Misplaced Pages

Time: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 03:22, 17 November 2008 view sourceDonkeydarling (talk | contribs)2 editsm Philosophy: added authorlink to existing WL Craig reference← Previous edit Latest revision as of 13:51, 7 January 2025 view source Aadirulez8 (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users49,295 editsm v2.05 - Autofix / Fix errors for CW project (Link equal to linktext)Tag: WPCleaner 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Continuous progression from past to future}}
:''For other uses, see ]
{{About||the magazine|Time (magazine){{!}}''Time'' (magazine)|other uses}}{{For|musical conceptions of "time"|Time (music)|Tempo}}{{Not to be confused with|Thyme}}
] shown in ].
{{pp-protected|small=yes}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=September 2019}}
{{Time sidebar}}


'''Time''' is the continuous progression of our changing ] that occurs in an apparently ] succession from the ], through the ], and into the ].<ref>
The motions of ] and ] have demonstrated and symbolized time throughout humanity's existence.<ref name="Rudgley">{{cite book | title=The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age| last=Rudgley| first=Richard| authorlink=Richard Rudgley| year=1999| pages=86-105| publisher=Simon & Schuster| location=New York}}</ref>]]
{{cite web |url=http://oxforddictionaries.com/definition/time |title=Time |website=Oxford Dictionaries |quote=The indefinite continued progress of existence and events in the past, present, and future regarded as a whole |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=18 May 2017 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120704084938/http://oxforddictionaries.com/definition/time |archive-date=4 July 2012 }}
] can be used to keep track of elapsed time. It also concretely represents the ] as being between the ] and the ].]]
</ref><ref name=DefRefs02/><ref>
{{Cite journal |url=http://ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=time |title=Time |journal=The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language |edition=Fourth |date=2011 |quote=A nonspatial continuum in which events occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future.|url-status=live |archive-url=http://archive.wikiwix.com/cache/20120719114813/http://ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=time |archive-date=19 July 2012 }}
</ref> It is a component quantity of various ]s used to ] ], to compare the duration of events (or the intervals between them), and to ] ] of ] in ] or in the ] ].<ref>
{{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120508031242/http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/time |date=8 May 2012 }} the measured or measurable period during which an action, process, or condition exists or continues : duration; a nonspatial continuum which is measured in terms of events that succeed one another from past through present to future
</ref><ref>
Compact ] A limited stretch or space of continued existence, as the interval between two successive events or acts, or the period through which an action, condition, or state continues. (1971).
</ref><ref name=DefRefs01/><ref name=Poidevin/> Time is often referred to as a fourth ], along with ].<ref>"Newton did for time what the Greek geometers did for space, idealized it into an exactly measurable dimension." ''About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution'', Paul Davies, p. 31, Simon & Schuster, 1996, {{isbn|978-0-684-81822-1}}
</ref><ref name="metafizika">{{cite journal|last1=Bunyadzade |first1=Konul |title=Thoughts of Time |url=https://metafizikajurnali.az/yukle/files/Vol.1-8%281%29.pdf |journal=] |publisher=AcademyGate Publishing |access-date=2018-03-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190405102207/https://metafizikajurnali.az/yukle/files/Vol.1-8(1).pdf |archive-date=5 April 2019 |pages=8–29 |language=az |doi=10.33864/MTFZK.2019.0 |date=2018-03-15 |volume=1 |url-status=live|issn=2616-6879 }}</ref> Scientists have theorized a beginning of time in ] (the ]) and an end (e.g., ] or the ]). A ] describes a cyclical nature, whereas the ] views the subject from a different angle.


Time is one of the seven fundamental ] in both the ] (SI) and ]. The SI base ] is the ], which is defined by measuring the ] ] of ] atoms. ] is the primary framework for understanding how spacetime works.<ref>{{cite book |title=Partial Differential Equations in General Relativity |edition=illustrated |first1=Alan D. |last1=Rendall |publisher=OUP Oxford |year=2008 |isbn=978-0-19-921540-9 |page=9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CPkaAQAAIAAJ |access-date=24 November 2020 |archive-date=14 April 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210414095906/https://books.google.com/books?id=CPkaAQAAIAAJ |url-status=live }}</ref> Through advances in both theoretical and experimental investigations of spacetime, it has been shown that time can be distorted and ], particularly at the edges of ]s.
'''Time''' is a component of a ] used to sequence events, to compare the durations of events and the intervals between them, and to quantify the motions of objects. Time has been a major subject of ], ], and ], but defining time in a non-controversial manner applicable to all fields of study has consistently eluded the greatest scholars.


Throughout history, time has been an important subject of study in religion, philosophy, and science. Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and ] and has been a prime motivation in ] and ]. Time is also of significant social importance, having ] ("]") as well as personal value, due to an ] of the limited time in each day and in ]. Cultural attitudes towards the human use of time are apparent in the verbs used—from "kill" to "waste" to "pass"—and sayings (like '']'').
In ] and other sciences, ''time'' is considered one of the few ].<ref name="Trialogue">{{cite paper
| author = Duff, Michael J.
| coauthors = Okun, Lev B.; Veneziano, Gabriele
| title = Trialogue on the number of fundamental constants
| version =
| publisher = Institute of Physics Publishing for SISSA/ISAS
| month = March | year = 2002
| url = http://jhep.sissa.it/archive/papers/jhep032002023/jhep032002023.pdf
| format = PDF
| accessdate = 2008-02-02 }} p. 17. "I only add to this the observation that relativity and quantum mechanics provide, in string theory, units of length and time which look, at present, more fundamental than any other."</ref> ''Time'' is used to define other quantities – such as ] – and defining ''time'' in terms of such quantities would result in ].<ref name="TrialogueP3">Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ''ibid.'' p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature. … The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e. actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of
wrong statements."</ref> An ] of time, wherein one says that observing a certain number of repetitions of one or another standard cyclical event (such as the passage of a free-swinging pendulum) constitutes one standard unit such as the ], is highly useful in the conduct of both advanced experiments and everyday affairs of life. The operational definition leaves aside the question whether there is something called time, apart from the counting activity just mentioned, that flows and that can be measured. Investigations of a single continuum called ] brings the nature of time into association with related questions into the nature of ], questions that have their roots in the works of early students of ].


== Definition ==
Among prominent philosophers, there are two distinct viewpoints on ''time''.
One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the ], a ] in which events occur in ]. ], in this view, becomes a possibility as other "times" persist like frames of a film strip, spread out across the time line. ] subscribed to this ] view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as ].<ref name=Rynasiewicz>
{{cite web
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/newton-stm/
|title=Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion
|date=2004-08-12
|copyright=2004
|first=Robert : Johns Hopkins University
|last=Rynasiewicz
|publisher=Stanford University
|work=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|quote=Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation the anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year).
|accessdate=2008-01-10}}
</ref><ref>
{{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time/#3
|last=Markosian
|first=Ned
|title=Time
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition)
|editor=Edward N. Zalta
|quote=The opposing view, normally referred to either as “Platonism with Respect to Time” or as “Absolutism with Respect to Time,” has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it.
|accessddate=2008-01-18}}</ref> The opposing view is that ''time'' does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with ] and ]) within which humans sequence and compare events. This second view, in the tradition of ]<ref name=Burnham>{{cite web
|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/l/leib-met.htm#H7
|title=Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) Metaphysics - 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles
|first=Douglas : Staffordshire University
|last=Burnham
|year=2006
|work=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|quote=First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time.
|accessdate=2008-01-10}}</ref>
and ],<ref name=Mattey>
{{cite web
|url=http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIMELEC.HTM
|title=Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis
|date=1997-01-22
|last=Mattey
|first=G. J. : UC Davis
|quote=What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, mutatis mutandis, to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition."
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}}</ref><ref name=McCormick>
{{cite web
|title=Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Metaphysics : 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism
|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/k/kantmeta.htm#H4
|work=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|first=Matt : California State University, Sacramento
|last=McCormick
|year=2006
|quote=Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the a priori contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues.
|accessdate=2008-01-10}}
</ref>
holds that ''time'' is neither an event nor a thing, and thus is not itself measurable nor can it be traveled.


The concept of time can be complex. Multiple notions exist and defining time in a manner applicable to all fields without ] has consistently eluded scholars.<ref name=Poidevin/><ref name="Carroll2009">{{cite journal|last=Carroll |first=Sean M. |title=From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time |title-link=From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time |date=2009 |journal=Physics Today |publisher=Dutton |isbn=978-0-525-95133-9 |volume=63 |pages=54–55 |bibcode=2010PhT....63d..54C |doi=10.1063/1.3397046 |issue=4}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web |title=The Feynman Lectures on Physics Vol. I Ch. 5: Time and Distance |url=https://www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu/I_05.html |access-date=2023-12-15 |website=www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu}}</ref> Nevertheless, diverse fields such as business, industry, sports, the sciences, and the performing arts all incorporate some notion of time into their respective ].<ref name="MLB">{{cite web |last= |first= |date=2011 |title=Official Baseball Rules – 8.03 and 8.04 |url=http://mlb.mlb.com/mlb/downloads/y2011/Official_Baseball_Rules.pdf |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170701102437/http://mlb.mlb.com/mlb/downloads/y2011/Official_Baseball_Rules.pdf |archive-date=1 July 2017 |access-date=18 May 2017 |publisher=Major League Baseball |format=Free PDF download |quote=Rule 8.03 Such preparatory pitches shall not consume more than one minute of time...Rule 8.04 When the bases are unoccupied, the pitcher shall deliver the ball to the batter within 12 seconds...The 12-second timing starts when the pitcher is in possession of the ball and the batter is in the box, alert to the pitcher. The timing stops when the pitcher releases the ball.}}</ref><ref name=Guinness>{{cite web |title=Guinness Book of Baseball World Records |publisher=Guinness World Records, Ltd. |url=http://www.baseball-almanac.com/recbooks/rb_guin.shtml |quote=The record for the fastest time for circling the bases is 13.3 seconds, set by Evar Swanson at Columbus, Ohio in 1932...The greatest reliably recorded speed at which a baseball has been pitched is 100.9 mph by Lynn Nolan Ryan (California Angels) at Anaheim Stadium in California on 20 August 1974. |access-date=7 July 2012 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120606114603/http://www.baseball-almanac.com/recbooks/rb_guin.shtml |archive-date=6 June 2012 }}</ref><ref name=Zeigler>{{cite book |last=Zeigler |first=Kenneth |title=Getting organized at work : 24 lessons to set goals, establish priorities, and manage your time |publisher=McGraw-Hill |date=2008 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=acPPD6lCCxcC |isbn=978-0-07-159138-6 |access-date=30 July 2019 |archive-date=18 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200818215121/https://books.google.com/books?id=acPPD6lCCxcC |url-status=live }} 108 pages.</ref> Traditional definitions of time involved the observation of periodic motion such as the apparent motion of the sun across the sky, the phases of the moon, and the passage of a free-swinging pendulum. More modern systems include the ], other satellite systems, ] and ]. Although these systems differ from one another, with careful measurements they can be synchronized.
Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and ]s, and was a prime motivation in ] and ].
Periodic events and periodic motion have long served as standards for units of time. Examples include the apparent motion of the sun across the sky, the phases of the moon, the swing of a pendulum, and the beat of a heart. Currently, the international unit of time, the ], is defined in terms of radiation emitted by ] atoms (see ]). Time is also of significant social importance, having economic value ("]") as well as personal value, due to an ] of the limited time in each day and in ].


In physics, time is a fundamental concept to define other quantities, such as ]. To avoid a circular definition,<ref name="TrialogueP3">Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ''ibid''. p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature.&nbsp;... The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e., actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of wrong statements."
==Temporal measurement==
</ref> ] is ] as "what a ] reads", specifically a count of repeating events such as the ].<ref name=DefRefs01/><ref name=Burnham/><ref>{{cite book |title=Process instruments and controls handbook |edition=3 |first1=Douglas M. |last1=Considine |first2=Glenn D. |last2=Considine |publisher=McGraw-Hill |year=1985 |isbn=978-0-07-012436-3 |pages=18–61 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kt1UAAAAMAAJ |bibcode=1985pich.book.....C |access-date=1 November 2016 |archive-date=31 December 2013 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131231121535/http://books.google.com/books?id=kt1UAAAAMAAJ |url-status=live }}</ref> Although this aids in practical measurements, it does not address the essence of time. Physicists developed the concept of the ] continuum, where events are assigned four coordinates: three for space and one for time. Events like ]s, ]s, or ]es have coordinates that may vary for different observers, making concepts like "now" and "here" relative. In ], these coordinates do not directly correspond to the causal structure of events. Instead, the ] is calculated and classified as either space-like or time-like, depending on whether an observer exists that would say the events are separated by space or by time.<ref>{{cite book |author1=Lilley |first=Sam |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ZS45AAAAIAAJ |title=Discovering Relativity for Yourself |publisher=Cambridge University Press Archive |year=1981 |isbn=978-0-521-23038-4 |edition=illustrated |page=125}} .</ref> Since the time required for light to travel a specific distance is the same for all observers—a fact first publicly demonstrated by the ]—all observers will consistently agree on this definition of time as a ].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Surya |first1=Sumati |title=The causal set approach to quantum gravity |journal=Living Reviews in Relativity |date=December 2019 |volume=22 |issue=1 |page=5 |doi=10.1007/s41114-019-0023-1 |quote=Thus, the causal structure poset (M, ≺) of a future and past distinguishing spacetime is equivalent to its conformal geometry.|doi-access=free |arxiv=1903.11544 |bibcode=2019LRR....22....5S }}</ref>
Temporal measurement, or ], takes two distinct period forms: the ], a mathematical abstraction for calculating extensive periods of time,<ref name="Richards">{{cite book | title=Mapping Time: The Calendar and its History| last=Richards| first=E. G.| authorlink=| year=1998| pages=3-5| publisher=Oxford University Press}}</ref> and the ], a concrete mechanism that counts the ongoing passage of time. In day-to-day life, the clock is consulted for periods less than a day, the calendar, for periods longer than a day. The number (as on a clock dial or calendar) that marks the occurrence of a specified event as to hour or date is obtained by counting from a fiducial epoch—a central reference point.


General relativity does not address the nature of time for extremely small intervals where quantum mechanics holds. In quantum mechanics, time is treated as a universal and absolute parameter, differing from general relativity's notion of independent clocks. The ] consists of reconciling these two theories.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Macías |first1=Alfredo |last2=Camacho |first2=Abel |title=On the incompatibility between quantum theory and general relativity |journal=Physics Letters B |date=May 2008 |volume=663 |issue=1–2 |pages=99–102 |doi=10.1016/j.physletb.2008.03.052 |quote=In our opinion, it is not possible to reconciliate and integrate into a common scheme the absolute and non-dynamical character of Newtonian time of canonical quantization and path integral approaches with the relativistic and dynamical character of time in general relativity.|doi-access=free |bibcode=2008PhLB..663...99M }}</ref> As of 2024, there is no generally accepted theory of quantum general relativity.<ref>{{cite news |last1=Shavit |first1=Joseph |title=Revolutionary theory finally unites quantum mechanics and Einstein's theory of general relativity |url=https://www.thebrighterside.news/post/revolutionary-theory-finally-unites-quantum-mechanics-and-einsteins-theory-of-general-relativity/ |work=The Brighter Side of News |date=18 July 2024 |language=en |quote=The prevailing consensus has been that Einstein's theory of gravity must be modified to fit within the framework of quantum theory when it comes to merging these two theories into a single, comprehensive framework, the scientific community has hit a roadblock.}}</ref>
===History of the calendar===
{{main|Calendar}}
Artifacts from the ] suggest that the moon was used to calculate time as early as 12,000, and possibly even 30,000 ].<ref name="Rudgley" />


== Measurement ==
The ]ian civilization of approximately 2000 BC introduced the ] system based on the number 60. 60 seconds in a minute, 60 minutes in an hour – and possibly a calendar with 360 (60x6) days in a year (with a few more days added on).
] uses the flow of ] to measure the passage of time.]]
Twelve also features prominently, with roughly 12 hours of day and 12 of night, and 12 months in a year (with 12 being 1/5 of 60).<!--- use of 60 could not have appeared until people started using minutes - which they would not have done with sundials --->


Generally speaking, historical methods of temporal measurement, or ], have taken two distinct forms: the ], a mathematical tool for organising long intervals of time,<ref name="Richards">{{cite book |title=Mapping Time: The Calendar and its History |url=https://archive.org/details/mappingtimecalen00rich_059 |url-access=limited |last=Richards |first=E. G. |date=1998 |pages=–5 |publisher=]|isbn=978-0-19-850413-9 }}
The reforms of ] in 45 BC put the ] on a ]. This ] was faulty in that its ] still allowed the astronomical ]s and ]es to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. ] introduced a correction in 1582; the ] was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but is today the one in most common use around the world.
</ref> and the ] (e.g., ]), a physical mechanism that counts the passage of time. In day-to-day life, a clock was consulted for periods less than a day, whereas a calendar was consulted for periods longer than a day.


Increasingly, personal electronic devices display both calendars and clocks simultaneously. The number (as on a ] or calendar) that marks the occurrence of a specified event (as to hour or date) is obtained by counting from certain starting date (]), and relevant to a certain ] (including ]). Precise measurements, as in ], use a fiducial epoch&nbsp;– a central reference point.
===History of time measurement devices===
] in ] (1833)]]
{{main|History of timekeeping devices}}{{seealso|Clock}}


=== History of the calendar ===
A large variety of ]s have been invented to measure time. The study of these devices is called ].
{{Main|Calendar}}


Artifacts from the ] suggest that the moon was used to reckon time as early as 6,000 years ago.<ref name="Rudgley">{{cite book |title=The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age |last=Rudgley |first=Richard |author-link=Richard Rudgley |date=1999 |pages=86–105 |publisher=Simon & Schuster |location=New York}}
An ]ian device dating to c.1500 BC, similar in shape to a bent ], measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a non-linear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At ], the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.<ref>Barnett, Jo Ellen ''Time's Pendulum: The Quest to Capture Time—from Sundials to Atomic Clocks'' Plenum, 1998 ISBN 0-306-45787-3 p.28</ref>
</ref> ]s were among the first to appear, with years of either 12 or 13 ]s (either 354 or 384 days). Without ] to add days or months to some years, seasons quickly drift in a calendar based solely on twelve lunar months. ]s have a thirteenth month added to some years to make up for the difference between a full year (now known to be about 365.24 days) and a year of just twelve lunar months. The numbers twelve and thirteen came to feature prominently in many cultures, at least partly due to this relationship of months to years. Other early forms of calendars originated in Mesoamerica, particularly in ancient Mayan civilization. These calendars were religiously and astronomically based, with 18 months in a year and 20 days in a month, plus five ] days at the end of the year.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Van Stone | first1 = Mark | year = 2011 | title = The Maya Long Count Calendar: An Introduction | journal = Archaeoastronomy | volume = 24 | pages = 8–11 }}</ref>


The reforms of ] in 45 BC put the ] on a ]. This ] was faulty in that its intercalation still allowed the astronomical ]s and ]es to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. ] introduced a correction in 1582; the ] was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but it is now by far the most commonly used calendar around the world.
A ] uses a ] to cast a shadow on a set of markings which were calibrated to the ]. The position of the shadow marked the hour in ].


During the ], a new clock and calendar were invented as part of the ] and to create a more rational system in order to replace the Gregorian calendar. The ]'s days consisted of ten hours of a hundred minutes of a hundred seconds, which marked a deviation from the base 12 (]) system used in many other devices by many cultures. The system was abolished in 1806.<ref>"French Republican Calendar | Chronology." Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, n.d. Web. 21 February 2016.</ref>
The most precise timekeeping devices of the ancient world were the ] or ''clepsydra'', one of which was found in the tomb of Egyptian pharaoh ] (1525–1504 BC). They could be used to measure the hours even at night, but required manual timekeeping to replenish the flow of water. The ] and ] regularly maintained timekeeping records as an essential part of their astronomical observations. ] and ] in particular made improvements on the use of water clocks up to the Middle Ages.<ref>Barnett, ''ibid'', p.37</ref>


=== History of other devices ===
The Arab engineers also invented the first mechanical clocks to be driven by ] and ]s in the 11th century.<ref name=Salim>Professor ] (2006), ''1001 Inventions: Muslim Heritage in Our World'', FSTC, ISBN 0955242606</ref><ref name="Where the heart is">, ''1001 Inventions: Muslim Heritage in Our World'', 2006</ref><ref name=Hassan>], , ''History of Science and Technology in Islam''.</ref> Also in the 11th century, the ] and ] invented the first mechanical clocks to be driven by an ] mechanism.
] in Canberra]]
]
{{Main|History of timekeeping devices}}
{{See also|Clock}}


A large variety of ] have been invented to measure time. The study of these devices is called ].<ref>{{Cite web | url=https://nawcc.org/index.php/main-education | title=Education | access-date=1 July 2018 | archive-date=1 May 2019 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190501213902/https://nawcc.org/index.php/main-education | url-status=live }}</ref>
]]]
The ] uses the flow of sand to measure the flow of time. They were used in navigation. ] used 18 glasses on each ship for his circumnavigation of the globe (1522).<ref>Laurence Bergreen, ''Over the Edge of the World: Magellan's Terrifying Circumnavigation of the Globe'', HarperCollins Publishers, 2003, hardcover 480 pages, ISBN 0-06-621173-5</ref>


An Egyptian device that dates to {{Circa|1500 BC}}, similar in shape to a bent ], measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a nonlinear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At noon, the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.<ref>{{cite book |author1=Barnett |first=Jo Ellen |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-ygDdx73hvcC |title=Time's Pendulum: From Sundials to Atomic Clocks, the Fascinating History of Timekeeping and how Our Discoveries Changed the World |publisher=Harcourt Brace |year=1999 |isbn=978-0-15-600649-1 |edition=reprinted |page=28}}</ref>
Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Waterclocks, and later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. ] (1292–1336), abbot of St. Alban's abbey, famously built a mechanical clock as an astronomical ] about 1330.<ref>North, J. (2004) ''God's Clockmaker: Richard of Wallingford and the Invention of Time''. Oxbow Books. ISBN 1-85285-451-0</ref><ref>Watson, E (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". ''Antiquarian Horology'' 372-384.</ref>


A ] uses a ] to cast a shadow on a set of markings calibrated to the hour. The position of the shadow marks the hour in ]. The idea to separate the day into smaller parts is credited to Egyptians because of their sundials, which operated on a duodecimal system. The importance of the number 12 is due to the number of lunar cycles in a year and the number of stars used to count the passage of night.<ref>Lombardi, Michael A. "Why Is a Minute Divided into 60 Seconds, an Hour into 60 Minutes, Yet There Are Only 24 Hours in a Day?" Scientific American. Springer Nature, 5 March 2007. Web. 21 February 2016.</ref>
The English word ] probably comes from the Middle Dutch word "klocke" which is in turn derived from the mediaeval Latin word "clocca", which is ultimately derived from Celtic, and is cognate with French, Latin, and German words that mean ]. The passage of the hours at sea were marked by bells, and denoted the time (see ]). The hours were marked by bells in the abbeys as well as at sea.


