pp. 89–90.
- Siwecka 2011. sfn error: no target: CITEREFSiwecka2011 (help)
- Fleck 1979, pp. 101–102.
- Fleck 1979, pp. 118–120, 142–145.
- Bunge 1983, pp. 175, 202–03.
- Tuomela 1987, p. 88.
- ^ Bunge 1983, p. 175.
- ^ Bunge 1983, pp. 202–03.
- ^ Tuomela 1987, p. 91.
- ^ Tuomela 1987, p. 92.
- ^ Bunge 1983, p. 203.
- ^ Bunge 2010, p. 253.
- ^ Bunge 1983, p. 160.
- ^ Costa 2014, p. 12.
- ^ Popper 2002, p. 347.
- Johnson 2021, p. 42.
- ^ Owens 2014.
- Newburgh, Peidle & Rueckner 2006.
- ^ Tuomela 1987, p. 100.
- Oreskes & Le Grand 2001, p. 7.
- Heene & Ferguson 2017, p. 37.
- Sehon 1997.
- Grant & Cavanagh 2007.
- Grimes, Schulz & Raymond 2010.
- Kaplan & Barach 2002.
- Hatleback 2018.
References
- Bullivant, Stephen; Ruse, Michael (2021). The Cambridge history of atheism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-68899-4.
- Bunge, Mario (1983). Epistemology & Methodology II: Understanding the World. Treatise on Basic Philosophy. Vol. 6. Dordrecht: Reidel. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-6921-7. ISBN 90-277-1634-X. OCLC 9759870.
- Bunge, Mario (2010). Matter and Mind: a philosophical inquiry. Boston studies in the philosophy of science. Vol. 287. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: Springer Verlag. doi:10.1007/978-90-481-9225-0. ISBN 9789048192243.
- Bunge, Mario (1984). "What is pseudoscience?" (PDF). The Skeptical Inquirer. Vol. 9. pp. 36–46.
- Costa, Claudio F. (2014). Lines of thought : rethinking philosophical assumptions. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4438-5349-1.
- Grant, Anthony M.; Cavanagh, Michael J. (2007). "Evidence-based coaching: Flourishing or languishing?". Australian Psychologist. 42 (4): 239–254. doi:10.1080/00050060701648175.
- Fleck, Ludwik (1935). Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache - Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv (in German). Basel: Schwabe und Co., Verlagsbuchhandlung. OCLC 257469753.
- Fleck, Ludwik (1979), Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, Univ. of Chicago, ISBN 978-0-226-25325-1. (written in German, 1935, Entstehung und Entwickelung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache: Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollectiv) English translation by Thaddeus J. Trenn and Fred Bradley, 1979 Archived 2023-04-06 at the Wayback Machine Edited by Thaddeus J. Trenn and Robert K. Merton. Foreword by Robert K. Merton
- Grimes, David A.; Schulz, Kenneth F.; Raymond, Elizabeth G. (2010). "Surrogate end points in women's health research: science, protoscience, and pseudoscience". Fertility and Sterility. 93 (6): 1731–1734. doi:10.1016/j.fertnstert.2009.12.054. PMID 20153470.
- Hatleback, Eric N (2018). "The protoscience of cybersecurity". The Journal of Defense Modeling and Simulation: Applications, Methodology, Technology. 15 (1): 5–12. doi:10.1177/1548512917737635. S2CID 64688425.
- Hobhouse, Leonard Trelawny (1915). Morals in Evolution: A Study in Comparative Ethics. New York: Chapman & Hall.
- Johnson, Carl Garth (2021). "The Nlhaykapmx Oral Tradition of the Three Bears: Interpretations Old And New". Canadian Journal of Native Education. 25 (1): Vol. 25 No. 1 (2001). doi:10.14288/cjne.v25i1.195901.
- Jones, Robert (1910). "Dualism in economics". The Clare Market Review. The students magazine of the London school of economics and political science. London: Students union.
- Kaplan, H.; Barach, P. (2002). "Incident reporting: science or protoscience? Ten years later". BMJ Quality & Safety. 11 (2): 144–145. doi:10.1136/qhc.11.2.144. PMC 1743593. PMID 12448806. S2CID 22816124.
- Kuhn, Thomas Samuel (1970). "Reflections on my critics". In Lakatos, Imre; Musgrave, Alan (eds.). Criticism and the growth of knowledge;. Cambridge : University Press. ISBN 0521096235.
- Heene, Moritz; Ferguson, Christopher J. (2017). "Psychological Science's Aversion to the Null, and Why Many of the Things You Think Are True, Aren't". In Lilienfeld, Scott O.; Waldman, Irwin D. (eds.). Psychological science under scrutiny : recent challenges and proposed solutions. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell. pp. 34–52. ISBN 978-1118661079.
- Newburgh, Ronald; Peidle, Joseph; Rueckner, Wolfgang (2006). "Einstein, Perrin, and the reality of atoms: 1905 revisited". American Journal of Physics. 74 (6): 478–481. Bibcode:2006AmJPh..74..478N. doi:10.1119/1.2188962.
- Oreskes, Naomi; Le Grand, Homer (2001). Plate tectonics : an insider's history of the modern theory of the Earth. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press. ISBN 0-8133-3981-2.
- Owens, Nicholas J. P. (2014). "Sustained UK marine observations. Where have we been? Where are we now? Where are we going?". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 372 (2025): 20130332. Bibcode:2014RSPTA.37230332O. doi:10.1098/rsta.2013.0332. PMC 4150290. PMID 25157193. S2CID 34909909.
- Tuomela, Raimo (1987). "Science, Protoscience, and Pseudoscience". In Pitt, Joseph C.; Pera, Marcello (eds.). Rational Changes in Science : Essays on Scientific Reasoning. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 98. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. pp. 83–102. doi:10.1007/978-94-009-3779-6. ISBN 978-9400937802.
- Popper, Karl R. (2002). Conjectures and refutations : the growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-28593-3.
- Sehon, Scott R. (1997). "Natural-Kind Terms and the Status of Folk Psychology". American Philosophical Quarterly. 34 (3): 333–344. ISSN 0003-0481. JSTOR 20009903.
External links
- "Questions to help distinguish a pseudoscience from a protoscience". 7 January 2012. Archived from the original on 2012-01-07.