The most precise timekeeping device of the ] was the ], or ''clepsydra'', one of which was found in the tomb of Egyptian pharaoh ]. They could be used to measure the hours even at night but required manual upkeep to replenish the flow of water. The ] and the people from ] (southeastern Mesopotamia) regularly maintained timekeeping records as an essential part of their astronomical observations. Arab inventors and engineers, in particular, made improvements on the use of water clocks up to the Middle Ages.<ref>Barnett, ''ibid'', p. 37.</ref> In the 11th century, ] and ] invented the first mechanical clocks driven by an ] mechanism.
]
Clocks can range from ]es, to more exotic varieties such as the ]. They can be driven by a variety of means, including gravity, springs, and various forms of electrical power, and regulated by a variety of means such as a ].


], 2007 ]]
A ] is a portable timekeeper that meets certain precision standards. Initially, the term was used to refer to the ], a timepiece used to determine ] by means of ]. More recently, the term has also been applied to the ], a ] that meets precision standards set by the Swiss agency ].
The ] uses the flow of sand to measure the flow of time. They were used in navigation. ] used 18 glasses on each ship for his circumnavigation of the globe (1522).<ref>Bergreen, Laurence. ''Over the Edge of the World: Magellan's Terrifying Circumnavigation of the Globe'' (HarperCollins Publishers, 2003), {{isbn|0-06-621173-5}}{{page needed|date=October 2018}}</ref>


Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Water clocks, and, later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. ] (1292–1336), abbot of St. Alban's abbey, famously built a mechanical clock as an astronomical ] about 1330.<ref>North, J. (2004) ''God's Clockmaker: Richard of Wallingford and the Invention of Time''. Oxbow Books. {{isbn|1-85285-451-0}}</ref><ref>Watson, E., (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". ''Antiquarian Horology,'' pp. 372–384.</ref>
The most accurate timekeeping devices are ]s, which are accurate to seconds in many millions of years,<ref>{{cite news |url=http://www.canada.com/vancouversun/news/story.html?id=e24ccfa7-44eb-40b7-8b67-daf8263569ff |title=New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation |date=2008-02-16 |publisher=Vancouver Sun |accessdate=2008-02-16}}</ref> and are used to calibrate other clocks and timekeeping instruments.

Atomic clocks use the spin property of atoms as their basis, and since 1967, the International System of Measurements bases its unit of time, the second, on the properties of ] atoms. ] defines the second as 9,192,631,770 cycles of that radiation which corresponds to the transition between two electron spin energy levels of the ground state of the <sup>133</sup>Cs atom.
Great advances in accurate time-keeping were made by ] and especially ] with the invention of pendulum-driven clocks along with the invention of the minute hand by Jost Burgi.<ref name="Clocks 2016">"History of Clocks." About.com Inventors. About.com, n.d. Web. 21 February 2016.</ref>

The English word ] probably comes from the Middle Dutch word ''klocke'' which, in turn, derives from the medieval Latin word ''clocca'', which ultimately derives from Celtic and is cognate with French, Latin, and German words that mean ]. The passage of the hours at sea was marked by bells and denoted the time (see ]). The hours were marked by bells in abbeys as well as at sea.

]s, such as this one unveiled in 2004, are expected to greatly improve ] location.<ref>{{cite journal |url=https://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/miniclock.cfm |title=NIST Unveils Chip-Scale Atomic Clock |journal=NIST |date=27 August 2004 |access-date=9 June 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110522125607/http://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/miniclock.cfm |archive-date=22 May 2011 }}</ref>]]

Clocks can range from watches to more exotic varieties such as the ]. They can be driven by a variety of means, including gravity, springs, and various forms of electrical power, and regulated by a variety of means such as a ].

Alarm clocks first appeared in ancient Greece around 250 BC with a water clock that would set off a whistle. This idea was later mechanized by Levi Hutchins and ].<ref name="Clocks 2016"/>

A ] is a portable timekeeper that meets certain precision standards. Initially, the term was used to refer to the ], a timepiece used to determine ] by means of ], a precision first achieved by ]. More recently, the term has also been applied to the ], a watch that meets precision standards set by the Swiss agency ].

The most accurate timekeeping devices are ]s, which are accurate to seconds in many millions of years,<ref>{{cite news |url=http://www.canada.com/vancouversun/news/story.html?id=e24ccfa7-44eb-40b7-8b67-daf8263569ff |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120211190407/http://www.canada.com/vancouversun/news/story.html?id=e24ccfa7-44eb-40b7-8b67-daf8263569ff |url-status=dead |archive-date=11 February 2012 |title=New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation |date=16 February 2008 |work=Vancouver Sun |access-date=9 April 2011}}</ref> and are used to calibrate other clocks and timekeeping instruments.

Atomic clocks use the frequency of ]s in certain atoms to measure the second. One of the atoms used is ]; most modern atomic clocks probe caesium with microwaves to determine the frequency of these electron vibrations.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/n99-22.cf |title=NIST-F1 Cesium Fountain Clock |access-date=24 July 2015 |archive-date=25 March 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200325220323/https://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/n99-22.cf |url-status=dead }}</ref> Since 1967, the International System of Measurements bases its unit of time, the second, on the properties of ] atoms. ] defines the second as 9,192,631,770 cycles of the radiation that corresponds to the transition between two electron spin energy levels of the ground state of the <sup>133</sup>Cs atom.


Today, the ] in coordination with the ] can be used to synchronize timekeeping systems across the globe. Today, the ] in coordination with the ] can be used to synchronize timekeeping systems across the globe.
<br clear=right>


In medieval philosophical writings, the '''atom''' was a unit of time referred to as the smallest possible division of time. The earliest known occurrence in English is in ]'s ''Enchiridion'' (a science text) of 1010–1012,<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |title=Byrhtferth of Ramsey |year=2008 |encyclopedia=] |access-date=15 September 2008 |url=http://search.eb.com/eb/article-9438957 |archive-date=14 June 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200614055906/https://academic.eb.com/?target=%2Flevels |url-status=live }}</ref> where it was defined as 1/564 of a ''momentum'' (1{{frac|1|2}} minutes),<ref>"atom", ], Draft Revision September 2008 (contains relevant citations from Byrhtferth's ''Enchiridion'')</ref> and thus equal to 15/94 of a second. It was used in the '']'', the process of calculating the date of Easter.
== Definitions and standards ==
<!-- BEGIN common units of time table -->
{| class=wikitable align=right style="float:right; margin: 0.5em 0 0.5em 1em; font-size:90%"
|+ Common units of time
|-
! Unit !! Size!!Notes
|-
| ] || 0.000 000 000 001 seconds|| no way of accurately measuring
|-
| ] || 0.000 000 001 seconds||
|-
| ] || 0.000 001 seconds||
|-
| ] || 0.001 seconds||
|-
| ] || ] base unit||
|-
| ] || 60 seconds||
|-
| ] || 60 minutes||
|-
| ] || 24 hours||
|-
| ] || 7 days|| Also called sennight
|-
| ] || 14 days || 2 weeks
|-
| ] || 28 to 31 days||
|-
| ] || 3 months||
|-
| ] || 12 months||
|-
| common ] || 365 days || 52 weeks + 1 day
|-
| ] || 366 days||52 weeks + 2 days
|-
| ] || 365.24219 days||average
|-
| ] || 365.2425 days||average
|-
| ] || 4 year cycle ||
|-
| ] || 5 years||
|-
| ] || 10 years||
|-
| ] || 15 year cycle ||
|-
| ] || 20 years||
|-
| ] || 17 - 25 years ||approximate
|-
| ] || 50 years ||
|-
| ] || 100 years||
|-
| ] || 1,000 years||
|}
<!-- END common units of time table -->
{{seealso|Time standard|Orders of magnitude (time)}}


{{As of| May 2010}}, the smallest time interval uncertainty in direct measurements is on the order of 12 ]s (1.2 × 10<sup>−17</sup> seconds), about 3.7 × 10<sup>26</sup> ]s.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.physorg.com/news192909576.html |title=12 attoseconds is the world record for shortest controllable time |date=12 May 2010 |access-date=19 April 2012 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110805173204/http://www.physorg.com/news192909576.html |archive-date=5 August 2011 }}
The ] for time is the ] ]. From the second, larger units such as the ], ] and ] are defined, though they are "non-SI" units because they do not use the decimal system, and also because of the occasional need for a ]. They are, however, officially accepted for use ''with'' the International System. There are no fixed ratios between seconds and ]s or ]s as months and years have significant variations in length.<ref name="si_units">{{cite book | title = The International System of Units (SI), 7th Edition | url = http://www1.bipm.org/utils/en/pdf/si-brochure.pdf | format = PDF | year = 1998 | author = Organisation Intergouvernementale de la Convention du Métre | accessdate = 2006-06-13}}</ref>
</ref>


=== Units ===
The official SI definition of the second is as follows:<ref name="si_units">{{cite book | title = The International System of Units (SI), 7th Edition | url = http://www1.bipm.org/utils/en/pdf/si-brochure.pdf | format = PDF | year = 1998 | author = Organisation Intergouvernementale de la Convention du Métre | accessdate = 2006-06-13}}</ref><ref name="second">{{cite web | title = Base unit definitions: Second | url = http://physics.nist.gov/cuu/Units/second.html | publisher = ] | accessdate = 2008-01-09}}</ref>
{{See also|Time (Orders of magnitude)|Unit of time#List}}
{{Bquote|The second is the duration of 9,192,631,770 periods of the radiation corresponding to the transition between the two hyperfine levels of the ground state of the ] 133 atom.}}
<br clear=left>


The second (s) is the ] base unit. A ] (min) is 60 seconds in length (or, rarely, 59 or 61 seconds when leap seconds are employed), and an ] is 60 minutes or 3600 seconds in length. A day is usually 24 hours or 86,400 seconds in length; however, the duration of a calendar day can vary due to ] and ]s.
At its 1997 meeting, the CIPM affirmed that this definition refers to a caesium atom in its ground state at a temperature of 0 K.<ref name="si_units"/>
Previous to 1967, the second was defined as:
{{Bquote|the fraction 1/31,556,925.9747 of the ] for 1900 January 0 at 12 hours ].}}
<br clear=left>


== Time standards ==
The current definition of the second, coupled with the current definition of the ], is based on the ], which affirms our ] to be a ].
{{main|Time standard}}


A time standard is a specification for measuring time: assigning a number or ] to an ] (point in time), quantifying the duration of a time interval, and establishing a ] (ordering of events). In modern times, several time specifications have been officially recognized as standards, where formerly they were matters of custom and practice. The invention in 1955 of the caesium ] has led to the replacement of older and purely astronomical time standards such as ] and ], for most practical purposes, by newer time standards based wholly or partly on atomic time using the SI second.
===World time===
The measurement of time is so critical to the functioning of modern societies that it is coordinated at an international level. The basis for scientific time is a continuous count of seconds based on ]s around the world, known as the ]. This is the yardstick for other time scales, including ], which is the basis for civil time.


] (TAI) is the primary international time standard from which other time standards are calculated. ] (UT1) is mean solar time at 0° longitude, computed from astronomical observations. It varies from TAI because of the irregularities in Earth's rotation. ] (UTC) is an atomic time scale designed to approximate Universal Time. UTC differs from TAI by an integral number of seconds. UTC is kept within 0.9 second of UT1 by the introduction of one-second steps to UTC, the ]. The ] broadcasts a very precise time signal based on UTC time.
Earth is split up into a number of ]s. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from UTC or ]. In many locations these offsets vary twice yearly due to ] transitions.


The surface of the Earth is split into a number of ]s. Standard time or ] in a time zone deviates a fixed, round amount, usually a whole number of hours, from some form of Universal Time, usually UTC. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from UTC. For example, time zones at sea are based on UTC. In many locations (but not at sea) these offsets vary twice yearly due to ] transitions.
===Sidereal time===
] is the measurement of time relative to a distant star (instead of solar time that is relative to the sun). It is used in astronomy to predict when a star will be overhead. Due to the rotation of the earth around the sun a sidereal day is 1/366 (4 minutes) less than a solar day.


Some other time standards are used mainly for scientific work. ] is a theoretical ideal scale realized by TAI. ] and ] are scales defined as ]s in the context of the general theory of relativity. ] is an older relativistic scale that is still in use.
===Chronology===
{{main|Chronology}}
Another form of time measurement consists of studying the ]. Events in the past can be ordered in a sequence (creating a ]), and be put into chronological groups (]). One of the most important systems of periodization is ], which is a system of periodizing the events that shaped the ] and its life. Chronology, periodization, and interpretation of the past are together known as the study of ].
]


== Philosophy ==
==Religion and mythology==
{{see|:Category:Time and fate deities}}
In the ] book ], traditionally ascribed to ] (970–928 BC), time (as the Hebrew word עדן, זמן ''`iddan(time) zĕman(season)'' is often translated) was traditionally regarded as a medium for the passage of ] events. (Another word, זמן ''zman'', was current as meaning ''time fit for an event'', and is used as the modern ] equivalent to the English word "time".)
] shown ] ]]


=== Religion ===
<blockquote>
] texts shown ] ]]
There is an appointed time (''zman'') for everything. And there is a time (’êth) for every event under heaven–<br />
{{Further|Time and fate deities}}
A time (''’êth'') to give birth, and a time to die; A time to plant, and a time to uproot what is planted.<br />
A time to kill, and a time to heal; A time to tear down, and a time to build up.<br />
A time to weep, and a time to laugh; A time to mourn, and a time to dance.<br />
A time to throw stones, and a time to gather stones; A time to embrace, and a time to shun embracing.<br />
A time to search, and a time to give up as lost; A time to keep, and a time to throw away.<br />
A time to tear apart, and a time to sew together; A time to be silent, and a time to speak.<br />
A time to love, and a time to hate; A time for war, and a time for peace.


==== Religions which view time as cyclical ====
– {{bibleverse||Ecclesiastes|3:1–8|}}
{{See also|Calendar|Wheel of time}}
</blockquote>


Many ancient cultures, particularly in the East, had a cyclical view of time. In these traditions, time was often seen as a recurring pattern of ages or cycles, where events and phenomena repeated themselves in a predictable manner. One of the most famous examples of this concept is found in ], where time is depicted as a wheel called the "]" or "Wheel of Time." According to this belief, the universe undergoes endless cycles of creation, preservation, and destruction.<ref name="newman51">{{cite book |author=Newman |first=John |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iGDCQNn0C9oC |title=The Wheel of Time: Kalachakra in Context |publisher=Shambhala |year=1991 |isbn=978-1-55939-779-7 |editor=Geshe Lhundub Sopa |pages=51–54, 62–77}}</ref>
===Linear and cyclical time===
{{seealso|Time Cycles|Wheel of time}}
In general, the ] concept, based on the ], is that time is linear, with a beginning, the act of ] by ]. The ] view assumes also an end, the eschaton, expected to happen when ] returns to earth in the ] to judge the living and the dead. This will be the consummation of the world and time. ]'s '']'' was the first developed application of this concept to world history. The Christian view is that God is uncreated and eternal so that He and the supernatural world are outside time and exist in ].


Similarly, in other ancient cultures such as those of the Mayans, Aztecs, and Chinese, there were also beliefs in cyclical time, often associated with astronomical observations and calendars.<ref>{{Cite web |date=2012-02-27 |title=Chichén Itzá: Venus Cycle |url=https://www.nationalgeographic.com/travel/article/chichen-itza-venus-cycle |access-date=2024-05-08 |website=Travel |language=en}}</ref> These cultures developed complex systems to track time, seasons, and celestial movements, reflecting their understanding of cyclical patterns in nature and the universe.
Ancient cultures such as ], ], ], and other Native American Tribes, plus the ], ], ], ], ], and others have a concept of a ], that regards time as ] and ] consisting of repeating ages that happen to every being of the Universe between birth and extinction.
<br clear=both />


The cyclical view of time contrasts with the linear concept of time more common in Western thought, where time is seen as progressing in a straight line from past to future without repetition.<ref>{{cite book |title=The Future: A Very Short Introduction |author1=Jennifer M. Gidley |edition= |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2017 |isbn=978-0-19-105424-2 |page=13 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=I3NdDgAAQBAJ}} </ref>
==Philosophy==
{{main|Philosophy of space and time|Temporal finitism}}


==== Time in Abrahamic religions ====
The earliest recorded ] of time was expounded by the ]ian thinker ] (c. 2650–2600 BC), who said: "Do not lessen the time of following desire, for the wasting of time is an abomination to the spirit."{{Fact|date=May 2008}} The '']'', the earliest texts on ] and ] dating back to the late ], describe ancient ], in which the ] goes through repeated cycles of creation, destruction and rebirth, with each cycle lasting 4,320,000 years. ] ], including ] and ], wrote essays on the nature of time.<ref>Dagobert Runes, ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', p. 318</ref>
In general, the Islamic and ] world-view regards time as ]<ref>{{cite book |last1=Rust |first1=Eric Charles |title=Religion, Revelation and Reason |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=AcSw6GDlLVwC |publisher=Mercer University Press |publication-date=1981 |page=60 |isbn=978-0-86554-058-3 |quote=Profane time, as ] points out, is linear. As man dwelt increasingly in the profane and a sense of history developed, the desire to escape into the sacred began to drop in the background. The myths, tied up with cyclic time, were not so easily operative. So secular man became content with his linear time. He could not return to cyclic time and re-enter sacred space though its myths. Just here, as Eliade sees it, a new religious structure became available. In the Judaeo-Christian religions – Judaism, Christianity, Islam – history is taken seriously, and linear time is accepted. The cyclic time of the primordial mythical consciousness has been transformed into the time of profane man, but the mythical consciousness remains. It has been historicized. The Christian mythos and its accompanying ritual are bound up, for example, with history and center in authentic history, especially the Christ-event. Sacred space, the Transcendent Presence, is thus opened up to secular man because it meets him where he is, in the linear flow of secular time. The Christian myth gives such time a beginning in creation, a center in the Christ-event, and an end in the final consummation. |year=1981 |access-date=20 August 2015 |archive-date=3 April 2017 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170403232350/https://books.google.com/books?id=AcSw6GDlLVwC |url-status=live }}</ref> and ],<ref>{{cite book |editor1-last=Betz |editor1-first=Hans Dieter |title=Religion Past & Present: Encyclopedia of Theology and Religion |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kjIOAQAAMAAJ |volume=4 |edition=4 |publisher=Brill |publication-date=2008 |page=101 |isbn=978-90-04-14688-4 |quote= God produces a creation with a directional time structure . |year=2008 |access-date=20 August 2015 |archive-date=24 September 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150924154435/https://books.google.com/books?id=kjIOAQAAMAAJ |url-status=live }}</ref> beginning with the act of ] by God. The traditional Christian view sees time ending, teleologically,<ref>{{cite book |last1=Lundin |first1=Roger |last2=Thiselton |first2=Anthony C. |author-link2=Anthony Thiselton |last3=Walhout |first3=Clarence |title=The Promise of Hermeneutics |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3Y2F6rSq9VMC |publisher=Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing |publication-date=1999 |page=121 |isbn=978-0-8028-4635-8 |quote=We need to note the close ties between teleology, eschatology, and utopia. In Christian theology, the understanding of the teleology of particular actions is ultimately related to the teleology of history in general, which is the concern of eschatology. |year=1999 |access-date=20 August 2015 |archive-date=19 September 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150919095555/https://books.google.com/books?id=3Y2F6rSq9VMC |url-status=live }}</ref> with the ] end of the present order of things, the "]".


In the ] book ], traditionally ascribed to ] (970–928 BC), time (as the Hebrew word עידן, זמן ''iddan (age, as in "Ice age") zĕman(time)'' is often translated) is a medium for the passage of ] events.{{citation needed|date=January 2015}} (Another word, زمان" זמן" ''zamān'', meant ''time fit for an event'', and is used as the modern ], ], and ] equivalent to the English word "time".)
In Book 11 of ] '']'', he ruminates on the nature of time, asking, "What then is time? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one that asketh, I know not." He settles on time being defined more by what it is not than what it is.<ref>St. Augustine, ''Confessions'', Book 11. http://ccat.sas.upenn.edu/jod/augustine/Pusey/book11 (Accessed 5/26/07).</ref>


==== Time in Greek mythology ====
In contrast to ancient Greek philosophers who believed that the universe had an infinite past with no beginning, ] and ] developed the concept of the universe having a finite past with a beginning. This view was inspired by the ] shared by the three ]: ], ] and ]. The ], ], presented the first such argument against the ancient Greek notion of an infinite past. However, the most sophisticated medieval arguments against an infinite past were developed by the ], ] (Alkindus); the ], ] (Saadia ben Joseph); and the ], ] (Algazel). They developed two logical arguments against an infinite past, the first being the "argument from the impossibility of the existence of an actual infinite", which states:<ref name=Craig>{{citation|title=Whitrow and Popper on the Impossibility of an Infinite Past|first=William Lane|last=Craig|authorlink = William Lane Craig|journal=The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science|volume=30|issue=2|date=June 1979|pages=165-170 }}</ref>
The Greek language denotes two distinct principles, ] and ]. The former refers to numeric, or chronological, time. The latter, literally "the right or opportune moment", relates specifically to metaphysical or Divine time. In theology, Kairos is qualitative, as opposed to quantitative.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0057%3Aentry%3Dkairo%2Fs1 |title=(Dictionary Entry) |work=Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon |access-date=13 July 2015 |archive-date=7 May 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220507073935/https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0057%3Aentry%3Dkairo%2Fs1 |url-status=live }}</ref>


In Greek mythology, Chronos (ancient Greek: Χρόνος) is identified as the Personification of Time. His name in Greek means "time" and is alternatively spelled Chronus (Latin spelling) or Khronos. Chronos is usually portrayed as an old, wise man with a long, gray beard, such as "Father Time". Some English words whose etymological root is khronos/chronos include ''chronology'', ''chronometer'', ''chronic'', '']'', ''synchronise'', and ''chronicle''.
:"An actual infinite cannot exist."
:"An infinite temporal regress of events is an actual infinite."
:"{{Unicode|∴}} An infinite temporal regress of events cannot exist."


==== Time in Kabbalah & Rabbinical thought====
The second argument, the "argument from the impossibility of completing an actual infinite by successive addition", states:<ref name=Craig/>
Rabbis sometimes saw time like "an accordion that was expanded and collapsed at will."
<ref>New Myths and Meanings in Jewish New Moon Rituals
David M. Rosen, Victoria P. Rosen
Ethnology, Vol. 39, No. 3 (Summer, 2000), pp. 263–277
(referencing Yerushalmi 1989)
</ref> According to ], "time" is a ]<ref>{{cite book |title=Kabbalah and Modernity: Interpretations, Transformations, Adaptations |first1=Boʿaz |last1=Hus |first2=Marco |last2=Pasi |first3=Kocku von |last3=Stuckrad |author3-link=Kocku von Stuckrad |publisher=BRILL |date=2011 |isbn=978-90-04-18284-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mIGMsLiol7EC |access-date=27 February 2016 |archive-date=13 May 2016 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160513114415/https://books.google.com/books?id=mIGMsLiol7EC |url-status=live }}</ref> and an ].<ref>{{cite book |title=Alef, Mem, Tau: Kabbalistic Musings on Time, Truth, and Death |first1=Elliot R. |last1=Wolfson |publisher=University of California Press |date=2006 |isbn=978-0-520-93231-9 |page=111 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ozhPY2fcNCcC |access-date=7 May 2020 |archive-date=19 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200819171639/https://books.google.com/books?id=ozhPY2fcNCcC |url-status=live }} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220511191004/https://books.google.com/books?id=ozhPY2fcNCcC&pg=PA111 |date=11 May 2022 }}</ref>


==== Time in Advaita Vedanta ====
:"An actual infinite cannot be completed by successive addition."
According to ], time is integral to the phenomenal world, which lacks independent reality. Time and the phenomenal world are products of ], influenced by our senses, concepts, and imaginations. The phenomenal world, including time, is seen as impermanent and characterized by plurality, suffering, conflict, and division. Since phenomenal existence is dominated by temporality ('']''), everything within time is subject to change and decay. Overcoming pain and death requires knowledge that transcends temporal existence and reveals its eternal foundation.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Puligandla |first=R. |date=1974 |title=Time and History in the Indian Tradition |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/1398019 |journal=Philosophy East and West |volume=24 |issue=2 |pages=165–170 |doi=10.2307/1398019 |jstor=1398019 |issn=0031-8221}}</ref>
:"The temporal series of past events has been completed by successive addition."
:"{{Unicode|∴}} The temporal series of past events cannot be an actual infinite."


=== In Western philosophy ===
Both arguments were adopted by later Christian philosophers and theologians, and the second argument in particular became more famous after it was adopted by ] in his thesis of the first antimony concerning time.<ref name=Craig/>
{{Main|Philosophy of space and time|Temporal finitism}}
].]]


Two contrasting viewpoints on time divide prominent philosophers. One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the ]&nbsp;– a ] independent of events, in which events occur in ]. ] subscribed to this ] view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as ].<ref name="Rynasiewicz">
] believed time and ] form a container for events, which is as real as the ]s it contains.
{{cite encyclopedia |title=Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion |encyclopedia=] |publisher=Stanford University |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/newton-stm/ |access-date=5 February 2012 |last=Rynasiewicz |first=Robert: Johns Hopkins University |date=12 August 2004 |archive-url=https://archive.today/20120716191122/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/newton-stm/ |archive-date=16 July 2012 |quote=Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence&nbsp;... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation to anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year). |url-status=live}}
{{quotation|Absolute, true, and mathematical time, in and of itself and of its own nature, without reference to anything external, flows uniformly and by another name is called duration. Relative, apparent, and common time is any sensible and external measure (precise or imprecise) of duration by means of motion; such a measure – for example, an hour, a day, a month, a year – is commonly used instead of true time.|''Principia''<ref name="newton">{{cite book | last = Newton | first = Isaac | authorlink = Isaac Newton | title = The Principia, 3rd edition | year = 1726}} Translated by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1999.</ref>}}
</ref><ref name=Markosian >{{cite encyclopedia |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time/#3 |last=Markosian |first=Ned |author-link=Ned Markosian |title=Time |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition) |editor=Edward N. Zalta |quote=The opposing view, normally referred to either as "Platonism with Respect to Time" or as "Absolutism with Respect to Time", has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it. |access-date=23 September 2011 |archive-date=14 September 2006 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20060914153738/http://plato.stanford.edu//entries/time/#3 |url-status=live }}</ref>


The opposing view is that ''time'' does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with ] and number) within which humans sequence and compare events. This second view, in the tradition of ]<ref name="Burnham">
In contrast to Newton's belief in absolute space, and a precursor to Kantian time, ] believed that time and space are relational.<ref>Gottfried Martin, ''Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science''</ref> The differences between Leibniz's and Newton's interpretations came to a head in the famous ]. Leibniz thought of time as a fundamental part of an ] conceptual framework, together with ] and ], within which we sequence events, ] their duration, and compare the motions of objects. In this view, ''time'' does not refer to any kind of entity that "flows," that objects "move through," or that is a "container" for events.
{{cite encyclopedia |title=Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) Metaphysics&nbsp;– 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles |encyclopedia=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H7 |access-date=9 April 2011 |last=Burnham |first=Douglas: Staffordshire University |date=2006 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110514000548/http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H7 |archive-date=14 May 2011 |quote=First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time. |url-status=live}}
</ref> and ],<ref name="Mattey">
{{cite web |last=Mattey |first=G. J. |date=22 January 1997 |title=Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis |url=http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIMELEC.HTM |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20050314201600/http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIMELEC.HTM |archive-date=14 March 2005 |access-date=9 April 2011 |quote=What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded ... "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, ''mutatis mutandis'', to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition."}}
</ref><ref name="McCormick">
{{cite encyclopedia |title=Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) Metaphysics: 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta/#H4 |encyclopedia=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |first=Matt |last=McCormick |date=2006 |quote=Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the ''a priori'' contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues. |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110426002607/http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta/#H4 |archive-date=26 April 2011 }}
</ref> holds that ''time'' is neither an event nor a thing, and thus is not itself measurable nor can it be travelled.


Furthermore, it may be that there is a ] component to time, but whether or not time itself is "felt", as a sensation, or is a judgment, is a matter of debate.<ref name=DefRefs02>* {{cite web |url=http://www.yourdictionary.com/time |title=Webster's New World College Dictionary |date=2010 |quote=1.indefinite, unlimited duration in which things are considered as happening in the past, present, or future; every moment there has ever been or ever will be… a system of measuring duration 2.the period between two events or during which something exists, happens, or acts; measured or measurable interval |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110805101704/http://www.yourdictionary.com/time |archive-date=5 August 2011 }}
], in the '']'', described time as an '']'' intuition that allows us (together with the other ''a priori'' intuition, ]) to comprehend sense experience.<ref name="kant"> {{cite book | last = Kant | first = Immanuel | authorlink = Immanuel Kant | title = The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition | year = 1787}} translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn, eBooks@Adelaide, 2004—http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/k16p15.html</ref> With Kant, neither space nor time are conceived as ]s, but rather both are elements of a systematic mental ] that necessarily structures the experiences of any rational agent, or observing subject. Spatial ]s are used to ] how far apart ]s are, and temporal measurements are used to quantify how far apart ]s occur.
* {{cite web |url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary |date=2002 |quote=A duration or relation of events expressed in terms of past, present, and future, and measured in units such as minutes, hours, days, months, or years. |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120305015803/http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |archive-date=5 March 2012 }}
* {{cite web |url=http://www.collinslanguage.com/results.aspx?context=3&reversed=False&action=define&homonym=-1&text=time |title=Collins Language.com |publisher=HarperCollins |date=2011 |quote=1. The continuous passage of existence in which events pass from a state of potentiality in the future, through the present, to a state of finality in the past. 2. ''physics'' a quantity measuring duration, usually with reference to a periodic process such as the rotation of the earth or the frequency of electromagnetic radiation emitted from certain atoms. In classical mechanics, time is absolute in the sense that the time of an event is independent of the observer. According to the theory of relativity it depends on the observer's frame of reference. Time is considered as a fourth coordinate required, along with three spatial coordinates, to specify an event. |access-date=18 December 2011 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111002190630/http://www.collinslanguage.com/results.aspx?context=3&reversed=False&action=define&homonym=-1&text=time |archive-date=2 October 2011 }}
* {{cite web |url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=The American Heritage Science Dictionary @dictionary.com |date=2002 |quote=1. A continuous, measurable quantity in which events occur in a sequence proceeding from the past through the present to the future. 2a. An interval separating two points of this quantity; a duration. 2b. A system or reference frame in which such intervals are measured or such quantities are calculated. |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120305015803/http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |archive-date=5 March 2012 }}
* {{cite web |url=http://scienceworld.wolfram.com/physics/Time.html |title=Eric Weisstein's World of Science |date=2007 |quote=A quantity used to specify the order in which events occurred and measure the amount by which one event preceded or followed another. In special relativity, ct (where c is the speed of light and t is time), plays the role of a fourth dimension. |access-date=9 April 2011 |archive-date=29 November 2017 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171129190443/http://scienceworld.wolfram.com/physics/Time.html |url-status=live }}</ref><ref name=DefRefs01>* {{cite web |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/time/ |title=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=2010 |quote=Time is what clocks measure. We use time to place events in sequence one after the other, and we use time to compare how long events last... Among philosophers of physics, the most popular short answer to the question "What is physical time?" is that it is not a substance or object but rather a special system of relations among instantaneous events. This working definition is offered by Adolf Grünbaum who applies the contemporary mathematical theory of continuity to physical processes, and he says time is a linear continuum of instants and is a distinguished one-dimensional sub-space of four-dimensional spacetime. |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110411140140/http://www.iep.utm.edu/time/ |archive-date=11 April 2011 }}
* {{cite web |url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary |date=2010 |quote=1. the system of those sequential relations that any event has to any other, as past, present, or future; indefinite and continuous duration regarded as that in which events succeed one another.... 3. (sometimes initial capital letter) a system or method of measuring or reckoning the passage of time: mean time; apparent time; Greenwich Time. 4. a limited period or interval, as between two successive events: a long time.... 14. a particular or definite point in time, as indicated by a clock: What time is it? ... 18. an indefinite, frequently prolonged period or duration in the future: Time will tell if what we have done here today was right. |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120305015803/http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |archive-date=5 March 2012 }}
* {{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=HrHvAAAAMAAJ&q=%22time+is+what+clocks+measure%22 |title=Physics |first1=Donald G. |last1=Ivey |first2=J.N.P. |last2=Hume |volume=1 |page=65 |date=1974 |publisher=Ronald Press |quote=Our operational definition of time is that time is what clocks measure. |access-date=7 May 2020 |archive-date=14 April 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210414052527/https://books.google.com/books?id=HrHvAAAAMAAJ&q=%22time+is+what+clocks+measure%22 |url-status=live }}</ref><ref name=Poidevin>{{cite encyclopedia |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience |title=The Experience and Perception of Time |last=Le Poidevin |first=Robin |date=Winter 2004 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor=Edward N. Zalta |access-date=9 April 2011 |archive-date=22 October 2013 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131022013501/http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience/ |url-status=live }}</ref><ref>
{{cite book |last=Carrol|first= Sean |chapter=Chapter One, Section Two, Plume |title=From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time |title-link=From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time |isbn=978-0-452-29654-1 |quote=As human beings we 'feel' the passage of time.|year=2010 |publisher=Penguin }}
</ref><ref name=lehar>
Lehar, Steve. (2000). {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151021061139/http://cns-alumni.bu.edu/~slehar/webstuff/consc1/consc1.html |date=21 October 2015 }}, ''Consciousness and Cognition''.
</ref>


In Philosophy, time was questioned throughout the centuries; what time is and if it is real or not. Ancient Greek philosophers asked if time was linear or cyclical and if time was endless or ].<ref name="Philosophy of Time">{{Cite web|url=http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/|title=Philosophy of Time – Exactly What Is Time?|access-date=2019-03-28|archive-date=28 March 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190328174952/http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/|url-status=live}}</ref> These philosophers had different ways of explaining time; for instance, ancient Indian philosophers had something called the ] It is believed that there was repeating ages over the lifespan of the universe.<ref name="Ancient Philosophy">{{Cite web|url=http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/ancient-philosophy/|title=Ancient Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?|access-date=2019-03-28|archive-date=28 March 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190328174951/http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/ancient-philosophy/|url-status=live}}</ref> This led to beliefs like cycles of rebirth and ].<ref name="Ancient Philosophy" /> The Greek philosophers believe that the universe was infinite, and was an illusion to humans.<ref name="Ancient Philosophy" /> ] believed that time was made by the Creator at the same instant as the heavens.<ref name="Ancient Philosophy" /> He also says that time is a period of motion of the ].<ref name="Ancient Philosophy" /> ] believed that time correlated to movement, that time did not exist on its own but was relative to motion of objects.<ref name="Ancient Philosophy" /> He also believed that time was related to the motion of ]; the reason that humans can tell time was because of ] and therefore there was a duration on time.<ref name="Bunnag-2017">{{Cite journal|last=Bunnag|first=Anawat|date=August 2017|title=The concept of time in philosophy: A comparative study between Theravada Buddhist and Henri Bergson's concept of time from Thai philosophers' perspectives|url=https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S2452315117300140|journal=Kasetsart Journal of Social Sciences|doi=10.1016/j.kjss.2017.07.007|doi-access=free|access-date=11 April 2019|archive-date=2 April 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190402163654/https://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/S2452315117300140|url-status=live}}</ref>
In ], time is considered fundamental to the question of ],{{Fact|date=September 2007}} in particular by the philosopher ].{{Fact|date=September 2007}} (See ]).


The '']'', the earliest texts on ] and ] dating to the late ], describe ancient ], in which the ] goes through repeated cycles of creation, destruction and rebirth, with each cycle lasting 4,320&nbsp;million years.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Layton |first=Robert |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7TPIDL9RdsoC&pg=PA7 |title=Who Needs the Past?: Indigenous Values and Archaeology |date=1994 |publisher=Psychology Press |isbn=978-0-415-09558-7 |pages=7 |language=en}}</ref>
] believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as ''Duration''. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.<ref>Bergson, Henri (1907) ''Creative Evolution''. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998.</ref>
] ], including ] and ], wrote essays on the nature of time.<ref>Dagobert Runes, ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', p. 318.
</ref>
], in the ], identified time with the period of motion of the heavenly bodies. ], in Book IV of his ] defined time as 'number of movement in respect of the before and after'.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Hardie |first1=R. P. |last2=Gaye |first2=R. K. |title=Physics by Aristotle |url=http://classics.mit.edu//Aristotle/physics.4.iv.html |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140626030252/http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/physics.4.iv.html |archive-date=26 June 2014 |access-date=4 May 2014 |publisher=Massachusetts Institute of Technology}} "''Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is used in two senses – both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of what is continuous.''"</ref>


In Book 11 of his '']'', ] ruminates on the nature of time, asking, "What then is time? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one that asketh, I know not." He begins to define time by what it is not rather than what it is,<ref>
===Time as "unreal"===
{{cite book |url=http://en.wikisource.org/Nicene_and_Post-Nicene_Fathers:_Series_I/Volume_I/Confessions/Book_XI/Chapter_14 |author-link=Augustine of Hippo |author=Augustine of Hippo |title=Confessions |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120119043221/http://en.wikisource.org/Nicene_and_Post-Nicene_Fathers:_Series_I/Volume_I/Confessions/Book_XI/Chapter_14 |archive-date=19 January 2012 }} Book 11, Chapter 14.
In 5th century BC ], ] the ], in a fragment preserved from his chief work ''On Truth'' held that: ''"Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)."''
</ref> an approach similar to that taken in other ]. However, Augustine ends up calling time a "distention" of the mind (Confessions 11.26) by which we simultaneously grasp the past in memory, the present by attention, and the future by expectation.
] went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the ] of his follower ].<ref>{{cite web|author=Harry Foundalis|title=You are about to disappear|url=http://www.foundalis.com/phi/WhyTimeFlows.htm|accessdate=2007-04-27}}</ref>
Time as illusion is also a common theme in ] thought,<ref>{{cite web|title=Buddhism and the illusion of time|url=http://www.buddhistinformation.com/buddhism_and_the_illusion_of_time.htm|accessdate=2007-04-27|author=Tom Huston}}</ref> and some modern philosophers have carried on with this theme. ]'s 1908 '']'', for example, argues that time is unreal (see also ]).


] believed in absolute space and absolute time; Leibniz believed that time and space are relational.<ref>Gottfried Martin, ''Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science.''
However, these arguments often center around what it means for something to be "real". Modern physicists generally consider time to be as "real" as space, though others such as ] in his '']'' argue that quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless ]realm containing every possible "Now" or momentary configuration of the universe, which he terms 'platonia'.<ref>{{cite web|title=Time is an illusion?|url=http://physicsandphysicists.blogspot.com/2007/03/time-is-illusion.html|accessdate=2007-04-27}}</ref> (See also: ].)
</ref>
The differences between Leibniz's and Newton's interpretations came to a head in the famous ].


Philosophers in the 17th and 18th century questioned if time was real and absolute, or if it was an intellectual concept that humans use to understand and sequence events.<ref name="Philosophy of Time"/> These questions lead to realism vs anti-realism; the realists believed that time is a fundamental part of the universe, and be perceived by events happening in a sequence, in a dimension.<ref name="Early Modern Philosophy">{{Cite web|url=http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/early-modern-philosophy/|title=Early Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?|access-date=2019-03-28|archive-date=28 March 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190328174950/http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/early-modern-philosophy/|url-status=live}}</ref> ] said that we are merely occupying time, he also says that humans can only understand ].<ref name="Early Modern Philosophy" /> Relative time is a measurement of objects in motion.<ref name="Early Modern Philosophy" /> The anti-realists believed that time is merely a convenient intellectual concept for humans to understand events.<ref name="Early Modern Philosophy" /> This means that time was useless unless there were objects that it could interact with, this was called ].<ref name="Early Modern Philosophy" /> ], ], and ] said that one's mind needs to acknowledge time, in order to understand what time is.<ref name="Bunnag-2017"/> ] believed that we can not know what something is unless we experience it first hand.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.iep.utm.edu/kantview/|title=Immanuel Kant|last=Jankowiak|first=Tim|access-date=2019-04-02|archive-date=23 May 2021|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210523180236/https://iep.utm.edu/kantview/|url-status=live}}</ref>
==Physical definition==
{{main|Time in physics}}
From the age of ] up until ] profound reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space, time was considered to be "absolute" and to flow "equably" (to use the words of Newton) for all observers.<ref>Herman M. Schwartz, ''Introduction to Special Relativity'', McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1968, hardcover 442 pages, see ISBN 0882754785 (1977 edition), pp. 10-13</ref> The science of classical mechanics is based on this Newtonian idea of time.


{{Quote box
Einstein, in his ],<ref>A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, H. Minkowski, ''The Principle of Relativity'', Dover Publications, Inc, 2000, softcover 216 pages, ISBN 0486600815, See pp. 37-65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper.</ref> postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer.
|quote=Time is not an empirical concept. For neither co-existence nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did not exist as a foundation ''a priori''. Without this presupposition, we could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in succession.
|source=], '']'' (1781), trans. ] (London: Dent., 1991), p. 54.
|align=right
|width=35%
|quoted=1
}}
], in the '']'', described time as an '']'' intuition that allows us (together with the other ''a priori'' intuition, space) to comprehend ].<ref name="kant">
{{cite book |last=Kant |first=Immanuel |author-link=Immanuel Kant |url=https://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/complete.html |title=The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition |date=1787 |access-date=9 April 2011 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110413222609/http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/ |archive-date=13 April 2011 |url-status=dead}} translated by ], eBooks@Adelaide, 2004
</ref>
With Kant, neither space nor time are conceived as ], but rather both are elements of a systematic mental framework that necessarily structures the experiences of any rational agent, or observing subject. Kant thought of time as a fundamental part of an ] conceptual framework, together with space and number, within which we sequence events, ] their duration, and compare the motions of objects. In this view, ''time'' does not refer to any kind of entity that "flows," that objects "move through," or that is a "container" for events. Spatial ]s are used to ] the extent of and distances between ], and temporal measurements are used to quantify the durations of and between ]. Time was designated by Kant as the purest possible ] of a pure concept or category.

] believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as '']''. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.<ref>Bergson, Henri (1907) ''Creative Evolution''. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998.
</ref>

According to ] we do not exist inside time, we ''are'' time. Hence, the relationship to the past is a present awareness of ''having been'', which allows the past to exist in the present. The relationship to the future is the state of anticipating a potential possibility, task, or engagement. It is related to the human propensity for caring and being concerned, which causes "being ahead of oneself" when thinking of a pending occurrence. Therefore, this concern for a potential occurrence also allows the future to exist in the present. The present becomes an experience, which is qualitative instead of quantitative. Heidegger seems to think this is the way that a linear relationship with time, or temporal existence, is broken or transcended.<ref name=Balslev>{{Cite book |last=Balslev |first=Anindita N. |author2=Jitendranath Mohanty |title=Religion and Time |publisher=Brill Academic Publishers |series=Studies in the History of Religions, 54. |date=November 1992 |location=The Netherlands |pages=53–59 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y94cKeEVa3sC |isbn=978-90-04-09583-0 |access-date=30 July 2019 |archive-date=20 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200820024824/https://books.google.com/books?id=y94cKeEVa3sC |url-status=live }}</ref>
We are not stuck in sequential time. We are able to remember the past and project into the future&nbsp;– we have a kind of random access to our representation of temporal existence; we can, in our thoughts, step out of (ecstasis) sequential time.<ref>{{cite book |author=Heidegger |first=Martin |title=Being and Time |date=1962 |publisher=Blackwell |isbn=978-0-631-19770-6 |page=425 |chapter=V |access-date=30 July 2019 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=S57m5gW0L-MC&pg=PA425 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200819212325/https://books.google.com/books?id=S57m5gW0L-MC&pg=PA425 |archive-date=19 August 2020 |url-status=live}}</ref>

Modern era philosophers asked: is time real or unreal, is time happening all at once or a duration, is time tensed or tenseless, and is there a future to be?<ref name="Philosophy of Time"/> There is a theory called the tenseless or ]; this theory says that any tensed terminology can be replaced with tenseless terminology.<ref name="Modern Philosophy">{{Cite web|url=http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/modern-philosophy/|title=Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?|access-date=2019-03-28|archive-date=28 March 2019|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190328175027/http://www.exactlywhatistime.com/philosophy-of-time/modern-philosophy/|url-status=live}}</ref> For example, "we will win the game" can be replaced with "we do win the game", taking out the future tense. On the other hand, there is a theory called the tense or ]; this theory says that our language has tense verbs for a reason and that the future can not be determined.<ref name="Modern Philosophy" /> There is also something called imaginary time, this was from ], who said that space and imaginary time are finite but have no boundaries.<ref name="Modern Philosophy" /> ] is not real or unreal, it is something that is hard to visualize.<ref name="Modern Philosophy" /> Philosophers can agree that physical time exists outside of the human mind and is objective, and psychological time is mind-dependent and subjective.<ref name="Bunnag-2017"/>

=== Unreality ===
In 5th century BC ], ] the ], in a fragment preserved from his chief work ''On Truth'', held that: "Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)." ] went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the ] of his follower ].<ref>{{cite web |author=Foundalis |first=Harry |title=You are about to disappear |url=http://www.foundalis.com/phi/WhyTimeFlows.htm |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110512072013/http://www.foundalis.com/phi/WhyTimeFlows.htm |archive-date=12 May 2011 |access-date=9 April 2011}}</ref> Time as an illusion is also a common theme in ] thought.<ref>{{cite web |title=Buddhism and the illusion of time |url=http://www.buddhasvillage.com/teachings/time.htm |first=Tom |last=Huston |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110708103214/http://www.buddhasvillage.com/teachings/time.htm |archive-date=8 July 2011 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kfsyfoO1IlYC&pg=RA1-PR19 |last=Garfield |first=Jay L. |title=The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā |date=1995 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=New York |isbn=978-0-19-509336-0 |access-date=19 May 2018 |archive-date=19 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200819134845/https://books.google.com/books?id=kfsyfoO1IlYC&pg=RA1-PR19 |url-status=live }}</ref>

]'s 1908 '']'' argues that, since every event has the characteristic of being both present and not present (i.e., future or past), that time is a self-contradictory idea (see also ]).{{cn|date=January 2024}}

These arguments often center on what it means for something to be ''unreal''. Modern physicists generally believe that time is as ''real'' as space&nbsp;– though others, such as ], argue quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless ] containing every possible ''now'' or momentary configuration of the universe.{{cn|date=January 2024}}

A modern philosophical theory called ] views the past and the future as human-mind interpretations of movement instead of real parts of time (or "dimensions") which coexist with the present. This theory rejects the existence of all direct interaction with the past or the future, holding only the present as tangible. This is one of the philosophical arguments against time travel. This contrasts with ] (all time: present, past and future, is real) and the ] (the present and the past are real, but the future is not).{{cn|date=January 2024}}


== Physical definition ==
] showed that if time and space is measured using electromagnetic phenomena (like light bouncing between mirrors) then due to the constancy of the speed of light, time and space become mathematically entangled together in a certain way (called ] ]) which in turn results in ] and in entanglement of all other important derivative physical quantities (like energy, momentum, mass, force, etc) in a certain 4-vectorial way (see ] for more details).
{{Classical mechanics|cTopic=Fundamental concepts}} {{Classical mechanics|cTopic=Fundamental concepts}}
{{Main|Time in physics}}


Until ] reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space in 1907, time was considered to be the same everywhere in the universe, with all observers measuring the same time interval for any event.<ref>Herman M. Schwartz, ''Introduction to Special Relativity'', McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1968, hardcover 442 pages, see {{isbn|0-88275-478-5}} (1977 edition), pp. 10–13
===Classical mechanics===
</ref> Non-relativistic ] is based on this Newtonian idea of time.
In ] Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works pretty well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience.


Einstein, in his ],<ref>A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, H. Minkowski, ''The Principle of Relativity'', Dover Publications, Inc, 2000, softcover, 216 pages, {{isbn|0-486-60081-5}}, See pp. 37–65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper.
===Modern physics===
</ref> postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer.
In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. Einstein resolved these problems by invoking a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the result that time appears to elapse at different rates relative to different observers in motion relative to one another.
{{clear}}
]. The past and future ]s are absolute, the "present" is a relative concept different for observers in relative motion.]]


The theory of special relativity finds a convenient formulation in ]time, a mathematical structure that combines three dimensions of space with a single dimension of time. In this formalism, distances in space can be measured by how long light takes to travel that distance, e.g., a ] is a measure of distance, and a meter is now defined in terms of how far light travels in a certain amount of time. Two ] in Minkowski spacetime are separated by an '']'', which can be either ], ], or ]. Events that have a time-like separation cannot be simultaneous in any ], there must be a temporal component (and possibly a spatial one) to their separation. Events that have a space-like separation will be simultaneous in some frame of reference, and there is no frame of reference in which they do not have a spatial separation. Different observers may calculate different distances and different time intervals between two events, but the ''invariant interval'' between the events is independent of the observer (and his or her velocity).
===Spacetime===
{{main|Spacetime}}
Modern ] views the curvature of ] around an object as much a feature of that object as are its ] and ].{{Fact|date=February 2008}}


=== Arrow of time ===
Time has historically been closely related with ], the two together comprising ] in ] ] and ]. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the ], and the human perception as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks are different for observers in relative motion.{{Fact|date=February 2008}} Even the temporal order of events can change, but the past and future are defined by the backward and forward ]s, which never change.{{Fact|date=February 2008}} The ] is the set of events that can send light signals to the observer, the ] the events to which the observer can send light signals. All else is non-observable and within that set of events the very time-order differs for different observers.{{Fact|date=February 2008}}
{{Main|Arrow of time}}


Unlike space, where an object can travel in the opposite directions (and in 3 dimensions), time appears to have only one dimension and only one direction&nbsp;– the past lies behind, fixed and immutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet most laws of physics allow any process to proceed both forward and in reverse. There are only a few physical phenomena, that violate the reversibility of time. This time directionality is known as the ]. Acknowledged examples of the arrow of time are:<ref> Quantum causality and the arrows of time and thermodynamics. 2020. Prog Part Nucl Phys. 115/13. J.F. Donoghue, G. Menezes. doi: 10.1016/j.ppnp.2020.103812.</ref><ref>The Direction of Time. 2015. Time: A Philosophical Introduction. pp. 191–214. J. Harrington, J. Harrington.</ref><ref>Time irreversibility in active matter, from micro to macro. 2022. Nat Rev Phys. 4/3, pp. 167–183.</ref><ref> J. O'byrne, Y. Kafri, J. Tailleur, F. Van Wijland. doi: 10.1038/s42254-021-00406-2.</ref><ref>The Nature and Origin of Time-Asymmetric Spacetime Structures. 2014. Springer Handbook of Spacetime. pp. 185–196. H.D. Zeh.</ref><ref>The Arrow of Time. 2016. Cosmological and Psychological Time. 285/155-62. M. Hemmo, O. Shenker. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-22590-6_9.</ref><ref>Relativity Theory May not Have the Last Word on the Nature of Time: Quantum Theory and Probabilism. 2017. Space, Time and the Limits of Human Understanding. pp. 109214. N. Maxwell. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-44418-5_9.</ref><ref>Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 2013. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. pp. 1–357. doi: 10.1017/cbo9781139225700.</ref>
===Time dilation===
# Radiative arrow of time, manifested in waves (e.g. light and sound) travelling only expanding (rather than focusing) in time (see ]);
]: Event B is simultaneous with A in the green reference frame, but it occurred
# ]: according to the ] an isolated system evolves toward a larger disorder rather than orders spontaneously;
before in the blue frame, and will occur later in the red frame.]]
# Quantum arrow time, which is related to irreversibility of ] according to the ] of ];
{{main|Time dilation}}
# Weak arrow of time: preference for a certain time direction of ] in ] (see ]);
"Time is nature's way of keeping everything from happening at once". This quote, attributed variously to ], ], and ], says that time is what separates ]. Einstein showed that people travelling at different speeds, whilst agreeing on cause and effect, will measure different time separations between events and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are minute unless one is travelling at a speed close to that of light, the effect becomes pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. Many ]s exist for only a fixed fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but some that travel close to the speed of light can be measured to travel further and survive much longer than expected (a ] is one example). According to the ], in the high-speed particle's ], it exists, on the average, for a standard amount of time known as its ], and the distance it travels in that time is zero, because its velocity is zero. Relative to a frame of reference at rest, time seems to "slow down" for the particle. Relative to the high-speed particle, distances seems to shorten. Even in Newtonian terms time may be considered the fourth dimension of motion; but Einstein showed how both temporal and spatial dimensions can be altered (or "warped") by high-speed motion.
# ] arrow of time, which follows the accelerated ] after the ].


The relationship(s) between these different Arrows of Time is a hotly debated topic in ].<ref>Peter Coveney and Roger Highfield. ''The Arrow of Time : A Voyage Through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery.'' Hardcover – May 14, 1991. https://www.publishersweekly.com/9780449906309 </ref>
Einstein (''The Meaning of Relativity''): "Two ]s taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relatively to K, which register the same simultaneously."


=== Classical mechanics ===
Einstein wrote in his book, ''Relativity'', that ], i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference.
In non-relativistic ], Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works sufficiently well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience. In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. Einstein resolved these problems by invoking a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the conclusion that observers in motion relative to one another measure different elapsed times for the same event.


]s are absolute, the "present" is a relative concept different for observers in relative motion.]]
===Relativistic time versus Newtonian time===


=== Spacetime ===
] of a rapidly accelerating observer in a Newtonian universe. The events ("dots") that pass the horizontal line are the events current to the observer.]]
{{Main|Spacetime}}
Time has historically been closely related with space, the two together merging into spacetime in ] ] and ]. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the ], and the human perception, as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks, are different for observers in relative motion. For example, if a spaceship carrying a clock flies through space at (very nearly) the speed of light, its crew does not notice a change in the speed of time on board their vessel because everything traveling at the same speed slows down at the same rate (including the clock, the crew's thought processes, and the functions of their bodies). However, to a stationary observer watching the spaceship fly by, the spaceship appears flattened in the direction it is traveling and the clock on board the spaceship appears to move very slowly.


On the other hand, the crew on board the spaceship also perceives the observer as slowed down and flattened along the spaceship's direction of travel, because both are moving at very nearly the speed of light relative to each other. Because the outside universe appears flattened to the spaceship, the crew perceives themselves as quickly traveling between regions of space that (to the stationary observer) are many light years apart. This is reconciled by the fact that the crew's perception of time is different from the stationary observer's; what seems like seconds to the crew might be hundreds of years to the stationary observer. In either case, however, causality remains unchanged: the ] is the set of events that can send light signals to an entity and the ] is the set of events to which an entity can send light signals.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ev9zrt__lec |title=Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity |publisher=YouTube |date=30 November 2011 |access-date=24 September 2013 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131017182611/http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ev9zrt__lec |archive-date=17 October 2013 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V7vpw4AH8QQ |title=Time Travel: Einstein's big idea (Theory of Relativity) |publisher=YouTube |date=9 January 2007 |access-date=24 September 2013 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131017182714/http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V7vpw4AH8QQ |archive-date=17 October 2013 }}</ref>
] of a rapidly accelerating observer in a relativistic universe. The events ("dots") that pass the two diagonal lines in the bottom half of the image (the past ] of the observer in the origin) are the events visible to the observer.]]


=== Dilation ===
The animations on the left and the right visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At heart of these differences are the ] and ]s applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively.
{{Main|Time dilation}}
]: Event B is simultaneous with A in the green reference frame, but it occurred before in the blue frame, and occurs later in the red frame.]]


] showed in his thought experiments that people travelling at different speeds, while agreeing on ], measure different time separations between events, and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are typically minute in the human experience, the effect becomes much more pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. ]s exist for a well-known average fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but when travelling close to the speed of light they are measured to travel farther and exist for much longer than when at rest. According to the ], in the high-speed particle's ], it exists, on the average, for a standard amount of time known as its ], and the distance it travels in that time is zero, because its velocity is zero. Relative to a frame of reference at rest, time seems to "slow down" for the particle. Relative to the high-speed particle, distances seem to shorten. Einstein showed how both temporal and spatial dimensions can be altered (or "warped") by high-speed motion.
In both figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the ] trajectory ("]") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime.


Einstein ('']''): "Two ] taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relative to K, which register the same simultaneously."
The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer. Note how in both pictures the view of spacetime changes when the observer accelerates.


Einstein wrote in his book, ''Relativity'', that ], i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference.
In the Newtonian description these changes are such that ''time'' is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e. whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer).


=== Relativistic versus Newtonian ===
However, in the relativistic description the ''observability of events'' is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "]" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of ''absolute time'' is no longer applicable: events move up-and-down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer.
] of a rapidly accelerating observer in a relativistic universe. The events ("dots") that pass the two diagonal lines in the bottom half of the image (the past ] of the observer in the origin) are the events visible to the observer.]]


The animations visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At the heart of these differences are the ] and ]s applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively.
===Arrow of time===
{{main|Arrow of time}}
Time appears to have a direction – the past lies behind, fixed and incommutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet the majority of the laws of physics don't provide this ]. The exceptions include the ], which states that ] must increase over time (see ]); the ] arrow of time, which points away from the ], and the radiative arrow of time, caused by ] only traveling forwards in time. In ], there is also the weak arrow of time, from ], and also ] in ] (see ]).


In the figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the spacetime trajectory ("]") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime.
===Quantised time===
{{seealso|Chronon}}
Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories (the ] of Particles and Interactions and ]) time is not quantized.


The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer. In both pictures the view of spacetime changes when the observer accelerates.
] (~ ] seconds) is the unit of time in the system of ] known as ]. Current established physical theories are believed to fail at this time scale, and many physicists expect that the Planck time might be the smallest unit of time that could ever be measured, even in principle. Tentative physical theories that describe this time scale exist; see for instance ].


In the Newtonian description these changes are such that ''time'' is absolute:<ref>{{Cite book |last1=Knudsen |first1=Jens M. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=rkP1CAAAQBAJ&pg=PA30 |title=Elements of Newtonian Mechanics |last2=Hjorth |first2=Poul G. |date=2012-12-06 |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |isbn=978-3-642-97599-8 |page=30 |language=en}}</ref> the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e., whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer).
==Time and the Big Bang==
] in particular has addressed a connection between time and the ]. In '']'' and elsewhere, Hawking says that even if time did not begin with the Big Bang and there were another time frame before the Big Bang, no information from events then would be accessible to us, and nothing that happened then would have any effect upon the present time-frame.<ref name=BOT-lecture-B>{{cite web
|url=http://www.hawking.org.uk/lectures/bot.html
|title=The Beginning of Time
|publisher=University of Cambridge
|first=Stephen
|last=Hawking
|quote=Since events before the Big Bang have no observational consequences, one may as well cut them out of the theory, and say that time began at the Big Bang. Events before the Big Bang, are simply not defined, because there's no way one could measure what happened at them. This kind of beginning to the universe, and of time itself, is very different to the beginnings that had been considered earlier.
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}}</ref> Upon occasion, Hawking has stated that time actually began with the Big Bang, and that questions about what happened ''before'' the Big Bang are ''meaningless''.<ref name=BOT-lecture>{{cite web
|url=http://www.hawking.org.uk/lectures/bot.html
|title=The Beginning of Time
|publisher=University of Cambridge
|first=Stephen
|last=Hawking
|quote=The conclusion of this lecture is that the universe has not existed forever. Rather, the universe, and time itself, had a beginning in the Big Bang, about 15 billion years ago.
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}}</ref><ref>{{cite web
|url=http://www.admin.ox.ac.uk/po/news/2005-06/feb/27.shtml
|title=Professor Stephen Hawking lectures on the origin of the universe
|first=Stephen
|last=Hawking
|date=2006-02-27
|publisher=University of Oxford
|quote=Suppose the beginning of the universe was like the South Pole of the earth, with degrees of latitude playing the role of time. The universe would start as a point at the South Pole. As one moves north, the circles of constant latitude, representing the size of the universe, would expand. To ask what happened before the beginning of the universe would become a meaningless question because there is nothing south of the South Pole.'
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}}</ref><ref>{{cite web
|url=http://www.ghandchi.com/312-SpaceEng.htm
|title=Space and New Thinking
|first=Sam : Editor/Publisher
|last=Ghandchi
|date=2004-01-16
|quote=and as Stephen Hawking puts it, asking what was before Big Bang is like asking what is North of North Pole, a meaningless question.
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}}</ref> This less-nuanced, but commonly repeated formulation has received criticisms from philosophers such as ] philosopher ].<ref>{{cite web
|url=http://radicalacademy.com/adlertheology1.htm
|title=Natural Theology, Chance, and God
|first=Mortimer J., Ph.D.
|last=Adler
|quote=Hawking could have avoided the error of supposing that time had a beginning with the Big Bang if he had distinguished time as it is measured by physicists from time that is not measurable by physicists.... an error shared by many other great physicists in the twentieth century, the error of saying that what cannot be measured by physicists does not exist in reality.
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}} {{cite encyclopedia
|title=The Great Ideas Today
|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedia Britannica
|year=1992
}}</ref><ref>
{{cite web
|url=http://radicalacademy.com/adlertheology2.htm
|title=Natural Theology, Chance, and God
|first=Mortimer J., Ph.D.
|last=Adler
|quote=Where Einstein had said that what is not measurable by physicists is of no interest to them, Hawking flatly asserts that what is not measurable by physicists does not exist — has no reality whatsoever.<br>With respect to time, that amounts to the denial of psychological time which is not measurable by physicists, and also to everlasting time — time before the Big Bang — which physics cannot measure. Hawking does not know that both Aquinas and Kant had shown that we cannot rationally establish that time is either finite or infinite.
|accessdate=2008-01-10
}} {{cite encyclopedia
|title=The Great Ideas Today
|encyclopedia=Encyclopaedia Britannica
|year=1992
}}
</ref>


However, in the relativistic description the ''observability of events'' is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "]" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of ''absolute time'' is no longer applicable: events move up and down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer.
Scientists have come to some agreement on descriptions of events that happened 10<sup>−35</sup> seconds after the Big Bang, but generally agree that descriptions about what happened before one ] (5 × 10<sup>−44</sup> seconds) after the Big Bang will likely remain pure speculation.


=== Quantization ===
===Speculative physics beyond the Big Bang===
{{See also|Chronon}}
<!-- article is about TIME, not about the Big Bang. This section needs to go to ] article -->
] seen on the left. Image from ] press release, 2006.]]


Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories (the ] of Particles and Interactions and ]) time is not quantized.
While the Big Bang model is well established in cosmology, it is likely to be refined in the future. Little is known about the earliest moments of the universe's history. The ] require the existence of a singularity at the beginning of cosmic time. However, these theorems assume that ] is correct, but general relativity must break down before the universe reaches the ], and a correct treatment of ] may avoid the singularity.<ref>{{cite book | author=Hawking, Stephen; and Ellis, G. F. R. | title = The Large Scale Structure of Space-Time | location= Cambridge | publisher=Cambridge University Press | year=1973 |id = ISBN 0-521-09906-4}}</ref>


] (~ 5.4 × 10<sup>−44</sup> seconds) is the unit of time in the system of ] known as ]. Current established physical theories are believed to fail at this time scale, and many physicists expect that the Planck time might be the smallest unit of time that could ever be measured, even in principle. Tentative physical theories that describe this time scale exist; see for instance ].
There may also be parts of the universe well beyond what can be observed in principle. If inflation occurred this is likely, for exponential expansion would push large regions of space beyond our observable horizon.


=== Thermodynamics ===
Some proposals, each of which entails untested hypotheses, are:
The ] states that ] must increase over time (see ]). This can be in either direction – ] theorizes that, according to the equations, the change in entropy occurs symmetrically whether going forward or backward in time. So entropy tends to increase in either direction, and our current low-entropy universe is a statistical aberration, in a similar manner as tossing a coin often enough that eventually heads will result ten times in a row. However, this theory is not supported empirically in local experiment.<ref>{{cite book |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yZujlUD1oAAC |last=Greene |first=Brian |author-link=Brian Greene |title=The Fabric of the Cosmos |title-link=The Fabric of the Cosmos |chapter=Chapter 6: Chance and the Arrow |date=2005 |publisher=Penguin Books Limited |isbn=978-0-14-195995-5 |access-date=16 September 2017 |archive-date=20 August 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200820035526/https://books.google.com/books?id=yZujlUD1oAAC |url-status=live }}</ref>
* models including the ] in which the whole of space-time is finite; the Big Bang does represent the limit of time, but without the need for a singularity.<ref>{{cite journal | author=] and ] | title=Wave function of the universe | journal=Phys. Rev. D | volume=28 | pages=2960 | year=1983 | doi=10.1103/PhysRevD.28.2960}}</ref>
* ] models<ref>{{cite journal | author=Langlois, David | title=Brane cosmology: an introduction | year=2002 | id={{arxiv|archive=hep-th|id=0209261}} }}</ref> in which inflation is due to the movement of branes in ]; the pre-big bang model; the ] model, in which the Big Bang is the result of a collision between branes; and the ], a variant of the ekpyrotic model in which collisions occur periodically.<ref>{{cite journal | last=Linde | first=Andre | year=2002 | title=Inflationary Theory versus Ekpyrotic/Cyclic Scenario | id={{arxiv|archive=hep-th|id=0205259}} }}</ref><ref name="rebirth">{{cite news | url=http://www.space.com/scienceastronomy/060508_mm_cyclic_universe.html | title=Recycled Universe: Theory Could Solve Cosmic Mystery | publisher=] | date=] ] | accessdate=2007-07-03}}</ref><ref name="rebirth2">{{cite web | url=http://www.science.psu.edu/alert/Bojowald6-2007.htm | title=What Happened Before the Big Bang? | accessdate=2007-07-03}}</ref>
* ], in which inflation events start here and there in a random quantum-gravity foam, each leading to a ''bubble universe'' expanding from its own big bang.<ref>{{cite journal | author = A. Linde |title = Eternal chaotic inflation | journal = Mod. Phys. Lett. |volume = A1 |year =1986 | pages=81}}<br />{{cite journal | author = A. Linde |title = Eternally existing self-reproducing chaotic inflationary universe | journal = Phys. Lett. |volume = B175 |year =1986|pages=395&ndash;400}}</ref>


== Travel ==
Proposals in the last two categories see the Big Bang as an event in a much larger and older universe, or ], and not the literal beginning.
{{Main|Time travel}}
{{See also|Time travel in fiction|Wormhole|Twin paradox}}


Time travel is the concept of moving backwards or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through space, and different from the normal "flow" of time to an earthbound observer. In this view, all points in time (including future times) "persist" in some way. Time travel has been a ] in fiction since the 19th century. Travelling backwards or forwards in time has never been verified as a process, and doing so presents many theoretical problems and contradictive logic which to date have not been overcome. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a ].
==Time travel==
{{main|Time travel}}
{{seealso|Time travel in fiction|Grandfather paradox}}


A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of ]; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of a ]. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between ], ], or ]s.
Time travel is the concept of moving backwards and/or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through ] and different than the "normal" flow of time to an earthbound observer. Although time travel has been a ] in ] since the 19th century, and one-way travel into the future is arguably possible given the phenomenon of ] in the ], it is currently unknown whether the ] would allow time travel to the past. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a ].
A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of ]; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of ]. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between ] or ]s.


Another solution to the problem of causality-based temporal paradoxes is that such paradoxes cannot arise simply because they have not arisen. As illustrated in numerous works of fiction, ] either ceases to exist in the past or the outcomes of such decisions are predetermined. As such, it would not be possible to enact the ] because it is a historical fact that one's grandfather was not killed before his child (one's parent) was conceived. This view does not simply hold that history is an unchangeable constant, but that any change made by a hypothetical future time traveller would already have happened in his or her past, resulting in the reality that the traveller moves from. More elaboration on this view can be found in the ].
Theory would point toward there having to be a physical ] in which one could travel to, where the ] (i.e. the point that which you are leaving) would be present at a point fixed in either the past or future. Seeing as this theory would be dependent upon the theory of a ], it is uncertain how or if it would be possible to just prove the possibility of time travel.


== Perception ==
==Perception of time==
]]]
===Psychology===
{{Main|Time perception}}
{{see also|Mental chronometry|Sense of time}}
Even in the presence of timepieces, different individuals may judge an identical length of time to be passing at different rates.{{Fact|date=February 2008}} Commonly, this is referred to as time seeming to "fly" (a period of time seeming to pass faster than possible) or time seeming to "drag" (a period of time seeming to pass slower than possible). The psychologist ] called this form of time perception "lived time."{{Fact|date=February 2008}}


The ] refers to the time duration wherein one's ]s are considered to be in the present. The experienced present is said to be 'specious' in that, unlike the objective present, it is an interval and not a durationless instant. The term ''specious present'' was first introduced by the psychologist E. R. Clay, and later developed by ].<ref name="Andersen">{{cite journal |author=Andersen |first1=Holly |last2=Grush |first2=Rick |date=2009 |title=A brief history of time-consciousness: historical precursors to James and Husserl |url=http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/bhtc/Andersen&Grush.pdf |url-status=dead |journal=Journal of the History of Philosophy |volume=47 |issue=2 |pages=277–307 |doi=10.1353/hph.0.0118 |s2cid=16379171 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080216100320/http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/bhtc/Andersen%26Grush.pdf |archive-date=16 February 2008 |access-date=9 April 2011}}
This common experience was used to familiarize the general public to the ideas presented by ]'s theory of relativity in a 1930 cartoon by ]:<ref name=Priestley">{{cite book | last = Priestley | first = J. B. | authorlink = J. B. Priestley | title = Man and Time | publisher = Crescent Books | location = New York | year = 1964 | pages = 96 | doi = | isbn = }}</ref><ref name="Sunrise">{{cite web | last = Sunrise | first = | title = Unified Field Theory: A new interpretation | work = Chapter 2—The Development of the Unified Field Theory, pg. 31 | publisher = Sunrise Information Services | year = 2008 | url = http://www.sunrisepage.com/uft/history.pdf| format =PDF | doi = | accessdate = }}</ref>
</ref>


=== Biopsychology ===
{{quotation|'''Man:''' Well, it's like this,—supposing I were to sit next to a pretty girl for half an hour it would seem like half a minute,—<br>'''Einstein:''' Braffo! You haf zee ideah! ]'']<br>'''Man:''' But if I were to sit on a hot stove for two seconds then it would seem like two hours.}}
The brain's judgment of time is known to be a highly distributed system, including at least the ], ] and ] as its components. One particular component, the ], is responsible for the ], while other cell clusters appear capable of shorter-range (]) timekeeping.


Psychoactive drugs can impair the judgment of time. ]s can lead both humans and rats to overestimate time intervals,<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Wittmann |first1=M. |last2=Leland |first2=D. S. |last3=Churan |first3=J. |last4=Paulus |first4=M. P. |date=8 October 2007 |title=Impaired time perception and motor timing in stimulant-dependent subjects |journal=Drug Alcohol Depend. |volume=90 |issue=2–3 |pages=183–192 |doi=10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2007.03.005 |pmc=1997301 |pmid=17434690}}
A form of temporal illusion verifiable by experiment is the ],<ref name="Wada">Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement</ref> whereby time intervals between visual events are perceived as relatively longer or shorter depending on the relative spatial positions of the events. In other words: the perception of temporal intervals appears to be directly affected, in these cases, by the perception of spatial intervals.
</ref><ref>
{{cite journal |last=Cheng |first=Ruey-Kuang |author2=Macdonald, Christopher J. |author3=Meck, Warren H. |date=2006 |title=Differential effects of cocaine and ketamine on time estimation: Implications for neurobiological models of interval timing |journal=] |volume=85 |issue=1 |pages=114–122 |pmid=16920182 |doi=10.1016/j.pbb.2006.07.019 |s2cid=42295255 |url=http://cat.inist.fr/?aModele=afficheN&cpsidt=18303059 |format=online abstract |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110810071741/http://cat.inist.fr/?aModele=afficheN&cpsidt=18303059 |archive-date=10 August 2011 }}
</ref> while ]s can have the opposite effect.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Tinklenberg |first1=Jared R. |author-link=Jared Tinklenberg |last2=Roth |first2=Walton T. |last3=Kopell |first3=Bert S. |date=January 1976 |title=Marijuana and ethanol: Differential effects on time perception, heart rate, and subjective response |journal=Psychopharmacology |volume=49 |issue=3 |pages=275–279 |doi=10.1007/BF00426830 |pmid=826945 |s2cid=25928542}}
</ref> The level of activity in the brain of ]s such as ] and ] may be the reason for this.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Arzy |first1=Shahar |last2=Molnar-Szakacs |first2=Istvan |last3=Blanke |first3=Olaf |date=18 June 2008 |title=Self in Time: Imagined Self-Location Influences Neural Activity Related to Mental Time Travel |journal=The Journal of Neuroscience |volume=28 |issue=25 |pages=6502–6507 |doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5712-07.2008 |pmc=6670885 |pmid=18562621}}
</ref> Such chemicals will either excite or inhibit the firing of ]s in the brain, with a greater firing rate allowing the brain to register the occurrence of more events within a given interval (speed up time) and a decreased firing rate reducing the brain's capacity to distinguish events occurring within a given interval (slow down time).<ref name="Carter 186–187">{{cite book |title=The Human Brain Book |first1=Rita |last1=Carter |publisher=Dorling Kindersley Publishing |date=2009 |isbn=978-0-7566-5441-2 |pages=186–187 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eCV6cwU3qm0C |access-date=27 February 2016 |archive-date=13 May 2016 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160513113657/https://books.google.com/books?id=eCV6cwU3qm0C |url-status=live }}</ref>


] is the use of response time in perceptual-motor tasks to infer the content, duration, and temporal sequencing of cognitive operations.
Time also appears to pass more quickly as one gets older.{{Fact|date=July 2008}} ] suggests that the perception of time is a ratio: ''Unit of Time : Time Lived''.{{Fact|date=February 2008}} For example, one hour to a six-month-old person would be approximately "1:4368", while one hour to a 40-year-old would be "1:349,440". Therefore an hour appears much longer to a young child than to an aged adult, even though the measure of time is the same.


=== Early childhood education ===
===Altered states of consciousness===
Children's expanding cognitive abilities allow them to understand time more clearly. Two- and three-year-olds' understanding of time is mainly limited to "now and not now". Five- and six-year-olds can grasp the ideas of past, present, and future. Seven- to ten-year-olds can use clocks and calendars.<ref>{{cite magazine |url=http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/growing-friendships/201403/time-management-kids |title=Time Management for Kids |last=Kennedy-Moore |first=Eileen |author-link=Eileen Kennedy-Moore |date=28 March 2014 |magazine=Psychology Today |access-date=26 April 2014 |archive-date=30 July 2022 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20220730093159/https://www.psychologytoday.com/us/blog/growing-friendships/201403/time-management-kids |url-status=live }}</ref>
Altered states of consciousness are sometimes characterized by a different estimation of time. Some psychoactive substances – such as ]s – may also dramatically alter a person's temporal judgement. When viewed under the influence of such substances as ], ], and ], a clock may appear to be a strange reference point and a useless tool for measuring the passage of events as it does not correlate with the user's experience. At higher doses, time may appear to slow down, stop, speed up, go backwards and even seem out of sequence. A typical thought might be "I can't believe it's only 8 o'clock, but then again, what does 8 o'clock mean?" As the boundaries for experiencing time are removed, so is its relevance. Many users claim this unbounded timelessness feels like a glimpse into spiritual infinity. To imagine that one exists somewhere "outside" of time is one of the hallmark experiences of a psychedelic voyage.{{Fact|date=February 2008}} ], a milder psychedelic, may also distort the perception of time to a lesser degree.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.erowid.org/plants/cannabis/cannabis_effects.shtml |title=Cannabis Effects |accessdate=2008-02-15 |work=Erowid |quote=Time sense altered: cars seem like they are moving too fast, time dilation and compression are common at higher doses.}}</ref>


=== Alterations ===
The practice of ], central to all Buddhist traditions, takes as its goal the reflection of the mind back upon itself, thus altering the subjective experience of time; the so called, 'entering the now', or 'the moment'.{{Fact|date=February 2008}}
In addition to psychoactive drugs, judgments of time can be altered by ]s (like the ]),<ref name="Wada">Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement.
</ref> age,<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg16422180.900-look-how-time-flies |title=Look how time flies |last=Adler |first=Robert |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110614233936/http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg16422180.900-look-how-time-flies |archive-date=14 June 2011 }}
</ref> and ].<ref>{{Cite journal |title=Hypnosis and the perception of time |volume=27 |issue=1 |date=January 1979 |pages=29–41 |doi=10.1080/00207147908407540 |author=Bowers, Kenneth |journal=International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis |pmid=541126 |last2=Brenneman |first2=Heather A. }}
</ref> The sense of time is impaired in some people with neurological diseases such as ] and ].


Psychologists assert that time seems to go faster with age, but the literature on this age-related perception of time remains controversial.<ref>{{cite book |title=Studies on the structure of time: from physics to psycho(patho)logy |chapter=Subjective Time Versus Proper (Clock) Time |editor1-first=R. |editor1-last=Buccheri |editor2-first=V. |editor2-last=Di Gesù |editor3-first=Metod |editor3-last=Saniga |first1=Ronald P. |last1=Gruber |first2=Lawrence F. |last2=Wagner |first3=Richard A. |last3=Block |publisher=Springer |date=2000 |isbn=978-0-306-46439-3 |page=54 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LMsDqsvcxckC |access-date=9 April 2011 |archive-date=21 July 2011 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110721230232/http://books.google.com/books?id=LMsDqsvcxckC |url-status=live }} {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160513024117/https://books.google.com/books?id=LMsDqsvcxckC&pg=PA54 |date=13 May 2016 }}</ref> Those who support this notion argue that young people, having more excitatory neurotransmitters, are able to cope with faster external events.<ref name="Carter 186–187"/>
===Culture===
Culture is another variable contributing to the perception of time. Anthropologist ] reported after studying the ] cultures that: "… the Hopi language is seen to contain no words, grammatical forms, construction or expressions or that refer directly to what we call “time”, or to past, present, or future…"<ref>Carroll, John B. (ed.)(1956). ''Language Thought and Reality. Selected Writings of Benjamin Lee Whorf''. MIT Press, Boston, Massachusetts. ISBN 0262730065 9780262730068</ref> Whorf's assertion has been challenged and modified. Pinker debunks Whorf's claims about time in the Hopi language, pointing out that the anthropologist Malotki (1983) has found that the Hopi do have a concept of time very similar to that of other cultures; they have units of time, and a sophisticated calendar.<ref>{{Citation | last = Parr-Davies | first = Neil | author-link = | title = The Sapir-Whorf Hypothesis: A Critique | publisher = ] | date = April 2001 | year = 2001 | url = http://www.aber.ac.uk/media/Students/njp0001.html | accessdate = ] }}</ref>


=== Spatial conceptualization ===
An interesting fact is that in ] (official language of ]), there is only one word ''kal'' for both ''yesterday'' and ''tomorrow''. The Hindi word ''kal'' could mean ''yesterday'' or it could mean ''tomorrow'', depending on the context.
Although time is regarded as an abstract concept, there is increasing evidence that time is ] in the mind in terms of space.<ref name="Núñez-2012">{{Cite journal |last1=Núñez |first1=Rafael |last2=Cooperrider |first2=Kensy |last3=Doan |first3=D |last4=Wassmann |first4=Jürg |date=1 July 2012 |title=Contours of time: Topographic construals of past, present, and future in the Yupno valley of Papua New Guinea |journal=Cognition |volume=124 |issue=1 |pages=25–35 |doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2012.03.007|pmid=22542697 |s2cid=17215084 }}</ref> That is, instead of thinking about time in a general, abstract way, humans think about time in a spatial way and mentally organize it as such. Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal events in a specific way.


This spatial representation of time is often represented in the mind as a Mental Time Line (MTL).<ref name="Bottini-2015">{{Cite journal |last1=Bottini |first1=Roberto |last2=Crepaldi |first2=Davide |last3=Casasanto |first3=Daniel |last4=Crollen |first4=Virgine |last5=Collignon |first5=Olivier |date=1 August 2015 |title=Space and time in the sighted and blind |journal=Cognition |volume=141 |pages=67–72 |doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2015.04.004|pmid=25935747 |hdl=2078.1/199842 |s2cid=14646964 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal order. These origins are shaped by many environmental factors<ref name="Núñez-2012" />––for example, ] appears to play a large role in the different types of MTLs, as reading/] provides an everyday temporal orientation that differs from culture to culture.<ref name="Bottini-2015" /> In western cultures, the MTL may unfold rightward (with the past on the left and the future on the right) since people read and write from left to right.<ref name="Bottini-2015" /> Western calendars also continue this trend by placing the past on the left with the future progressing toward the right. Conversely, Arabic, Farsi, Urdu and ] speakers read from right to left, and their MTLs unfold leftward (past on the right with future on the left), and evidence suggests these speakers organize time events in their minds like this as well.<ref name="Bottini-2015" />
==Use of time==
{{see also|Time management|Time discipline}}
In ] and ], ] is the general name given to ] and ] rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the social currency and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others.


This linguistic evidence that abstract concepts are based in spatial concepts also reveals that the way humans mentally organize time events varies across cultures––that is, a certain specific mental organization system is not universal. So, although Western cultures typically associate past events with the left and future events with the right according to a certain MTL, this kind of horizontal, egocentric MTL is not the spatial organization of all cultures. Although most developed nations use an egocentric spatial system, there is recent evidence that some cultures use an allocentric spatialization, often based on environmental features.<ref name="Núñez-2012" />
The use of time is an important issue in understanding ], ], and ]. ] is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with ], as the ] or the ] created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in ], has been observed to be about 20-30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period of time. This has led to the disputed ].


A study of the indigenous Yupno people of ] focused on the directional gestures used when individuals used time-related words.<ref name="Núñez-2012" /> When speaking of the past (such as "last year" or "past times"), individuals gestured downhill, where the river of the valley flowed into the ocean. When speaking of the future, they gestured uphill, toward the source of the river. This was common regardless of which direction the person faced, revealing that the Yupno people may use an allocentric MTL, in which time flows uphill.<ref name="Núñez-2012" />
] is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task will take to be completed, when it must be completed, and then adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so that completion is reached in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools.


A similar study of the Pormpuraawans, an ] in Australia, revealed a similar distinction in which when asked to organize photos of a man aging "in order," individuals consistently placed the youngest photos to the east and the oldest photos to the west, regardless of which direction they faced.<ref name="Boroditsky-2010">{{Cite journal |last1=Boroditsky |first1=Lera |author-link=Lera Boroditsky |last2=Gaby |first2=Alice |year=2010 |title=Remembrances of Times East |journal=Psychological Science |volume=21 |issue=11 |pages=1635–1639 |doi=10.1177/0956797610386621 |pmid=20959511 |s2cid=22097776}}</ref> This directly clashed with an American group that consistently organized the photos from left to right. Therefore, this group also appears to have an allocentric MTL, but based on the cardinal directions instead of geographical features.<ref name="Boroditsky-2010" />
] and ] have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective.


The wide array of distinctions in the way different groups think about time leads to the broader question that different groups may also think about other abstract concepts in different ways as well, such as causality and number.<ref name="Núñez-2012" />
==See also==
]]]
{{portal|Time|MontreGousset001.jpg}}
:''See the Time ] below for an exhaustive list of related articles.''


===Books=== == Use ==
{{See also|Time management}}
* '']''
* '']''
* '']''


In sociology and ], time discipline is the general name given to ] and economic rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the ] and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others. ]<ref>{{cite book |last=Hochschild |first=Arlie Russell |author-link=Arlie Russell Hochschild |title=The time bind: when work becomes home and home becomes work |title-link=Time bind |publisher=Metropolitan Books |year=1997 |location=New York}} {{isbn|978-0-8050-4471-3}}.</ref><ref>{{cite news |last=Russell Hochschild |first=Arlie |author-link=Arlie Russell Hochschild |url=https://www.nytimes.com/1997/04/20/magazine/there-s-no-place-like-work.html |title=There's no place like work |work=] |date=20 April 1997 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170323235804/http://www.nytimes.com/1997/04/20/magazine/there-s-no-place-like-work.html |archive-date=23 March 2017 |access-date=20 February 2017 }}</ref> and ]<ref>{{cite book |last=Elias |first=Norbert | author-link = Norbert Elias |title=Time: an essay |publisher=Blackwell |location=Oxford, UK Cambridge, US |year=1992 |isbn=978-0-631-15798-4}}</ref> have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective.
===Organizations===

''Leading scholarly organizations for researchers on the history and technology of time and timekeeping''
The use of time is an important issue in understanding ], education, and ]. ] is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with technology, as the television or the Internet created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in transport, has been observed to be about 20–30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period.
* ] - AHS (United Kingdom)

* ] - AFAHA (France)
] is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task requires and when it must be completed, and adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so it is done in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools.

== Sequence of events ==
A sequence of events, or series of events, is a ] of items, facts, events, actions, changes, or procedural steps, arranged in time order (chronological order), often with ] relationships among the items.<ref>{{cite web |title=Sequence – Order of Important Events |url=http://www.austinschools.org/curriculum/la/resources/documents/instResources/LA_res_Seq_ORS_Module.pdf |publisher=] |date=2009 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110927172713/http://www.austinschools.org/curriculum/la/resources/documents/instResources/LA_res_Seq_ORS_Module.pdf |archive-date=27 September 2011 }}
</ref><ref>
{{cite web |title=Sequence of Events Worksheets |url=http://www.reference.com/motif/Science/sequence-of-events-worksheets |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20101013032311/http://www.reference.com/motif/Science/sequence-of-events-worksheets |url-status=dead |archive-date=13 October 2010 |publisher=] }}
</ref><ref>
{{cite web |author1=Compiled by David Luckham |author2=Roy Schulte |name-list-style=amp |title=Event Processing Glossary&nbsp;– Version 2.0 |url=http://www.complexevents.com/2011/08/23/event-processing-glossary-version-2-0/ |publisher=Complex Event Processing |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111015182053/http://www.complexevents.com/2011/08/23/event-processing-glossary-version-2-0/ |archive-date=15 October 2011 |date=23 August 2011 }}
</ref>
Because of ], cause precedes ], or cause and effect may appear together in a single item, but effect never precedes cause. A sequence of events can be presented in text, ], ]s, or timelines. The description of the items or events may include a ]. A sequence of events that includes the time along with place or location information to describe a sequential path may be referred to as a ].

Uses of a sequence of events include stories,<ref>{{cite web |author=Nordquist |first=Richard |title=narrative |url=http://grammar.about.com/od/mo/g/narrative2term.htm |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110904221452/http://grammar.about.com/od/mo/g/narrative2term.htm |archive-date=4 September 2011 |publisher=]}}
</ref> historical events (]), directions and steps in procedures,<ref>{{cite web |author=Piasecki |first=David J. |title=Inventory Accuracy Glossary |url=http://www.accuracybook.com/glossary.htm |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110903094536/http://www.accuracybook.com/glossary.htm |archive-date=3 September 2011 |publisher=AccuracyBook.com (OPS Publishing)}}
</ref> and timetables for scheduling activities. A sequence of events may also be used to help describe ] in science, technology, and medicine. A sequence of events may be focused on past events (e.g., stories, history, chronology), on future events that must be in a predetermined order (e.g., ]s, ], procedures, timetables), or focused on the observation of past events with the expectation that the events will occur in the future (e.g., processes, projections). The use of a sequence of events occurs in fields as diverse as machines (]), documentaries ('']''), law (]), finance (]), ] (]), and ]<ref>{{cite web |title=Utility Communications Architecture (UCA) glossary |url=http://www.nettedautomation.com/glossary_menue/glossary_uca.html |publisher=NettedAutomation |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111210131225/http://nettedautomation.com/glossary_menue/glossary_uca.html |archive-date=10 December 2011 }}
</ref> (]). A specific example of a sequence of events is the ].

== See also ==
* ]
* ]
* ]

=== Organizations ===
* Antiquarian Horological Society&nbsp;– AHS (United Kingdom)
* ] (Switzerland) * ] (Switzerland)
* ] - DGC (Germany) * ]&nbsp;– DGC (Germany)
* ]&nbsp;– NAWCC (United States)
* ] Associazione Italiana Cultori di Orologeria Antica (Italy)
* ] - NAWCC (United States of America)


{{col-begin}} {{col-begin}}
{{col-break|width=25%}} {{col-break|width=25%}}

===Miscellaneous arts and sciences===
=== Miscellaneous arts and sciences ===
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ] (NTP)
* ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]


{{col-break|width=25%}} {{col-break|width=25%}}

===Miscellaneous units of time===
=== Miscellaneous units ===
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
{{col-end}} {{col-end}}


== References ==
==Notes and references==
{{reflist}}
{{Refimprove|date=July 2008}}
{{reflist|2}}


==Further reading== == Further reading ==
<div style="font-size:90%;">
* {{cite book | authorlink = Julian Barbour | last = Barbour | first = Julian | title = The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Physics | Publisher = Oxford University Press | year = 1999 | id = ISBN 0-19-514592-5 |}}
{{Div col}}
* {{cite book | last = Das | first = Tushar Kanti | title = The Time Dimension: An Interdisciplinary Guide | year = 1990 | location = New York | publisher = Praeger | id=ISBN 0275926818 }}- Research bibliography
* {{cite book | authorlink = Paul Davies | last = Davies | first = Paul | title=About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution | year = 1996|id=ISBN 0-684-81822-1}} * {{cite book |author-link=Julian Barbour |last=Barbour |first=Julian |title=The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Our Understanding of the Universe |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1999 |isbn=978-0-19-514592-2}}
* Craig Callendar, ''Introducing Time'', Icon Books, 2010, {{isbn|978-1-84831-120-6}}
* {{cite book | authorlink = Richard Feynman | last = Feynman | first = Richard | title=The Character of Physical Law | year = 1994|origyear=1965|location=Cambridge (Mass)|publisher=The MIT Press|id=ISBN 0-262-56003-8|pages=108-126|url=http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=5277}}
* {{cite book | authorlink = Peter Galison | last = Galison | first = Peter | title=Einstein's Clocks and Poincaré's Maps: Empires of Time | year = 1992|location=New York|publisher=W. W. Norton|id= ISBN 0-393-02001-0}} * {{cite book |last=Das |first=Tushar Kanti |title=The Time Dimension: An Interdisciplinary Guide |date=1990 |location=New York |publisher=Praeger |isbn=978-0-275-92681-6}} – Research bibliography
* {{cite book | last = Highfield | first = Roger | title = Arrow of Time: A Voyage through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery | publisher = Random House | year = 1992 | id = ISBN 0-449-90723-6}} * {{cite book |author-link=Paul Davies |last=Davies |first=Paul |title=About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution |date=1996 |isbn=978-0-684-81822-1 |publisher=Simon & Schuster Paperbacks |location=New York}}
* {{cite book | authorlink=Mermin|last = Mermin | first = N. David | title=It's About Time: Understanding Einstein's Relativity| year = 2005|publisher=Princeton University Press|id=ISBN 0-691-12201-6|url=http://press.princeton.edu/titles/8112.html}} * {{cite book |author-link=Richard Feynman |last=Feynman |first=Richard |title=The Character of Physical Law |date=1994 |orig-year=1965 |location=Cambridge (Mass) |publisher=The MIT Press |isbn=978-0-262-56003-0 |pages= |url=https://archive.org/details/characterofphysi0000feyn_u5j3/page/108 }}
* {{cite book | authorlink = Roger Penrose | last = Penrose | first = Roger | title=The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics | year = 1999|origyear=1989|location=New York|publisher=Oxford University Press|id=ISBN 0-19-286198-0|pages=391-417|url=http://www.oup.com/uk/catalogue/?ci=9780192861986}} * {{cite book |author-link=Peter Galison |last=Galison |first=Peter |title=Einstein's Clocks and Poincaré's Maps: Empires of Time |date=1992 |location=New York |publisher=W.W. Norton |isbn=978-0-393-02001-4 |url=https://archive.org/details/einsteinsclocksp00gali }}
* Benjamin Gal-Or, ''Cosmology, Physics and Philosophy'', Springer Verlag, 1981, 1983, 1987, {{isbn|0-387-90581-2|0-387-96526-2}}.
* {{cite book | last = Price | first = Huw | title=Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point| year = 1996|publisher=Oxford University Press|id=ISBN 0-19-511798-0|url=http://www.usyd.edu.au/time/price/TAAP.html}}
* ], (2005) ''Art, Time and Technology: Histories of the Disappearing Body'', Berg
* {{cite book | authorlink = Hans Reichenbach | last = Reichenbach | first = Hans | title=The Direction of Time | year = 1999|origyear=1956|location=New York|publisher=Dover|id=ISBN
* {{cite book |last=Highfield |first=Roger |title=Arrow of Time: A Voyage through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery |publisher=Random House |date=1992 |isbn=978-0-449-90723-8 |url=https://archive.org/details/arrowoftimevoy00cove }}
0-486-40926-0|url=http://store.doverpublications.com/0486409260.html}}
* {{cite book |author-link=David S. Landes |last=Landes |first=David |title=Revolution in Time |publisher=] |date=2000 |isbn=978-0-674-00282-1|title-link=Revolution in Time }}
*], '']''
* {{cite journal |last= Lebowitz |first=Joel L. |title=Time's arrow and Boltzmann's entropy |journal=Scholarpedia |date=2008 |volume=3 |number=4 |page=3448 |doi=10.4249/scholarpedia.3448 |bibcode=2008SchpJ...3.3448L |doi-access=free }}
* {{cite book | authorlink = Gerald James Whitrow | last = Whitrow | first = Gerald J. | title = The Nature of Time | publisher = Holt, Rinehart and Wilson (New York) | year = 1973}}
* {{cite book | last = Whitrow | first = Gerald J. | title = The Natural Philosophy of Time | publisher = Clarendon Press (Oxford) | year = 1980}} * {{cite book |author-link=N. David Mermin |last=Mermin |first=N. David |title=It's About Time: Understanding Einstein's Relativity |date=2005 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-12201-4 |url=https://archive.org/details/itsabouttimeunde0000merm |url-access=registration }}
* {{Cite book |title=Time's Arrows: Scientific Attitudes Toward Time |last=Morris |first=Richard |year=1985 |publisher=Simon and Schuster |location=New York |isbn=978-0-671-61766-0 |url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/timesarrows00rich |ref=none}}
* {{cite book | last = Whitrow | first = Gerald J. | title = Time in History. The evolution of our general awareness of time and temporal perspective | publisher = Oxford University Press | year = 1988 | id = ISBN 0-19-285211-6}}
* {{cite book |author-link=Roger Penrose |last=Penrose |first=Roger |title=The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics |date=1999 |orig-year=1989 |location=New York |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-286198-6 |pages=391–417 |url=http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780192861986.do |access-date=9 April 2011 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20101226155727/http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780192861986.do |archive-date=26 December 2010 }}
* {{cite book | last = Rovelli | first = Carlo | title = What is time? What is space? | publisher = Di Renzo Editore |location=Rome | year = 2006|id=ISBN 8883231465|url=http://www.direnzo.it/main.phtml?Language=en&Doc=0001&ISBN=8883231465}}
* {{cite book |last=Price |first=Huw |title=Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point |date=1996 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-511798-1 |url=https://archive.org/details/timesarrowarchim00pric |access-date=9 April 2011 }}
*], (2005) ''Art, Time and Technology: Histories of the Disappearing Body'', Berg
* {{cite book |author-link=Hans Reichenbach |last=Reichenbach |first=Hans |title=The Direction of Time |date=1999 |orig-year=1956 |location=New York |publisher=Dover |isbn=978-0-486-40926-9 |url=http://store.doverpublications.com/0486409260.html}}
* {{cite book |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |title=What is time? What is space? |publisher=Di Renzo Editore |location=Rome |date=2006 |isbn=978-88-8323-146-9 |url=http://www.direnzo.it/main.phtml?Language=en&Doc=0001&ISBN=8883231465 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070127102006/http://www.direnzo.it/main.phtml?Language=en&Doc=0001&ISBN=8883231465 |url-status=dead |archive-date=27 January 2007 }}
* {{cite book |last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |title=The Order of Time |publisher=Riverhead |location=New York |date=2018 |isbn=978-0735216105 |url=https://www.penguinrandomhouse.com/books/551483/the-order-of-time-by-carlo-rovelli/}}
* ], '']''
* Roberto Mangabeira Unger and Lee Smolin, '']'', Cambridge University Press, 2014, {{isbn|978-1-107-07406-4}}.
* {{cite book |author-link=Gerald James Whitrow |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=The Nature of Time |publisher=Holt, Rinehart and Wilson (New York) |date=1973}}
* {{cite book |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=The Natural Philosophy of Time |publisher=Clarendon Press (Oxford) |date=1980}}
* {{cite book |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=Time in History. The evolution of our general awareness of time and temporal perspective |url=https://archive.org/details/timeinhistoryevo00whit |url-access=registration |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1988 |isbn=978-0-19-285211-3}}
</div>
{{div col end}}


==External links== == External links ==
{{external links}} {{Sister project links|n=no|s=no|v=no}}
* (archived 16 October 2015).
{{wiktionarypar|time}}
* {{In Our Time|Time|p005465z|Time}}.
{{Wikiquote}}
* {{Merriam-Webster|Time}}
{{Wikibooks}}
* in the '']'', by Bradley Dowden.
{{Commonscat}}
* {{cite encyclopedia |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience |title=The Experience and Perception of Time |last=Le Poidevin |first=Robin |date=Winter 2004 |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor=Edward N. Zalta |access-date=9 April 2011}}
===Perception of time===
*


{{Nature nav}}
===Physics===
{{Time topics}}
*
{{Navboxes

|title=Time articles: Detailed navigation
===Philosophy===
|titlestyle=background:#ee9; border:1px solid silver; padding:0.2em 1em 0.2em 6.5em;
;'''Eastern Philosophy'''
|list1=
*
*

;'''Western Philosophy'''
* {{cite web
|url=http://www.onphilosophy.co.uk/time_-_a_dialogue.html
|title=Is there a defensible argument for the non-existence of time?
|first=Will
|last=Crouch
|Copyright James Nicholson
|year=2006-2008
|work=On Philosophy
|accessdate=2008-01-24}}
*{{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/t/time.htm
|title=Time
|first=Bradley (California State University, Sacramento)
|last=Dowden
|year=2007
|encyclopedia=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|editor=James Fieser, Ph.D., Bradley Dowden, Ph.D.
|accessdate=2008-01-31}}
* {{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience
|title=The Experience and Perception of Time
|last=Le Poidevin
|first=Robin
|year=Winter 2004
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|editor=Edward N. Zalta
|accessdate=2008-01-17}}
* {{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2007/entries/leibniz-physics/
|title=Leibniz's Philosophy of Physics
|year=Winter 2007
|copyright=2007
|first=Jeff (Harvard University)
|last=Mcdonough
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|editor=Edward N. Zalta
|publisher=Stanford University
|accessdate=2008-01-31}}
* {{cite web
|url=http://www.friesian.com/space.htm#clarke
|title=The Clarke-Leibniz Debate (1715-1716)
|first=Kelley L., Ph.D. (Los Angeles Valley College)
|last=Ross
|publisher=The Proceedings of the Friesian School, Fourth Series (1996, 1999, 2001)
|accessdate=2008-01-17}}
* {{cite web
|url=http://www.friesian.com/space.htm#kant
|title=Three Points in Kant's Theory of Space and Time
|first=Kelley L., Ph.D. (Los Angeles Valley College)
|last=Ross
|publisher=The Proceedings of the Friesian School, Fourth Series (1996, 1999, 2001)
|accessdate=2008-01-17}}
* {{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spacetime-bebecome/
|title=Being and Becoming in Modern Physics
|year=Fall 2007
|last=Savitt
|first=Steven, Ph.D. (University of British Columbia)
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|editor=Edward N. Zalta
|accessdate=2008-01-17}}
* {{cite encyclopedia
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2004/entries/kant-leibniz/
|title=Kant and Leibniz
|year=Summer 2004
|first=Catherine (City University of New York)
|last=Wilson
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
|editor=Edward N. Zalta
|publisher=Stanford University
|issn=1095-5054
|accessdate=2008-01-31}}

===Timekeeping===
*
*
*
*
*

===Miscellaneous===
*
* from Planck Time to the lifespan of the universe

==Navigation templates==<!-- Header linked from "See also" above -->
{{Time Topics}}
{| width="100%" class="collapsible collapsed" style="background:transparent; margin:1em 0 0;"
!style="background:#ee9; border:1px solid silver; padding:0.2em 1em 0.2em 6.5em; <!--to reduce size of "" link:-->font-size:90%;"| {{resize|110%|Time articles: Detailed navigation}}</tr>
|
{{Time measurement and standards}} {{Time measurement and standards}}
{{Chronology}} {{Chronology}}
{{Time in religion and mythology}} {{Time in religion and mythology}}
{{Time in philosophy}} {{Time in philosophy}}
{{metaphysics}}
|}
}}
{{SI base quantities}}
{{Portal bar|Physics|Astronomy|Stars|Science}}
{{Authority control}}


] ]
] ]
] ]
]

]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
] ]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]

Latest revision as of 13:51, 7 January 2025

Continuous progression from past to future For the magazine, see Time (magazine). For other uses, see Time (disambiguation).For musical conceptions of "time", see Time (music) and Tempo.Not to be confused with Thyme.

Time
Major concepts
Fields of study
Philosophy
Related topics

Time is the continuous progression of our changing existence that occurs in an apparently irreversible succession from the past, through the present, and into the future. It is a component quantity of various measurements used to sequence events, to compare the duration of events (or the intervals between them), and to quantify rates of change of quantities in material reality or in the conscious experience. Time is often referred to as a fourth dimension, along with three spatial dimensions. Scientists have theorized a beginning of time in our universe (the Big Bang) and an end (e.g., heat death or the Big Crunch). A cyclic model describes a cyclical nature, whereas the philosophy of eternalism views the subject from a different angle.

Time is one of the seven fundamental physical quantities in both the International System of Units (SI) and International System of Quantities. The SI base unit of time is the second, which is defined by measuring the electronic transition frequency of caesium atoms. General relativity is the primary framework for understanding how spacetime works. Through advances in both theoretical and experimental investigations of spacetime, it has been shown that time can be distorted and dilated, particularly at the edges of black holes.

Throughout history, time has been an important subject of study in religion, philosophy, and science. Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and technologists and has been a prime motivation in navigation and astronomy. Time is also of significant social importance, having economic value ("time is money") as well as personal value, due to an awareness of the limited time in each day and in human life spans. Cultural attitudes towards the human use of time are apparent in the verbs used—from "kill" to "waste" to "pass"—and sayings (like carpe diem).

Definition

The concept of time can be complex. Multiple notions exist and defining time in a manner applicable to all fields without circularity has consistently eluded scholars. Nevertheless, diverse fields such as business, industry, sports, the sciences, and the performing arts all incorporate some notion of time into their respective measuring systems. Traditional definitions of time involved the observation of periodic motion such as the apparent motion of the sun across the sky, the phases of the moon, and the passage of a free-swinging pendulum. More modern systems include the Global Positioning System, other satellite systems, Coordinated Universal Time and mean solar time. Although these systems differ from one another, with careful measurements they can be synchronized.

In physics, time is a fundamental concept to define other quantities, such as velocity. To avoid a circular definition, time in physics is operationally defined as "what a clock reads", specifically a count of repeating events such as the SI second. Although this aids in practical measurements, it does not address the essence of time. Physicists developed the concept of the spacetime continuum, where events are assigned four coordinates: three for space and one for time. Events like particle collisions, supernovas, or rocket launches have coordinates that may vary for different observers, making concepts like "now" and "here" relative. In general relativity, these coordinates do not directly correspond to the causal structure of events. Instead, the spacetime interval is calculated and classified as either space-like or time-like, depending on whether an observer exists that would say the events are separated by space or by time. Since the time required for light to travel a specific distance is the same for all observers—a fact first publicly demonstrated by the Michelson–Morley experiment—all observers will consistently agree on this definition of time as a causal relation.

General relativity does not address the nature of time for extremely small intervals where quantum mechanics holds. In quantum mechanics, time is treated as a universal and absolute parameter, differing from general relativity's notion of independent clocks. The problem of time consists of reconciling these two theories. As of 2024, there is no generally accepted theory of quantum general relativity.

Measurement

A sand timer uses the flow of sand to measure the passage of time.

Generally speaking, historical methods of temporal measurement, or chronometry, have taken two distinct forms: the calendar, a mathematical tool for organising long intervals of time, and the clock (e.g., watch), a physical mechanism that counts the passage of time. In day-to-day life, a clock was consulted for periods less than a day, whereas a calendar was consulted for periods longer than a day.

Increasingly, personal electronic devices display both calendars and clocks simultaneously. The number (as on a clock dial or calendar) that marks the occurrence of a specified event (as to hour or date) is obtained by counting from certain starting date (epoch), and relevant to a certain time zone (including daylight saving time). Precise measurements, as in astronomy, use a fiducial epoch – a central reference point.

History of the calendar

Main article: Calendar

Artifacts from the Paleolithic suggest that the moon was used to reckon time as early as 6,000 years ago. Lunar calendars were among the first to appear, with years of either 12 or 13 lunar months (either 354 or 384 days). Without intercalation to add days or months to some years, seasons quickly drift in a calendar based solely on twelve lunar months. Lunisolar calendars have a thirteenth month added to some years to make up for the difference between a full year (now known to be about 365.24 days) and a year of just twelve lunar months. The numbers twelve and thirteen came to feature prominently in many cultures, at least partly due to this relationship of months to years. Other early forms of calendars originated in Mesoamerica, particularly in ancient Mayan civilization. These calendars were religiously and astronomically based, with 18 months in a year and 20 days in a month, plus five epagomenal days at the end of the year.

The reforms of Julius Caesar in 45 BC put the Roman world on a solar calendar. This Julian calendar was faulty in that its intercalation still allowed the astronomical solstices and equinoxes to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. Pope Gregory XIII introduced a correction in 1582; the Gregorian calendar was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but it is now by far the most commonly used calendar around the world.

During the French Revolution, a new clock and calendar were invented as part of the dechristianization of France and to create a more rational system in order to replace the Gregorian calendar. The French Republican Calendar's days consisted of ten hours of a hundred minutes of a hundred seconds, which marked a deviation from the base 12 (duodecimal) system used in many other devices by many cultures. The system was abolished in 1806.

History of other devices

Horizontal sundial in Canberra
24-hour clock face in Florence
Main article: History of timekeeping devices See also: Clock

A large variety of devices have been invented to measure time. The study of these devices is called horology.

An Egyptian device that dates to c. 1500 BC, similar in shape to a bent T-square, measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a nonlinear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At noon, the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.

A sundial uses a gnomon to cast a shadow on a set of markings calibrated to the hour. The position of the shadow marks the hour in local time. The idea to separate the day into smaller parts is credited to Egyptians because of their sundials, which operated on a duodecimal system. The importance of the number 12 is due to the number of lunar cycles in a year and the number of stars used to count the passage of night.

The most precise timekeeping device of the ancient world was the water clock, or clepsydra, one of which was found in the tomb of Egyptian pharaoh Amenhotep I. They could be used to measure the hours even at night but required manual upkeep to replenish the flow of water. The ancient Greeks and the people from Chaldea (southeastern Mesopotamia) regularly maintained timekeeping records as an essential part of their astronomical observations. Arab inventors and engineers, in particular, made improvements on the use of water clocks up to the Middle Ages. In the 11th century, Chinese inventors and engineers invented the first mechanical clocks driven by an escapement mechanism.

A contemporary quartz watch, 2007

The hourglass uses the flow of sand to measure the flow of time. They were used in navigation. Ferdinand Magellan used 18 glasses on each ship for his circumnavigation of the globe (1522).

Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Water clocks, and, later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. Richard of Wallingford (1292–1336), abbot of St. Alban's abbey, famously built a mechanical clock as an astronomical orrery about 1330.

Great advances in accurate time-keeping were made by Galileo Galilei and especially Christiaan Huygens with the invention of pendulum-driven clocks along with the invention of the minute hand by Jost Burgi.

The English word clock probably comes from the Middle Dutch word klocke which, in turn, derives from the medieval Latin word clocca, which ultimately derives from Celtic and is cognate with French, Latin, and German words that mean bell. The passage of the hours at sea was marked by bells and denoted the time (see ship's bell). The hours were marked by bells in abbeys as well as at sea.

Chip-scale atomic clocks, such as this one unveiled in 2004, are expected to greatly improve GPS location.

Clocks can range from watches to more exotic varieties such as the Clock of the Long Now. They can be driven by a variety of means, including gravity, springs, and various forms of electrical power, and regulated by a variety of means such as a pendulum.

Alarm clocks first appeared in ancient Greece around 250 BC with a water clock that would set off a whistle. This idea was later mechanized by Levi Hutchins and Seth E. Thomas.

A chronometer is a portable timekeeper that meets certain precision standards. Initially, the term was used to refer to the marine chronometer, a timepiece used to determine longitude by means of celestial navigation, a precision first achieved by John Harrison. More recently, the term has also been applied to the chronometer watch, a watch that meets precision standards set by the Swiss agency COSC.

The most accurate timekeeping devices are atomic clocks, which are accurate to seconds in many millions of years, and are used to calibrate other clocks and timekeeping instruments.

Atomic clocks use the frequency of electronic transitions in certain atoms to measure the second. One of the atoms used is caesium; most modern atomic clocks probe caesium with microwaves to determine the frequency of these electron vibrations. Since 1967, the International System of Measurements bases its unit of time, the second, on the properties of caesium atoms. SI defines the second as 9,192,631,770 cycles of the radiation that corresponds to the transition between two electron spin energy levels of the ground state of the Cs atom.

Today, the Global Positioning System in coordination with the Network Time Protocol can be used to synchronize timekeeping systems across the globe.

In medieval philosophical writings, the atom was a unit of time referred to as the smallest possible division of time. The earliest known occurrence in English is in Byrhtferth's Enchiridion (a science text) of 1010–1012, where it was defined as 1/564 of a momentum (11⁄2 minutes), and thus equal to 15/94 of a second. It was used in the computus, the process of calculating the date of Easter.

As of May 2010, the smallest time interval uncertainty in direct measurements is on the order of 12 attoseconds (1.2 × 10 seconds), about 3.7 × 10 Planck times.

Units

See also: Time (Orders of magnitude) and Unit of time § List

The second (s) is the SI base unit. A minute (min) is 60 seconds in length (or, rarely, 59 or 61 seconds when leap seconds are employed), and an hour is 60 minutes or 3600 seconds in length. A day is usually 24 hours or 86,400 seconds in length; however, the duration of a calendar day can vary due to Daylight saving time and Leap seconds.

Time standards

Main article: Time standard

A time standard is a specification for measuring time: assigning a number or calendar date to an instant (point in time), quantifying the duration of a time interval, and establishing a chronology (ordering of events). In modern times, several time specifications have been officially recognized as standards, where formerly they were matters of custom and practice. The invention in 1955 of the caesium atomic clock has led to the replacement of older and purely astronomical time standards such as sidereal time and ephemeris time, for most practical purposes, by newer time standards based wholly or partly on atomic time using the SI second.

International Atomic Time (TAI) is the primary international time standard from which other time standards are calculated. Universal Time (UT1) is mean solar time at 0° longitude, computed from astronomical observations. It varies from TAI because of the irregularities in Earth's rotation. Coordinated Universal Time (UTC) is an atomic time scale designed to approximate Universal Time. UTC differs from TAI by an integral number of seconds. UTC is kept within 0.9 second of UT1 by the introduction of one-second steps to UTC, the leap second. The Global Positioning System broadcasts a very precise time signal based on UTC time.

The surface of the Earth is split into a number of time zones. Standard time or civil time in a time zone deviates a fixed, round amount, usually a whole number of hours, from some form of Universal Time, usually UTC. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from UTC. For example, time zones at sea are based on UTC. In many locations (but not at sea) these offsets vary twice yearly due to daylight saving time transitions.

Some other time standards are used mainly for scientific work. Terrestrial Time is a theoretical ideal scale realized by TAI. Geocentric Coordinate Time and Barycentric Coordinate Time are scales defined as coordinate times in the context of the general theory of relativity. Barycentric Dynamical Time is an older relativistic scale that is still in use.

Philosophy

Religion

Scale of time in Jain texts shown logarithmically
Further information: Time and fate deities

Religions which view time as cyclical

See also: Calendar and Wheel of time

Many ancient cultures, particularly in the East, had a cyclical view of time. In these traditions, time was often seen as a recurring pattern of ages or cycles, where events and phenomena repeated themselves in a predictable manner. One of the most famous examples of this concept is found in Hindu philosophy, where time is depicted as a wheel called the "Kalachakra" or "Wheel of Time." According to this belief, the universe undergoes endless cycles of creation, preservation, and destruction.

Similarly, in other ancient cultures such as those of the Mayans, Aztecs, and Chinese, there were also beliefs in cyclical time, often associated with astronomical observations and calendars. These cultures developed complex systems to track time, seasons, and celestial movements, reflecting their understanding of cyclical patterns in nature and the universe.

The cyclical view of time contrasts with the linear concept of time more common in Western thought, where time is seen as progressing in a straight line from past to future without repetition.

Time in Abrahamic religions

In general, the Islamic and Judeo-Christian world-view regards time as linear and directional, beginning with the act of creation by God. The traditional Christian view sees time ending, teleologically, with the eschatological end of the present order of things, the "end time".

In the Old Testament book Ecclesiastes, traditionally ascribed to Solomon (970–928 BC), time (as the Hebrew word עידן, זמן iddan (age, as in "Ice age") zĕman(time) is often translated) is a medium for the passage of predestined events. (Another word, زمان" זמן" zamān, meant time fit for an event, and is used as the modern Arabic, Persian, and Hebrew equivalent to the English word "time".)

Time in Greek mythology

The Greek language denotes two distinct principles, Chronos and Kairos. The former refers to numeric, or chronological, time. The latter, literally "the right or opportune moment", relates specifically to metaphysical or Divine time. In theology, Kairos is qualitative, as opposed to quantitative.

In Greek mythology, Chronos (ancient Greek: Χρόνος) is identified as the Personification of Time. His name in Greek means "time" and is alternatively spelled Chronus (Latin spelling) or Khronos. Chronos is usually portrayed as an old, wise man with a long, gray beard, such as "Father Time". Some English words whose etymological root is khronos/chronos include chronology, chronometer, chronic, anachronism, synchronise, and chronicle.

Time in Kabbalah & Rabbinical thought

Rabbis sometimes saw time like "an accordion that was expanded and collapsed at will." According to Kabbalists, "time" is a paradox and an illusion.

Time in Advaita Vedanta

According to Advaita Vedanta, time is integral to the phenomenal world, which lacks independent reality. Time and the phenomenal world are products of maya, influenced by our senses, concepts, and imaginations. The phenomenal world, including time, is seen as impermanent and characterized by plurality, suffering, conflict, and division. Since phenomenal existence is dominated by temporality (kala), everything within time is subject to change and decay. Overcoming pain and death requires knowledge that transcends temporal existence and reveals its eternal foundation.

In Western philosophy

Main articles: Philosophy of space and time and Temporal finitism
Time's mortal aspect is personified in this bronze statue by Charles van der Stappen.

Two contrasting viewpoints on time divide prominent philosophers. One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the universe – a dimension independent of events, in which events occur in sequence. Isaac Newton subscribed to this realist view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as Newtonian time.

The opposing view is that time does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with space and number) within which humans sequence and compare events. This second view, in the tradition of Gottfried Leibniz and Immanuel Kant, holds that time is neither an event nor a thing, and thus is not itself measurable nor can it be travelled.

Furthermore, it may be that there is a subjective component to time, but whether or not time itself is "felt", as a sensation, or is a judgment, is a matter of debate.

In Philosophy, time was questioned throughout the centuries; what time is and if it is real or not. Ancient Greek philosophers asked if time was linear or cyclical and if time was endless or finite. These philosophers had different ways of explaining time; for instance, ancient Indian philosophers had something called the Wheel of Time. It is believed that there was repeating ages over the lifespan of the universe. This led to beliefs like cycles of rebirth and reincarnation. The Greek philosophers believe that the universe was infinite, and was an illusion to humans. Plato believed that time was made by the Creator at the same instant as the heavens. He also says that time is a period of motion of the heavenly bodies. Aristotle believed that time correlated to movement, that time did not exist on its own but was relative to motion of objects. He also believed that time was related to the motion of celestial bodies; the reason that humans can tell time was because of orbital periods and therefore there was a duration on time.

The Vedas, the earliest texts on Indian philosophy and Hindu philosophy dating to the late 2nd millennium BC, describe ancient Hindu cosmology, in which the universe goes through repeated cycles of creation, destruction and rebirth, with each cycle lasting 4,320 million years. Ancient Greek philosophers, including Parmenides and Heraclitus, wrote essays on the nature of time. Plato, in the Timaeus, identified time with the period of motion of the heavenly bodies. Aristotle, in Book IV of his Physica defined time as 'number of movement in respect of the before and after'.

In Book 11 of his Confessions, St. Augustine of Hippo ruminates on the nature of time, asking, "What then is time? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one that asketh, I know not." He begins to define time by what it is not rather than what it is, an approach similar to that taken in other negative definitions. However, Augustine ends up calling time a "distention" of the mind (Confessions 11.26) by which we simultaneously grasp the past in memory, the present by attention, and the future by expectation.

Isaac Newton believed in absolute space and absolute time; Leibniz believed that time and space are relational. The differences between Leibniz's and Newton's interpretations came to a head in the famous Leibniz–Clarke correspondence.

Philosophers in the 17th and 18th century questioned if time was real and absolute, or if it was an intellectual concept that humans use to understand and sequence events. These questions lead to realism vs anti-realism; the realists believed that time is a fundamental part of the universe, and be perceived by events happening in a sequence, in a dimension. Isaac Newton said that we are merely occupying time, he also says that humans can only understand relative time. Relative time is a measurement of objects in motion. The anti-realists believed that time is merely a convenient intellectual concept for humans to understand events. This means that time was useless unless there were objects that it could interact with, this was called relational time. René Descartes, John Locke, and David Hume said that one's mind needs to acknowledge time, in order to understand what time is. Immanuel Kant believed that we can not know what something is unless we experience it first hand.

Time is not an empirical concept. For neither co-existence nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition, we could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in succession.

Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781), trans. Vasilis Politis (London: Dent., 1991), p. 54.

Immanuel Kant, in the Critique of Pure Reason, described time as an a priori intuition that allows us (together with the other a priori intuition, space) to comprehend sense experience. With Kant, neither space nor time are conceived as substances, but rather both are elements of a systematic mental framework that necessarily structures the experiences of any rational agent, or observing subject. Kant thought of time as a fundamental part of an abstract conceptual framework, together with space and number, within which we sequence events, quantify their duration, and compare the motions of objects. In this view, time does not refer to any kind of entity that "flows," that objects "move through," or that is a "container" for events. Spatial measurements are used to quantify the extent of and distances between objects, and temporal measurements are used to quantify the durations of and between events. Time was designated by Kant as the purest possible schema of a pure concept or category.

Henri Bergson believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as Duration. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.

According to Martin Heidegger we do not exist inside time, we are time. Hence, the relationship to the past is a present awareness of having been, which allows the past to exist in the present. The relationship to the future is the state of anticipating a potential possibility, task, or engagement. It is related to the human propensity for caring and being concerned, which causes "being ahead of oneself" when thinking of a pending occurrence. Therefore, this concern for a potential occurrence also allows the future to exist in the present. The present becomes an experience, which is qualitative instead of quantitative. Heidegger seems to think this is the way that a linear relationship with time, or temporal existence, is broken or transcended. We are not stuck in sequential time. We are able to remember the past and project into the future – we have a kind of random access to our representation of temporal existence; we can, in our thoughts, step out of (ecstasis) sequential time.

Modern era philosophers asked: is time real or unreal, is time happening all at once or a duration, is time tensed or tenseless, and is there a future to be? There is a theory called the tenseless or B-theory; this theory says that any tensed terminology can be replaced with tenseless terminology. For example, "we will win the game" can be replaced with "we do win the game", taking out the future tense. On the other hand, there is a theory called the tense or A-theory; this theory says that our language has tense verbs for a reason and that the future can not be determined. There is also something called imaginary time, this was from Stephen Hawking, who said that space and imaginary time are finite but have no boundaries. Imaginary time is not real or unreal, it is something that is hard to visualize. Philosophers can agree that physical time exists outside of the human mind and is objective, and psychological time is mind-dependent and subjective.

Unreality

In 5th century BC Greece, Antiphon the Sophist, in a fragment preserved from his chief work On Truth, held that: "Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)." Parmenides went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the paradoxes of his follower Zeno. Time as an illusion is also a common theme in Buddhist thought.

J. M. E. McTaggart's 1908 The Unreality of Time argues that, since every event has the characteristic of being both present and not present (i.e., future or past), that time is a self-contradictory idea (see also The flow of time).

These arguments often center on what it means for something to be unreal. Modern physicists generally believe that time is as real as space – though others, such as Julian Barbour, argue quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless realm containing every possible now or momentary configuration of the universe.

A modern philosophical theory called presentism views the past and the future as human-mind interpretations of movement instead of real parts of time (or "dimensions") which coexist with the present. This theory rejects the existence of all direct interaction with the past or the future, holding only the present as tangible. This is one of the philosophical arguments against time travel. This contrasts with eternalism (all time: present, past and future, is real) and the growing block theory (the present and the past are real, but the future is not).

Physical definition

Part of a series on
Classical mechanics
F = d p d t {\displaystyle {\textbf {F}}={\frac {d\mathbf {p} }{dt}}} Second law of motion
Branches
Fundamentals
Formulations
Core topics
Rotation
Scientists
Main article: Time in physics

Until Einstein's reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space in 1907, time was considered to be the same everywhere in the universe, with all observers measuring the same time interval for any event. Non-relativistic classical mechanics is based on this Newtonian idea of time.

Einstein, in his special theory of relativity, postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer.

The theory of special relativity finds a convenient formulation in Minkowski spacetime, a mathematical structure that combines three dimensions of space with a single dimension of time. In this formalism, distances in space can be measured by how long light takes to travel that distance, e.g., a light-year is a measure of distance, and a meter is now defined in terms of how far light travels in a certain amount of time. Two events in Minkowski spacetime are separated by an invariant interval, which can be either space-like, light-like, or time-like. Events that have a time-like separation cannot be simultaneous in any frame of reference, there must be a temporal component (and possibly a spatial one) to their separation. Events that have a space-like separation will be simultaneous in some frame of reference, and there is no frame of reference in which they do not have a spatial separation. Different observers may calculate different distances and different time intervals between two events, but the invariant interval between the events is independent of the observer (and his or her velocity).

Arrow of time

Main article: Arrow of time

Unlike space, where an object can travel in the opposite directions (and in 3 dimensions), time appears to have only one dimension and only one direction – the past lies behind, fixed and immutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet most laws of physics allow any process to proceed both forward and in reverse. There are only a few physical phenomena, that violate the reversibility of time. This time directionality is known as the arrow of time. Acknowledged examples of the arrow of time are:

  1. Radiative arrow of time, manifested in waves (e.g. light and sound) travelling only expanding (rather than focusing) in time (see light cone);
  2. Entropic arrow of time: according to the second law of thermodynamics an isolated system evolves toward a larger disorder rather than orders spontaneously;
  3. Quantum arrow time, which is related to irreversibility of measurement in quantum mechanics according to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics;
  4. Weak arrow of time: preference for a certain time direction of weak force in particle physics (see violation of CP symmetry);
  5. Cosmological arrow of time, which follows the accelerated expansion of the Universe after the Big Bang.

The relationship(s) between these different Arrows of Time is a hotly debated topic in theoretical physics.

Classical mechanics

In non-relativistic classical mechanics, Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works sufficiently well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience. In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. Einstein resolved these problems by invoking a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the conclusion that observers in motion relative to one another measure different elapsed times for the same event.

Two-dimensional space depicted in three-dimensional spacetime. The past and future light cones are absolute, the "present" is a relative concept different for observers in relative motion.

Spacetime

Main article: Spacetime

Time has historically been closely related with space, the two together merging into spacetime in Einstein's special relativity and general relativity. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the spatial reference frame of the observer, and the human perception, as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks, are different for observers in relative motion. For example, if a spaceship carrying a clock flies through space at (very nearly) the speed of light, its crew does not notice a change in the speed of time on board their vessel because everything traveling at the same speed slows down at the same rate (including the clock, the crew's thought processes, and the functions of their bodies). However, to a stationary observer watching the spaceship fly by, the spaceship appears flattened in the direction it is traveling and the clock on board the spaceship appears to move very slowly.

On the other hand, the crew on board the spaceship also perceives the observer as slowed down and flattened along the spaceship's direction of travel, because both are moving at very nearly the speed of light relative to each other. Because the outside universe appears flattened to the spaceship, the crew perceives themselves as quickly traveling between regions of space that (to the stationary observer) are many light years apart. This is reconciled by the fact that the crew's perception of time is different from the stationary observer's; what seems like seconds to the crew might be hundreds of years to the stationary observer. In either case, however, causality remains unchanged: the past is the set of events that can send light signals to an entity and the future is the set of events to which an entity can send light signals.

Dilation

Main article: Time dilation
Relativity of simultaneity: Event B is simultaneous with A in the green reference frame, but it occurred before in the blue frame, and occurs later in the red frame.

Einstein showed in his thought experiments that people travelling at different speeds, while agreeing on cause and effect, measure different time separations between events, and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are typically minute in the human experience, the effect becomes much more pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. Subatomic particles exist for a well-known average fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but when travelling close to the speed of light they are measured to travel farther and exist for much longer than when at rest. According to the special theory of relativity, in the high-speed particle's frame of reference, it exists, on the average, for a standard amount of time known as its mean lifetime, and the distance it travels in that time is zero, because its velocity is zero. Relative to a frame of reference at rest, time seems to "slow down" for the particle. Relative to the high-speed particle, distances seem to shorten. Einstein showed how both temporal and spatial dimensions can be altered (or "warped") by high-speed motion.

Einstein (The Meaning of Relativity): "Two events taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relative to K, which register the same simultaneously."

Einstein wrote in his book, Relativity, that simultaneity is also relative, i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference.

Relativistic versus Newtonian

Views of spacetime along the world line of a rapidly accelerating observer in a relativistic universe. The events ("dots") that pass the two diagonal lines in the bottom half of the image (the past light cone of the observer in the origin) are the events visible to the observer.

The animations visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At the heart of these differences are the Galilean and Lorentz transformations applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively.

In the figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the spacetime trajectory ("world line") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime.

The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer. In both pictures the view of spacetime changes when the observer accelerates.

In the Newtonian description these changes are such that time is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e., whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer).

However, in the relativistic description the observability of events is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "light cone" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of absolute time is no longer applicable: events move up and down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer.

Quantization

See also: Chronon

Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories (the Standard Model of Particles and Interactions and General Relativity) time is not quantized.

Planck time (~ 5.4 × 10 seconds) is the unit of time in the system of natural units known as Planck units. Current established physical theories are believed to fail at this time scale, and many physicists expect that the Planck time might be the smallest unit of time that could ever be measured, even in principle. Tentative physical theories that describe this time scale exist; see for instance loop quantum gravity.

Thermodynamics

The second law of thermodynamics states that entropy must increase over time (see Entropy). This can be in either direction – Brian Greene theorizes that, according to the equations, the change in entropy occurs symmetrically whether going forward or backward in time. So entropy tends to increase in either direction, and our current low-entropy universe is a statistical aberration, in a similar manner as tossing a coin often enough that eventually heads will result ten times in a row. However, this theory is not supported empirically in local experiment.

Travel

Main article: Time travel See also: Time travel in fiction, Wormhole, and Twin paradox

Time travel is the concept of moving backwards or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through space, and different from the normal "flow" of time to an earthbound observer. In this view, all points in time (including future times) "persist" in some way. Time travel has been a plot device in fiction since the 19th century. Travelling backwards or forwards in time has never been verified as a process, and doing so presents many theoretical problems and contradictive logic which to date have not been overcome. Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a time machine.

A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of causality; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of a temporal paradox. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between branch points, parallel realities, or universes.

Another solution to the problem of causality-based temporal paradoxes is that such paradoxes cannot arise simply because they have not arisen. As illustrated in numerous works of fiction, free will either ceases to exist in the past or the outcomes of such decisions are predetermined. As such, it would not be possible to enact the grandfather paradox because it is a historical fact that one's grandfather was not killed before his child (one's parent) was conceived. This view does not simply hold that history is an unchangeable constant, but that any change made by a hypothetical future time traveller would already have happened in his or her past, resulting in the reality that the traveller moves from. More elaboration on this view can be found in the Novikov self-consistency principle.

Perception

Philosopher and psychologist William James
Main article: Time perception

The specious present refers to the time duration wherein one's perceptions are considered to be in the present. The experienced present is said to be 'specious' in that, unlike the objective present, it is an interval and not a durationless instant. The term specious present was first introduced by the psychologist E. R. Clay, and later developed by William James.

Biopsychology

The brain's judgment of time is known to be a highly distributed system, including at least the cerebral cortex, cerebellum and basal ganglia as its components. One particular component, the suprachiasmatic nuclei, is responsible for the circadian (or daily) rhythm, while other cell clusters appear capable of shorter-range (ultradian) timekeeping.

Psychoactive drugs can impair the judgment of time. Stimulants can lead both humans and rats to overestimate time intervals, while depressants can have the opposite effect. The level of activity in the brain of neurotransmitters such as dopamine and norepinephrine may be the reason for this. Such chemicals will either excite or inhibit the firing of neurons in the brain, with a greater firing rate allowing the brain to register the occurrence of more events within a given interval (speed up time) and a decreased firing rate reducing the brain's capacity to distinguish events occurring within a given interval (slow down time).

Mental chronometry is the use of response time in perceptual-motor tasks to infer the content, duration, and temporal sequencing of cognitive operations.

Early childhood education

Children's expanding cognitive abilities allow them to understand time more clearly. Two- and three-year-olds' understanding of time is mainly limited to "now and not now". Five- and six-year-olds can grasp the ideas of past, present, and future. Seven- to ten-year-olds can use clocks and calendars.

Alterations

In addition to psychoactive drugs, judgments of time can be altered by temporal illusions (like the kappa effect), age, and hypnosis. The sense of time is impaired in some people with neurological diseases such as Parkinson's disease and attention deficit disorder.

Psychologists assert that time seems to go faster with age, but the literature on this age-related perception of time remains controversial. Those who support this notion argue that young people, having more excitatory neurotransmitters, are able to cope with faster external events.

Spatial conceptualization

Although time is regarded as an abstract concept, there is increasing evidence that time is conceptualized in the mind in terms of space. That is, instead of thinking about time in a general, abstract way, humans think about time in a spatial way and mentally organize it as such. Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal events in a specific way.

This spatial representation of time is often represented in the mind as a Mental Time Line (MTL). Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal order. These origins are shaped by many environmental factors––for example, literacy appears to play a large role in the different types of MTLs, as reading/writing direction provides an everyday temporal orientation that differs from culture to culture. In western cultures, the MTL may unfold rightward (with the past on the left and the future on the right) since people read and write from left to right. Western calendars also continue this trend by placing the past on the left with the future progressing toward the right. Conversely, Arabic, Farsi, Urdu and Israeli-Hebrew speakers read from right to left, and their MTLs unfold leftward (past on the right with future on the left), and evidence suggests these speakers organize time events in their minds like this as well.

This linguistic evidence that abstract concepts are based in spatial concepts also reveals that the way humans mentally organize time events varies across cultures––that is, a certain specific mental organization system is not universal. So, although Western cultures typically associate past events with the left and future events with the right according to a certain MTL, this kind of horizontal, egocentric MTL is not the spatial organization of all cultures. Although most developed nations use an egocentric spatial system, there is recent evidence that some cultures use an allocentric spatialization, often based on environmental features.

A study of the indigenous Yupno people of Papua New Guinea focused on the directional gestures used when individuals used time-related words. When speaking of the past (such as "last year" or "past times"), individuals gestured downhill, where the river of the valley flowed into the ocean. When speaking of the future, they gestured uphill, toward the source of the river. This was common regardless of which direction the person faced, revealing that the Yupno people may use an allocentric MTL, in which time flows uphill.

A similar study of the Pormpuraawans, an aboriginal group in Australia, revealed a similar distinction in which when asked to organize photos of a man aging "in order," individuals consistently placed the youngest photos to the east and the oldest photos to the west, regardless of which direction they faced. This directly clashed with an American group that consistently organized the photos from left to right. Therefore, this group also appears to have an allocentric MTL, but based on the cardinal directions instead of geographical features.

The wide array of distinctions in the way different groups think about time leads to the broader question that different groups may also think about other abstract concepts in different ways as well, such as causality and number.

Use

See also: Time management

In sociology and anthropology, time discipline is the general name given to social and economic rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the social currency and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others. Arlie Russell Hochschild and Norbert Elias have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective.

The use of time is an important issue in understanding human behavior, education, and travel behavior. Time-use research is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with technology, as the television or the Internet created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in transport, has been observed to be about 20–30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period.

Time management is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task requires and when it must be completed, and adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so it is done in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools.

Sequence of events

A sequence of events, or series of events, is a sequence of items, facts, events, actions, changes, or procedural steps, arranged in time order (chronological order), often with causality relationships among the items. Because of causality, cause precedes effect, or cause and effect may appear together in a single item, but effect never precedes cause. A sequence of events can be presented in text, tables, charts, or timelines. The description of the items or events may include a timestamp. A sequence of events that includes the time along with place or location information to describe a sequential path may be referred to as a world line.

Uses of a sequence of events include stories, historical events (chronology), directions and steps in procedures, and timetables for scheduling activities. A sequence of events may also be used to help describe processes in science, technology, and medicine. A sequence of events may be focused on past events (e.g., stories, history, chronology), on future events that must be in a predetermined order (e.g., plans, schedules, procedures, timetables), or focused on the observation of past events with the expectation that the events will occur in the future (e.g., processes, projections). The use of a sequence of events occurs in fields as diverse as machines (cam timer), documentaries (Seconds From Disaster), law (choice of law), finance (directional-change intrinsic time), computer simulation (discrete event simulation), and electric power transmission (sequence of events recorder). A specific example of a sequence of events is the timeline of the Fukushima Daiichi nuclear disaster.

See also

Organizations

Miscellaneous arts and sciences


Miscellaneous units

References

  1. "Time". Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford University Press. Archived from the original on 4 July 2012. Retrieved 18 May 2017. The indefinite continued progress of existence and events in the past, present, and future regarded as a whole
  2. ^ * "Webster's New World College Dictionary". 2010. Archived from the original on 5 August 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. 1.indefinite, unlimited duration in which things are considered as happening in the past, present, or future; every moment there has ever been or ever will be… a system of measuring duration 2.the period between two events or during which something exists, happens, or acts; measured or measurable interval
    • "The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary". 2002. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011. A duration or relation of events expressed in terms of past, present, and future, and measured in units such as minutes, hours, days, months, or years.
    • "Collins Language.com". HarperCollins. 2011. Archived from the original on 2 October 2011. Retrieved 18 December 2011. 1. The continuous passage of existence in which events pass from a state of potentiality in the future, through the present, to a state of finality in the past. 2. physics a quantity measuring duration, usually with reference to a periodic process such as the rotation of the earth or the frequency of electromagnetic radiation emitted from certain atoms. In classical mechanics, time is absolute in the sense that the time of an event is independent of the observer. According to the theory of relativity it depends on the observer's frame of reference. Time is considered as a fourth coordinate required, along with three spatial coordinates, to specify an event.
    • "The American Heritage Science Dictionary @dictionary.com". 2002. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011. 1. A continuous, measurable quantity in which events occur in a sequence proceeding from the past through the present to the future. 2a. An interval separating two points of this quantity; a duration. 2b. A system or reference frame in which such intervals are measured or such quantities are calculated.
    • "Eric Weisstein's World of Science". 2007. Archived from the original on 29 November 2017. Retrieved 9 April 2011. A quantity used to specify the order in which events occurred and measure the amount by which one event preceded or followed another. In special relativity, ct (where c is the speed of light and t is time), plays the role of a fourth dimension.
  3. "Time". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (Fourth ed.). 2011. Archived from the original on 19 July 2012. A nonspatial continuum in which events occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future.
  4. Merriam-Webster Dictionary Archived 8 May 2012 at the Wayback Machine the measured or measurable period during which an action, process, or condition exists or continues : duration; a nonspatial continuum which is measured in terms of events that succeed one another from past through present to future
  5. Compact Oxford English Dictionary A limited stretch or space of continued existence, as the interval between two successive events or acts, or the period through which an action, condition, or state continues. (1971).
  6. ^ * "Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". 2010. Archived from the original on 11 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Time is what clocks measure. We use time to place events in sequence one after the other, and we use time to compare how long events last... Among philosophers of physics, the most popular short answer to the question "What is physical time?" is that it is not a substance or object but rather a special system of relations among instantaneous events. This working definition is offered by Adolf Grünbaum who applies the contemporary mathematical theory of continuity to physical processes, and he says time is a linear continuum of instants and is a distinguished one-dimensional sub-space of four-dimensional spacetime.
    • "Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary". 2010. Archived from the original on 5 March 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011. 1. the system of those sequential relations that any event has to any other, as past, present, or future; indefinite and continuous duration regarded as that in which events succeed one another.... 3. (sometimes initial capital letter) a system or method of measuring or reckoning the passage of time: mean time; apparent time; Greenwich Time. 4. a limited period or interval, as between two successive events: a long time.... 14. a particular or definite point in time, as indicated by a clock: What time is it? ... 18. an indefinite, frequently prolonged period or duration in the future: Time will tell if what we have done here today was right.
    • Ivey, Donald G.; Hume, J.N.P. (1974). Physics. Vol. 1. Ronald Press. p. 65. Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 7 May 2020. Our operational definition of time is that time is what clocks measure.
  7. ^ Le Poidevin, Robin (Winter 2004). "The Experience and Perception of Time". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 22 October 2013. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  8. "Newton did for time what the Greek geometers did for space, idealized it into an exactly measurable dimension." About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution, Paul Davies, p. 31, Simon & Schuster, 1996, ISBN 978-0-684-81822-1
  9. Bunyadzade, Konul (15 March 2018). "Thoughts of Time" (PDF). Metafizika Journal (in Azerbaijani). 1. AcademyGate Publishing: 8–29. doi:10.33864/MTFZK.2019.0. ISSN 2616-6879. Archived (PDF) from the original on 5 April 2019. Retrieved 15 March 2018.
  10. Rendall, Alan D. (2008). Partial Differential Equations in General Relativity (illustrated ed.). OUP Oxford. p. 9. ISBN 978-0-19-921540-9. Archived from the original on 14 April 2021. Retrieved 24 November 2020.
  11. Carroll, Sean M. (2009). "From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time". Physics Today. 63 (4). Dutton: 54–55. Bibcode:2010PhT....63d..54C. doi:10.1063/1.3397046. ISBN 978-0-525-95133-9.
  12. "The Feynman Lectures on Physics Vol. I Ch. 5: Time and Distance". www.feynmanlectures.caltech.edu. Retrieved 15 December 2023.
  13. "Official Baseball Rules – 8.03 and 8.04" (Free PDF download). Major League Baseball. 2011. Archived (PDF) from the original on 1 July 2017. Retrieved 18 May 2017. Rule 8.03 Such preparatory pitches shall not consume more than one minute of time...Rule 8.04 When the bases are unoccupied, the pitcher shall deliver the ball to the batter within 12 seconds...The 12-second timing starts when the pitcher is in possession of the ball and the batter is in the box, alert to the pitcher. The timing stops when the pitcher releases the ball.
  14. "Guinness Book of Baseball World Records". Guinness World Records, Ltd. Archived from the original on 6 June 2012. Retrieved 7 July 2012. The record for the fastest time for circling the bases is 13.3 seconds, set by Evar Swanson at Columbus, Ohio in 1932...The greatest reliably recorded speed at which a baseball has been pitched is 100.9 mph by Lynn Nolan Ryan (California Angels) at Anaheim Stadium in California on 20 August 1974.
  15. Zeigler, Kenneth (2008). Getting organized at work : 24 lessons to set goals, establish priorities, and manage your time. McGraw-Hill. ISBN 978-0-07-159138-6. Archived from the original on 18 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019. 108 pages.
  16. Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ibid. p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature. ... The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e., actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of wrong statements."
  17. ^ Burnham, Douglas: Staffordshire University (2006). "Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) Metaphysics – 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 14 May 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time.
  18. Considine, Douglas M.; Considine, Glenn D. (1985). Process instruments and controls handbook (3 ed.). McGraw-Hill. pp. 18–61. Bibcode:1985pich.book.....C. ISBN 978-0-07-012436-3. Archived from the original on 31 December 2013. Retrieved 1 November 2016.
  19. Lilley, Sam (1981). Discovering Relativity for Yourself (illustrated ed.). Cambridge University Press Archive. p. 125. ISBN 978-0-521-23038-4. Extract of page 125.
  20. Surya, Sumati (December 2019). "The causal set approach to quantum gravity". Living Reviews in Relativity. 22 (1): 5. arXiv:1903.11544. Bibcode:2019LRR....22....5S. doi:10.1007/s41114-019-0023-1. Thus, the causal structure poset (M, ≺) of a future and past distinguishing spacetime is equivalent to its conformal geometry.
  21. Macías, Alfredo; Camacho, Abel (May 2008). "On the incompatibility between quantum theory and general relativity". Physics Letters B. 663 (1–2): 99–102. Bibcode:2008PhLB..663...99M. doi:10.1016/j.physletb.2008.03.052. In our opinion, it is not possible to reconciliate and integrate into a common scheme the absolute and non-dynamical character of Newtonian time of canonical quantization and path integral approaches with the relativistic and dynamical character of time in general relativity.
  22. Shavit, Joseph (18 July 2024). "Revolutionary theory finally unites quantum mechanics and Einstein's theory of general relativity". The Brighter Side of News. The prevailing consensus has been that Einstein's theory of gravity must be modified to fit within the framework of quantum theory when it comes to merging these two theories into a single, comprehensive framework, the scientific community has hit a roadblock.
  23. Richards, E. G. (1998). Mapping Time: The Calendar and its History. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–5. ISBN 978-0-19-850413-9.
  24. Rudgley, Richard (1999). The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age. New York: Simon & Schuster. pp. 86–105.
  25. Van Stone, Mark (2011). "The Maya Long Count Calendar: An Introduction". Archaeoastronomy. 24: 8–11.
  26. "French Republican Calendar | Chronology." Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, n.d. Web. 21 February 2016.
  27. "Education". Archived from the original on 1 May 2019. Retrieved 1 July 2018.
  28. Barnett, Jo Ellen (1999). Time's Pendulum: From Sundials to Atomic Clocks, the Fascinating History of Timekeeping and how Our Discoveries Changed the World (reprinted ed.). Harcourt Brace. p. 28. ISBN 978-0-15-600649-1.
  29. Lombardi, Michael A. "Why Is a Minute Divided into 60 Seconds, an Hour into 60 Minutes, Yet There Are Only 24 Hours in a Day?" Scientific American. Springer Nature, 5 March 2007. Web. 21 February 2016.
  30. Barnett, ibid, p. 37.
  31. Bergreen, Laurence. Over the Edge of the World: Magellan's Terrifying Circumnavigation of the Globe (HarperCollins Publishers, 2003), ISBN 0-06-621173-5
  32. North, J. (2004) God's Clockmaker: Richard of Wallingford and the Invention of Time. Oxbow Books. ISBN 1-85285-451-0
  33. Watson, E., (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". Antiquarian Horology, pp. 372–384.
  34. ^ "History of Clocks." About.com Inventors. About.com, n.d. Web. 21 February 2016.
  35. "NIST Unveils Chip-Scale Atomic Clock". NIST. 27 August 2004. Archived from the original on 22 May 2011. Retrieved 9 June 2011.
  36. "New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation". Vancouver Sun. 16 February 2008. Archived from the original on 11 February 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  37. "NIST-F1 Cesium Fountain Clock". Archived from the original on 25 March 2020. Retrieved 24 July 2015.
  38. "Byrhtferth of Ramsey". Encyclopædia Britannica. 2008. Archived from the original on 14 June 2020. Retrieved 15 September 2008.
  39. "atom", Oxford English Dictionary, Draft Revision September 2008 (contains relevant citations from Byrhtferth's Enchiridion)
  40. "12 attoseconds is the world record for shortest controllable time". 12 May 2010. Archived from the original on 5 August 2011. Retrieved 19 April 2012.
  41. Newman, John (1991). Geshe Lhundub Sopa (ed.). The Wheel of Time: Kalachakra in Context. Shambhala. pp. 51–54, 62–77. ISBN 978-1-55939-779-7.
  42. "Chichén Itzá: Venus Cycle". Travel. 27 February 2012. Retrieved 8 May 2024.
  43. Jennifer M. Gidley (2017). The Future: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-105424-2. Extract of page 13
  44. Rust, Eric Charles (1981). Religion, Revelation and Reason. Mercer University Press. p. 60. ISBN 978-0-86554-058-3. Archived from the original on 3 April 2017. Retrieved 20 August 2015. Profane time, as Eliade points out, is linear. As man dwelt increasingly in the profane and a sense of history developed, the desire to escape into the sacred began to drop in the background. The myths, tied up with cyclic time, were not so easily operative. So secular man became content with his linear time. He could not return to cyclic time and re-enter sacred space though its myths. Just here, as Eliade sees it, a new religious structure became available. In the Judaeo-Christian religions – Judaism, Christianity, Islam – history is taken seriously, and linear time is accepted. The cyclic time of the primordial mythical consciousness has been transformed into the time of profane man, but the mythical consciousness remains. It has been historicized. The Christian mythos and its accompanying ritual are bound up, for example, with history and center in authentic history, especially the Christ-event. Sacred space, the Transcendent Presence, is thus opened up to secular man because it meets him where he is, in the linear flow of secular time. The Christian myth gives such time a beginning in creation, a center in the Christ-event, and an end in the final consummation.
  45. Betz, Hans Dieter, ed. (2008). Religion Past & Present: Encyclopedia of Theology and Religion. Vol. 4 (4 ed.). Brill. p. 101. ISBN 978-90-04-14688-4. Archived from the original on 24 September 2015. Retrieved 20 August 2015. God produces a creation with a directional time structure .
  46. Lundin, Roger; Thiselton, Anthony C.; Walhout, Clarence (1999). The Promise of Hermeneutics. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. p. 121. ISBN 978-0-8028-4635-8. Archived from the original on 19 September 2015. Retrieved 20 August 2015. We need to note the close ties between teleology, eschatology, and utopia. In Christian theology, the understanding of the teleology of particular actions is ultimately related to the teleology of history in general, which is the concern of eschatology.
  47. "(Dictionary Entry)". Henry George Liddell, Robert Scott, A Greek-English Lexicon. Archived from the original on 7 May 2022. Retrieved 13 July 2015.
  48. New Myths and Meanings in Jewish New Moon Rituals David M. Rosen, Victoria P. Rosen Ethnology, Vol. 39, No. 3 (Summer, 2000), pp. 263–277 (referencing Yerushalmi 1989)
  49. Hus, Boʿaz; Pasi, Marco; Stuckrad, Kocku von (2011). Kabbalah and Modernity: Interpretations, Transformations, Adaptations. BRILL. ISBN 978-90-04-18284-4. Archived from the original on 13 May 2016. Retrieved 27 February 2016.
  50. Wolfson, Elliot R. (2006). Alef, Mem, Tau: Kabbalistic Musings on Time, Truth, and Death. University of California Press. p. 111. ISBN 978-0-520-93231-9. Archived from the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 7 May 2020. Extract of page 111 Archived 11 May 2022 at the Wayback Machine
  51. Puligandla, R. (1974). "Time and History in the Indian Tradition". Philosophy East and West. 24 (2): 165–170. doi:10.2307/1398019. ISSN 0031-8221. JSTOR 1398019.
  52. Rynasiewicz, Robert: Johns Hopkins University (12 August 2004). "Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University. Archived from the original on 16 July 2012. Retrieved 5 February 2012. Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence ... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation to anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year).
  53. Markosian, Ned. "Time". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition). Archived from the original on 14 September 2006. Retrieved 23 September 2011. The opposing view, normally referred to either as "Platonism with Respect to Time" or as "Absolutism with Respect to Time", has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it.
  54. Mattey, G. J. (22 January 1997). "Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis". Archived from the original on 14 March 2005. Retrieved 9 April 2011. What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded ... "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, mutatis mutandis, to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition."
  55. McCormick, Matt (2006). "Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) Metaphysics: 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 26 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the a priori contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues.
  56. Carrol, Sean (2010). "Chapter One, Section Two, Plume". From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time. Penguin. ISBN 978-0-452-29654-1. As human beings we 'feel' the passage of time.
  57. Lehar, Steve. (2000). The Function of Conscious Experience: An Analogical Paradigm of Perception and Behavior Archived 21 October 2015 at the Wayback Machine, Consciousness and Cognition.
  58. ^ "Philosophy of Time – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
  59. ^ "Ancient Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
  60. ^ Bunnag, Anawat (August 2017). "The concept of time in philosophy: A comparative study between Theravada Buddhist and Henri Bergson's concept of time from Thai philosophers' perspectives". Kasetsart Journal of Social Sciences. doi:10.1016/j.kjss.2017.07.007. Archived from the original on 2 April 2019. Retrieved 11 April 2019.
  61. Layton, Robert (1994). Who Needs the Past?: Indigenous Values and Archaeology. Psychology Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-415-09558-7.
  62. Dagobert Runes, Dictionary of Philosophy, p. 318.
  63. Hardie, R. P.; Gaye, R. K. "Physics by Aristotle". Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Archived from the original on 26 June 2014. Retrieved 4 May 2014. "Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is used in two senses – both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of what is continuous."
  64. Augustine of Hippo. Confessions. Archived from the original on 19 January 2012. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Book 11, Chapter 14.
  65. Gottfried Martin, Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science.
  66. ^ "Early Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
  67. Jankowiak, Tim. "Immanuel Kant". Archived from the original on 23 May 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2019.
  68. Kant, Immanuel (1787). The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition. Archived from the original on 13 April 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. translated by J.M.D. Meiklejohn, eBooks@Adelaide, 2004
  69. Bergson, Henri (1907) Creative Evolution. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998.
  70. Balslev, Anindita N.; Jitendranath Mohanty (November 1992). Religion and Time. Studies in the History of Religions, 54. The Netherlands: Brill Academic Publishers. pp. 53–59. ISBN 978-90-04-09583-0. Archived from the original on 20 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019.
  71. Heidegger, Martin (1962). "V". Being and Time. Blackwell. p. 425. ISBN 978-0-631-19770-6. Archived from the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 30 July 2019.
  72. ^ "Modern Philosophy – Exactly What Is Time?". Archived from the original on 28 March 2019. Retrieved 28 March 2019.
  73. Foundalis, Harry. "You are about to disappear". Archived from the original on 12 May 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  74. Huston, Tom. "Buddhism and the illusion of time". Archived from the original on 8 July 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  75. Garfield, Jay L. (1995). The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-509336-0. Archived from the original on 19 August 2020. Retrieved 19 May 2018.
  76. Herman M. Schwartz, Introduction to Special Relativity, McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1968, hardcover 442 pages, see ISBN 0-88275-478-5 (1977 edition), pp. 10–13
  77. A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, H. Minkowski, The Principle of Relativity, Dover Publications, Inc, 2000, softcover, 216 pages, ISBN 0-486-60081-5, See pp. 37–65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper.
  78. Quantum causality and the arrows of time and thermodynamics. 2020. Prog Part Nucl Phys. 115/13. J.F. Donoghue, G. Menezes. doi: 10.1016/j.ppnp.2020.103812.
  79. The Direction of Time. 2015. Time: A Philosophical Introduction. pp. 191–214. J. Harrington, J. Harrington.
  80. Time irreversibility in active matter, from micro to macro. 2022. Nat Rev Phys. 4/3, pp. 167–183.
  81. J. O'byrne, Y. Kafri, J. Tailleur, F. Van Wijland. doi: 10.1038/s42254-021-00406-2.
  82. The Nature and Origin of Time-Asymmetric Spacetime Structures. 2014. Springer Handbook of Spacetime. pp. 185–196. H.D. Zeh.
  83. The Arrow of Time. 2016. Cosmological and Psychological Time. 285/155-62. M. Hemmo, O. Shenker. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-22590-6_9.
  84. Relativity Theory May not Have the Last Word on the Nature of Time: Quantum Theory and Probabilism. 2017. Space, Time and the Limits of Human Understanding. pp. 109214. N. Maxwell. doi: 10.1007/978-3-319-44418-5_9.
  85. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. 2013. Complexity and the Arrow of Time. pp. 1–357. doi: 10.1017/cbo9781139225700.
  86. Peter Coveney and Roger Highfield. The Arrow of Time : A Voyage Through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery. Hardcover – May 14, 1991. https://www.publishersweekly.com/9780449906309
  87. "Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity". YouTube. 30 November 2011. Archived from the original on 17 October 2013. Retrieved 24 September 2013.
  88. "Time Travel: Einstein's big idea (Theory of Relativity)". YouTube. 9 January 2007. Archived from the original on 17 October 2013. Retrieved 24 September 2013.
  89. Knudsen, Jens M.; Hjorth, Poul G. (6 December 2012). Elements of Newtonian Mechanics. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 30. ISBN 978-3-642-97599-8.
  90. Greene, Brian (2005). "Chapter 6: Chance and the Arrow". The Fabric of the Cosmos. Penguin Books Limited. ISBN 978-0-14-195995-5. Archived from the original on 20 August 2020. Retrieved 16 September 2017.
  91. Andersen, Holly; Grush, Rick (2009). "A brief history of time-consciousness: historical precursors to James and Husserl" (PDF). Journal of the History of Philosophy. 47 (2): 277–307. doi:10.1353/hph.0.0118. S2CID 16379171. Archived from the original (PDF) on 16 February 2008. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  92. Wittmann, M.; Leland, D. S.; Churan, J.; Paulus, M. P. (8 October 2007). "Impaired time perception and motor timing in stimulant-dependent subjects". Drug Alcohol Depend. 90 (2–3): 183–192. doi:10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2007.03.005. PMC 1997301. PMID 17434690.
  93. Cheng, Ruey-Kuang; Macdonald, Christopher J.; Meck, Warren H. (2006). "Differential effects of cocaine and ketamine on time estimation: Implications for neurobiological models of interval timing" (online abstract). Pharmacology Biochemistry and Behavior. 85 (1): 114–122. doi:10.1016/j.pbb.2006.07.019. PMID 16920182. S2CID 42295255. Archived from the original on 10 August 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  94. Tinklenberg, Jared R.; Roth, Walton T.; Kopell, Bert S. (January 1976). "Marijuana and ethanol: Differential effects on time perception, heart rate, and subjective response". Psychopharmacology. 49 (3): 275–279. doi:10.1007/BF00426830. PMID 826945. S2CID 25928542.
  95. Arzy, Shahar; Molnar-Szakacs, Istvan; Blanke, Olaf (18 June 2008). "Self in Time: Imagined Self-Location Influences Neural Activity Related to Mental Time Travel". The Journal of Neuroscience. 28 (25): 6502–6507. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5712-07.2008. PMC 6670885. PMID 18562621.
  96. ^ Carter, Rita (2009). The Human Brain Book. Dorling Kindersley Publishing. pp. 186–187. ISBN 978-0-7566-5441-2. Archived from the original on 13 May 2016. Retrieved 27 February 2016.
  97. Kennedy-Moore, Eileen (28 March 2014). "Time Management for Kids". Psychology Today. Archived from the original on 30 July 2022. Retrieved 26 April 2014.
  98. Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement.
  99. Adler, Robert. "Look how time flies". Archived from the original on 14 June 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011.
  100. Bowers, Kenneth; Brenneman, Heather A. (January 1979). "Hypnosis and the perception of time". International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis. 27 (1): 29–41. doi:10.1080/00207147908407540. PMID 541126.
  101. Gruber, Ronald P.; Wagner, Lawrence F.; Block, Richard A. (2000). "Subjective Time Versus Proper (Clock) Time". In Buccheri, R.; Di Gesù, V.; Saniga, Metod (eds.). Studies on the structure of time: from physics to psycho(patho)logy. Springer. p. 54. ISBN 978-0-306-46439-3. Archived from the original on 21 July 2011. Retrieved 9 April 2011. Extract of page 54 Archived 13 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine
  102. ^ Núñez, Rafael; Cooperrider, Kensy; Doan, D; Wassmann, Jürg (1 July 2012). "Contours of time: Topographic construals of past, present, and future in the Yupno valley of Papua New Guinea". Cognition. 124 (1): 25–35. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2012.03.007. PMID 22542697. S2CID 17215084.
  103. ^ Bottini, Roberto; Crepaldi, Davide; Casasanto, Daniel; Crollen, Virgine; Collignon, Olivier (1 August 2015). "Space and time in the sighted and blind". Cognition. 141: 67–72. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2015.04.004. hdl:2078.1/199842. PMID 25935747. S2CID 14646964.
  104. ^ Boroditsky, Lera; Gaby, Alice (2010). "Remembrances of Times East". Psychological Science. 21 (11): 1635–1639. doi:10.1177/0956797610386621. PMID 20959511. S2CID 22097776.
  105. Hochschild, Arlie Russell (1997). The time bind: when work becomes home and home becomes work. New York: Metropolitan Books. ISBN 978-0-8050-4471-3.
  106. Russell Hochschild, Arlie (20 April 1997). "There's no place like work". The New York Times Magazine. Archived from the original on 23 March 2017. Retrieved 20 February 2017.
  107. Elias, Norbert (1992). Time: an essay. Oxford, UK Cambridge, US: Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-15798-4.
  108. "Sequence – Order of Important Events" (PDF). Austin Independent School District. 2009. Archived from the original (PDF) on 27 September 2011.
  109. "Sequence of Events Worksheets". Reference.com. Archived from the original on 13 October 2010.
  110. Compiled by David Luckham & Roy Schulte (23 August 2011). "Event Processing Glossary – Version 2.0". Complex Event Processing. Archived from the original on 15 October 2011.
  111. Nordquist, Richard. "narrative". About.com. Archived from the original on 4 September 2011.
  112. Piasecki, David J. "Inventory Accuracy Glossary". AccuracyBook.com (OPS Publishing). Archived from the original on 3 September 2011.
  113. "Utility Communications Architecture (UCA) glossary". NettedAutomation. Archived from the original on 10 December 2011.

Further reading

External links

Elements of nature
Universe
Earth
Weather
Natural environment
Life
See also
Time
Key concepts
Measurement
and standards
Chronometry
Measurement
systems
Calendars
Clocks
Philosophy of time
Human experience
and use of time
Time in science
Geology
Physics
Other fields
Related
Time articles: Detailed navigation
Time measurement and standards
International standards template illustration
template illustration
Obsolete standards
Time in physics
Horology
Calendar
Archaeology and geology
Astronomical chronology
Other units of time
Related topics
Chronology
Key topics
Calendar eras
Regnal year
Era names
Calendars
Pre-Julian / Julian
Gregorian
Astronomical
Others
Astronomic time
Geologic time
Concepts
Standards
Methods
Chronological
dating
Absolute dating
Relative dating
Genetic methods
Linguistic methods
Related topics
Time in religion and mythology
Philosophy of time
Concepts in time
Theories of time
Related articles
Metaphysics
Theories
Concepts
Metaphysicians
Notable works
Related topics
SI base quantities
Base quantities
Quantity SI unit
Name Symbol Dimension
symbol
Unit
name
Unit
symbol
time, duration t T second s
length l, x, r, etc. L metre m
mass m M kilogram kg
electric current  I , i  I  ampere A
thermodynamic temperature T Θ kelvin K
amount of substance n N mole mol
luminous intensity Iv J candela cd
See also
Portals: Categories: