Misplaced Pages

Euthanasia: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 17:32, 30 October 2007 view sourceAlison (talk | contribs)Edit filter managers, Autopatrolled, Checkusers, Administrators47,252 editsm Reverted edits by 155.42.144.20 (talk) to last version by Sesshomaru← Previous edit Latest revision as of 13:45, 6 January 2025 view source Writ Keeper (talk | contribs)Edit filter managers, Autopatrolled, Interface administrators, Administrators26,053 edits rm 
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Intentionally ending a life to relieve pain and suffering}}
{{For|mercy killings not performed on humans|animal euthanasia}}
{{About|euthanasia of humans|humane killings of other animals|Animal euthanasia|the killing of mortally wounded animals or humans|Coup de grâce|the ] album|Youthanasia{{!}}''Youthanasia''}}
{{pp-semi-protected|small= yes}}
{{Use British English|date= August 2015}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=February 2021}}
{{Euthanasia}}{{homicide}}
'''Euthanasia''' (from {{langx|el|εὐθανασία|lit=good death}}: {{langx|el|εὖ|lit=well, good|translit=eu|label=none}} + {{langx|el|θάνατος|lit=death|translit=thanatos|label=none}}) is the practice of intentionally ending life to eliminate ] and ].<ref>{{cite web|quotation='Euthanasia' is a compound of two Greek words – eu and thanatos meaning, literally, 'a good death'. Today, 'euthanasia' is generally understood to mean the bringing about of a good death – 'mercy killing,' where one person, A, ends the life of another person, B, for the sake of B."|url= http://www.worldrtd.net/euthanasia-fact-sheet|title= Euthanasia Fact Sheet |first1=Helga |last1=Kuhse |website= The World Federation of Right to Die Societies|access-date= 6 July 2017|url-status= dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20170805150346/http://www.worldrtd.net/euthanasia-fact-sheet|archive-date= 5 August 2017}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|chapter-url= http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/euthanasia-voluntary/ |title= Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date= 7 May 2019|chapter= Voluntary Euthanasia |publisher= Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University | quote = When a person performs an act of euthanasia, she brings about the death of another person because she believes the latter's present existence is so bad that he would be better off dead, or believes that unless she intervenes and ends his life, his life will very soon become so bad that he would be better off dead. |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190611083952/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/euthanasia-voluntary/ |archive-date= Jun 11, 2019
}}</ref>


Different countries have different ]. The British ] ] on ] defines euthanasia as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life to relieve intractable suffering".<ref name="Harris-2001">{{Cite journal | last1 = Harris | first1 = NM. | title = The euthanasia debate | journal = J R Army Med Corps | volume = 147 | issue = 3 | pages = 367–70 |date= October 2001 | pmid = 11766225 | doi= 10.1136/jramc-147-03-22| doi-access = free }}</ref> In the ] and ], euthanasia is understood as "termination of life by a doctor at the request of a patient".<ref> {{webarchive|url= https://web.archive.org/web/20110719071151/http://www.bbc.co.uk/health/support/terminalillness_euthanasia.shtml |date= 19 July 2011 }} '']''. Last reviewed June 2011. Accessed 25 July 2011. Archived from the original</ref> The Dutch law, however, does not use the term 'euthanasia' but includes the concept under the broader definition of "assisted suicide and termination of life on request".<ref>{{cite book |last1= Carr|first1= Claudia|title= Unlocking Medical Law and Ethics|date= 2014|publisher= Routledge|isbn= 9781317743514|page= 374|edition= 2nd|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=a5SLBQAAQBAJ&pg=PT402|access-date= 2 February 2018}}</ref>
'''Euthanasia''' is the practice of ending the ] of a human or animal who is incurably ] in a ] or minimally painful way, for the purpose of limiting ]. Laws around the world vary greatly with regard to euthanasia, and are constantly subject to change as cultural values shift and better ], or treatments become available. It is legal in some nations, while in others it may be ].


Euthanasia is categorised in different ways, which include ], ], and ].<ref name="BBC"> {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110905055247/http://www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/euthanasia/overview/volinvol.shtml |date=5 September 2011 }} '']'' Accessed 12 February 2012. Archived from the original</ref> Voluntary euthanasia is when a person wishes to have their life ended and is legal in a growing number of countries. Non-voluntary euthanasia occurs when a patient's consent is unavailable and is legal in some countries under certain limited conditions, in both active and passive forms. Involuntary euthanasia, which is done without asking for consent or against the patient's will, is illegal in all countries and is usually considered ].
Euthanasia can be conducted in various ways. In order to distinguish certain methods, more specific terminology may be used when discussing euthanasia.


{{As of | 2006}}, euthanasia had become the most active area of research in ].<ref>
===Euthanasia by means===
{{Cite journal
Euthanasia may be conducted passively, non-aggressively, and aggressively. Passive euthanasia entails the withholding of common treatments (such as antibiotics, pain medications, or surgery) or the distribution of a medication (such as morphine) to relieve ], knowing that it may also result in death (]). Passive euthanasia is the most accepted form, and it is a common practice in most hospitals. Non-aggressive euthanasia entails the withdrawing of life support and is more controversial. Aggressive euthanasia entails the use of lethal substances or force to kill and is the most controversial means.
|vauthors= Borry P, Schotsmans P, Dierickx K
|title= Empirical research in bioethical journals. A quantitative analysis
|journal= ] |volume= 32 |issue= 4
|pages= 240–45 |date= April 2006
|pmid= 16574880 |pmc= 2565792 |doi= 10.1136/jme.2004.011478
}}
</ref>
In some countries, divisive public controversy occurs over the moral, ethical, and legal issues associated with euthanasia. Passive euthanasia (known as "pulling the plug") is legal under some circumstances in many countries. Active euthanasia, however, is legal or ''de facto'' legal in only a handful of countries (for example, Belgium, Canada, and Switzerland), which limit it to specific circumstances and require the approval of ], doctors, or other specialists. In some countries—such as Nigeria, Saudi Arabia, and Pakistan—support for active euthanasia is almost nonexistent.


==Definition==
===Euthanasia by consent===
===Current usage===
Euthanasia may be conducted with or without consent. Involuntary euthanasia is conducted against someone’s will and equates to murder. This practice is almost always considered wrong and is rarely debated.{{Fact|date=August 2007}} Non-voluntary euthanasia can be administered when the person is incapable of making a decision and it is thus left to a proxy. One recent example of non-voluntary euthanasia is the ] case. This is highly controversial, especially because multiple proxies may claim the authority to decide for the patient. Voluntary euthanasia is euthanasia with the person’s direct consent, but is still controversial for reasons discussed below.<ref name="plato"/>
As of 2024, dictionary definitions focus on euthanasia as the act of killing someone to prevent further suffering. There is no sense of whether the person agrees or is proactive in the situation.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.dictionary.com/browse/euthanasia|title=Dictionary.com &#124; Meanings & Definitions of English Words|website=Dictionary.com}}</ref><ref>{{Cite web|url=https://dictionary.cambridge.org/dictionary/english/euthanasia|title=EUTHANASIA &#124; English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary}}</ref>


===Past discussions on key elements===
===Other designations===
In 1974 euthanasia was defined as the "painless inducement of a quick death".<ref>{{cite book | last = Kohl | first = Marvin | year = 1974 | title = The Morality of Killing | url = https://archive.org/details/moralityofkillin0000kohl | url-access = registration | publisher = Humanities Press | location = New York | page = | isbn = 9780391001954 }}, quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 294. A similar definition is offered by Blackburn (1994) with "the action of causing the quick and painless death of a person, or not acting to prevent it when prevention was within the agent's powers."</ref> However, it is argued that this approach fails to properly define euthanasia, as it leaves open a number of possible actions that would meet the requirements of the definition but would not be seen as euthanasia. In particular, these include situations where a person kills another, painlessly, but for no reason beyond that of personal gain, or accidental deaths that are quick and painless but not intentional.<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979">{{Cite journal| last1 = Beauchamp | first1 = Tom L. | author-link1 = Tom Beauchamp | last2 = Davidson | first2 = Arnold I. | author-link2 = Arnold Davidson | year = 1979 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | journal = ] | volume = 4 | issue = 3 | pages = 294–312 | doi=10.1093/jmp/4.3.294 | pmid=501249}}</ref><ref name="Draper1998">{{cite book | last = Draper | first = Heather | year = 1998 | chapter = Euthanasia | editor = Chadwick, Ruth | title = Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics | volume = 2 | publisher = Academic Press }}</ref>
Some important ]s of euthanasia consists of ], ]. The Canadian Council of Animal Care (CCAC) states that euthanasia is "to kill an animal painlessly, and without distress."<ref name="CCAC">"Glossary." CCAC Programs. 2005. Canadian Council on Animal Care. 13 July 2007 (http://www.ccac.ca/en/CCAC_Programs/ETCC/GlossaryEng.htm).</ref> The CCAC further explains a physical euthanasia technique called ] and a secondary technique called ].<ref name="CCAC"/>


Another approach incorporated the notion of ] into the definition.<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979" /> The definition offered by the ] incorporates suffering as a necessary condition with "the painless killing of a patient suffering from an incurable and painful disease or in an irreversible coma",<ref>{{cite web | title = euthanasia | work = Oxford Dictionaries | date = April 2010 | publisher = ] | url = http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/definition/euthanasia | access-date = 26 April 2011 | url-status = dead | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20110821152342/http://oxforddictionaries.com/definition/euthanasia | archive-date = 21 August 2011}}</ref> This approach is included in Marvin Khol and Paul Kurtz's definition of it as "a mode or act of inducing or permitting death painlessly as a relief from suffering".<ref>{{cite book | last1 = Kohl | first1 = Marvin | last2 = Kurtz | first2 = Paul | year = 1975 | chapter = A Plea for Beneficient Euthanasia | editor = Kohl, Marvin | title = Beneficient Euthanasia | publisher = Prometheus Books | location = Buffalo, New York | page = 94 }}, quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.</ref> Counterexamples can be given: such definitions may encompass killing a person suffering from an incurable disease for personal gain (such as to claim an inheritance), and commentators such as ] and ] have argued that doing so would constitute "murder simpliciter" rather than euthanasia.<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979" />
==History==
The term euthanasia comes from the Greek words “eu” and “thanatos” which combined means “good death”. ] mentions euthanasia in the ], which was written between 400 and 300 B.C. The original Oath states: “To please no one will I prescribe a deadly drug nor give advice which may cause his death.”<ref name="history"> http://www.euthanasia.com/historyeuthanasia.html </ref> Despite this, the ancient Greeks and Romans generally did not believe that life needed to be preserved at any cost and were, in consequence, tolerant of suicide in cases where no relief could be offered to the dying or, in the case of the ] and ], where a person no longer cared for his life.<ref name="plato"/><ref>See ]</ref>


The third element incorporated into many definitions is that of intentionality: the death must be intended rather than accidental, and the intent of the action must be a "merciful death".<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979" /> Michael Wreen argued that "the principal thing that distinguishes euthanasia from intentional killing simpliciter is the agent's motive: it must be a good motive insofar as the good of the person killed is concerned."<ref name="Wreen1988p639">{{Cite journal| last = Wreen | first = Michael | year = 1988 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | jstor = 2108012 | journal = ] | volume = 48 | doi = 10.2307/2108012 | issue = 4 | pages = 637–53 | pmid = 11652547 }}</ref> Similarly, Heather Draper speaks to the importance of motive, arguing that "the motive forms a crucial part of arguments for euthanasia, because it must be in the best interests of the person on the receiving end."<ref name="Draper1998" /> Definitions such as those offered by the ] ] on ] take this path, where euthanasia is defined as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, to relieve intractable suffering."<ref name="Harris-2001"/> Beauchamp and Davidson also highlight ]'s "an act of euthanasia is one in which one person&nbsp;... (A) kills another person (B) for the benefit of the second person, who actually does benefit from being killed".<ref>{{cite book | last1 = Brody | first1 = Baruch | year = 1975 | chapter = Voluntary Euthanasia and the Law | editor = Kohl, Marvin | title = Beneficient Euthanasia | publisher = Prometheus Books | location = Buffalo, New York | page = 94 }}, quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.</ref>
The ] from the 1300’s until today also disapproved of both suicide and assisting suicide. However, in the 1500s, ], in describing a utopian community, envisaged such a community as one that would facilitate the death of those whose lives had become burdensome as a result of "torturing and lingering pain".<ref name="plato"/><ref>See Humphry and Wickett (1986:8-10) on More, Montaigne, Donne, and Bacon.</ref>


Draper argued that any definition of euthanasia must incorporate four elements: an agent and a subject; an intention; causal proximity, such that the actions of the agent lead to the outcome; and an outcome. Based on this, she offered a definition incorporating those elements, stating that euthanasia "must be defined as death that results from the intention of one person to kill another person, using the most gentle and painless means possible, that is motivated solely by the best interests of the person who dies."<ref name="Draper1998p176">{{cite book | last = Draper | first = Heather | year = 1998 | chapter = Euthanasia | editor = Chadwick, Ruth | title = Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics | volume = 2 | publisher = Academic Press | page = 176 }}</ref> Prior to Draper, Beauchamp and Davidson had also offered a definition that included these elements. Their definition specifically discounts ]es to distinguish between abortions and euthanasia:<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979p303">{{Cite journal| last1 = Beauchamp | first1 = Tom L. | author-link1 = Tom Beauchamp | last2 = Davidson | first2 = Arnold I. | author-link2 = Arnold Davidson | year = 1979 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | journal = ] | volume = 4 | issue = 3 | page = 303| doi = 10.1093/jmp/4.3.294 | pmid=501249}}</ref>
===Modern history===


{{blockquote|In summary, we have argued&nbsp;... that the death of a human being, A, is an instance of euthanasia if and only if (1) A's death is intended by at least one other human being, B, where B is either the cause of death or a causally relevant feature of the event resulting in death (whether by action or by omission); (2) there is either sufficient current evidence for B to believe that A is acutely suffering or irreversibly comatose, or there is sufficient current evidence related to A's present condition such that one or more known causal laws supports B's belief that A will be in a condition of acute suffering or irreversible comatoseness; (3) (a) B's primary reason for intending A's death is cessation of A's (actual or predicted future) suffering or irreversible comatoseness, where B does not intend A's death for a different primary reason, though there may be other relevant reasons, and (b) there is sufficient current evidence for either A or B that causal means to A's death will not produce any more suffering than would be produced for A if B were not to intervene; (4) the causal means to the event of A's death are chosen by A or B to be as painless as possible, unless either A or B has an overriding reason for a more painful causal means, where the reason for choosing the latter causal means does not conflict with the evidence in 3b; (5) A is a nonfetal organism.<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979p304">{{Cite journal| last1 = Beauchamp | first1 = Tom L. | author-link1 = Tom Beauchamp | last2 = Davidson | first2 = Arnold I. | author-link2 = Arnold Davidson | year = 1979 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | journal = ] | volume = 4 | issue = 3 | page = 304| doi = 10.1093/jmp/4.3.294 | pmid=501249}}</ref>}}
Since the 19th Century, euthanasia has sparked intermittent debates and activism in North America and Europe. According to medical historian Ezekiel Emanuel, it was the availability of anesthesia that ushered in the modern era of euthanasia. In 1828, the first known anti-euthanasia law in the United States was passed in the state of ], with many other localities and states following suit over a period of several years.<ref name="euth-ppt"> (] presentation), Euthanasia.com. ''"The earliest American statute explicitly to outlaw assisting suicide was enacted in New York in 1828, Act of Dec. 10, 1828, ch. 20, §4, 1828 N. Y. Laws 19 (codified at 2 N. Y. Rev. Stat. pt. 4, ch. 1, tit. 2, art. 1, §7, p. 661 (1829)), and many of the new States and Territories followed New York's example. Marzen 73-74."'' Retrieved June 16, 2007.</ref> After the civil war, voluntary euthanasia was promoted by advocates, including some doctors.<ref>Humphry and Wickett 1986:11-12, Emanuel 2004.</ref> Support peaked around the turn of the century in the U.S. and then grew again in the 1930’s.


Wreen, in part responding to Beauchamp and Davidson, offered a six-part definition:
Euthanasia societies were formed in England in 1935 and in the U.S.A. in 1938 to promote aggressive euthanasia. Although euthanasia legislation did not pass in the U.S. or England, in 1937, doctor-assisted euthanasia was declared legal in Switzerland as long as the person ending the life has nothing to gain.<ref name="bartleby"/><ref name="history"/> During this period, euthanasia proposals were sometimes mixed with ].<ref>''Merciful Release'' and other sources...</ref> While some proponents focused on voluntary euthanasia for the terminally ill, others expressed interest in involuntary euthanasia for certain eugenic motivations (e.g., mentally "defective").<ref name="eug-archive"></ref> During this same era, meanwhile, U.S. court trials tackled cases involving critically ill people who requested physician assistance in dying as well as “mercy killings”, such as by parents of their severely disabled children.<ref>Kamisar 1977</ref>


{{blockquote|Person A committed an act of euthanasia if and only if (1) A killed B or let her die; (2) A intended to kill B; (3) the intention specified in (2) was at least partial cause of the action specified in (1); (4) the causal journey from the intention specified in (2) to the action specified in (1) is more or less in accordance with A's plan of action; (5) A's killing of B is a voluntary action; (6) the motive for the action specified in (1), the motive standing behind the intention specified in (2), is the good of the person killed.<ref name="Wreen1988pp637-640">{{Cite journal| last = Wreen | first = Michael | year = 1988 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | jstor = 2108012 | journal = ] | volume = 48 | doi = 10.2307/2108012 | issue = 4 | pages = 637–40 | pmid = 11652547 }}</ref>}}
Prior to World War II, the Nazis carried out a controversial and now-condemned euthanasia program. In 1939, Nazis, in what was code-named ], involuntarily euthanized children under three who exhibited mental retardation, physical deformity, or other debilitating problems whom they considered "life unworthy of life”. This program was later extended to include older children and adults.<ref name="history"/>


Wreen also considered a seventh requirement: "(7) The good specified in (6) is, or at least includes, the avoidance of evil", although, as Wreen noted in the paper, he was not convinced that the restriction was required.<ref name="Wreen1988p645">{{Cite journal| last = Wreen | first = Michael | year = 1988 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | jstor = 2108012 | journal = ] | volume = 48 | doi = 10.2307/2108012 | issue = 4 | pages = 637–53 | pmid = 11652547 }}</ref>
===Post-War history===


In discussing his definition, Wreen noted the difficulty of justifying euthanasia when faced with the notion of the subject's "]". In response, Wreen argued that euthanasia has to be voluntary and that "involuntary euthanasia is, as such, a great wrong".<ref name="Wreen1988p645"/> Other commentators incorporate consent more directly into their definitions. For example, in a discussion of euthanasia presented in 2003 by the European Association of Palliative Care (EPAC) Ethics Task Force, the authors offered: "Medicalized killing of a person without the person's consent, whether nonvoluntary (where the person is unable to consent) or involuntary (against the person's will), is not euthanasia: it is murder. Hence, euthanasia can be voluntary only."<ref name="Materstvedt2003">{{Cite journal| year = 2003 | title = Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a view from an EAPC Ethics Task Force |journal = ] | volume = 17 | pages = 97–101 | doi = 10.1191/0269216303pm673oa | pmid = 12701848 |author1=Materstvedt, Lars Johan |author2=Clark, David |author3=Ellershaw, John |author4=Førde, Reidun |author5=Boeck Gravgaard, Anne-Marie |author6=Müller-Busch, Christof |author7=Porta i Sales, Josep |author8=Rapin, Charles-Henri | issue = 2| citeseerx = 10.1.1.514.5064 | s2cid = 1498250 }}</ref> Although the EPAC Ethics Task Force argued that both ] and ] could not be included in the definition of euthanasia, there is discussion in the literature about excluding one but not the other.<ref name="Wreen1988p645" />
Due to outrage over Nazi euthanasia, in the 1940s and 1950s there was very little public support for euthanasia, especially for any involuntary, eugenics-based proposals. Catholic church leaders, among others, began speaking against euthanasia as a violation of the ]. (Nevertheless, owing to its ], Catholic moral theology did leave room for shortening life with pain-killers and what would could be characterized as passive euthanasia.<ref>Papal statements 1956-1957 and Gerald Kelly</ref>) On the other hand, judges were often lenient in mercy-killing cases. <ref>Humphrey and Wickett, ch.4. See also, Kamisar and ] case.</ref> During this period, prominent proponents of euthanasia included ] (''The Sanctity of Life and the Criminal Law'') and clergyman ] ("Morals and medicine"). By the 1960s, advocacy for a right-to-die approach to voluntary euthanasia increased.


===Historical use===
A key turning point in the debate over voluntary euthanasia (and physician assisted dying), at least in the United States, was the public furor over the case of ]. The Quinlan case paved the way for legal protection of voluntary passive euthanasia.<ref>For the U.K. see the Bland case.</ref> In 1977, California legalized living wills and other states soon followed suit.
"Euthanasia" has had different meanings depending on usage. The first apparent usage of the term "euthanasia" belongs to the historian ], who described how the Emperor ], "dying quickly and without suffering in the arms of his wife, Livia, experienced the 'euthanasia' he had wished for."<ref>Philippe Letellier, chapter: ''History and Definition of a Word,'' in ''Euthanasia: Ethical and Human Aspects'' By ]</ref> The word "euthanasia" was first used in a medical context by ] in the 17th century to refer to an easy, painless, happy death, during which it was a "physician's responsibility to alleviate the 'physical sufferings' of the body." Bacon referred to an "outward euthanasia"—the term "outward" he used to distinguish from a spiritual concept—the euthanasia "which regards the preparation of the soul."<ref>Francis Bacon: ''The Major Works by Francis Bacon,'' edited by Brian Vickers, p. 630.</ref>


==Classification==
In 1990, Dr. ], a Michigan physician, became infamous for encouraging and assisting people in committing suicide which resulted in a Michigan law against the practice in 1992. Kevorkian was tried and convicted in 1999 for a murder displayed on television.<ref name="bartleby"/><ref name="history"/> In 1990, the Supreme Court approved the use of non-aggressive euthanasia.<ref> ] </ref>
Euthanasia may be classified into three types, according to whether a person gives ]: voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary.<ref>{{Cite journal|author=Perrett RW |title=Buddhism, euthanasia and the sanctity of life |journal=J Med Ethics |volume=22 |issue=5 |pages=309–13 |date=October 1996 |pmid=8910785 |pmc=1377066 |doi=10.1136/jme.22.5.309}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|author=LaFollette, Hugh |title=Ethics in practice: an anthology |publisher=Blackwell |location=Oxford |year=2002 |pages=25–26 |isbn=978-0-631-22834-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=o5peQpgSTTIC&pg=RA1-PA3-IA1}}</ref>


There is a debate within the medical and bioethics literature about whether or not the non-voluntary (and by extension, involuntary) killing of patients can be regarded as euthanasia, irrespective of intent or the patient's circumstances. In the definitions offered by Beauchamp and Davidson and, later, by Wreen, consent on the part of the patient was not considered one of their criteria, although it may have been required to justify euthanasia.<ref name="BeauchampDavidson1979"/><ref name="Wreen1988">{{Cite journal| last = Wreen | first = Michael | year = 1988 | title = The Definition of Euthanasia | jstor = 2108012 | journal = ] | volume = 48 | pages = 637–53 | doi = 10.2307/2108012 | issue = 4| pmid = 11652547 }}</ref> However, others see consent as essential.
In 1994, Oregon voters approved doctor-assisted suicide and the Supreme Court allowed such laws in 1997.<ref name="plato"/> The Bush administration failed in its attempt to use drug law to stop Oregon in 2001.<ref name="bartleby"/> In 1999, non-aggressive euthanasia was permitted in Texas.


===Voluntary euthanasia===
In 1993, the Netherlands decriminalized doctor-assisted suicide, and in 2002, restrictions were loosened. During that year, physician-assisted suicide was approved in Belgium. Australia's Northern Territory approved a euthanasia bill in 1995, but that was overturned by Australia’s Federal Parliament in 1997.<ref name="bartleby"/><ref name="plato"/><ref name="history"/>
{{see also|Right to die}}
] is conducted with the consent of the patient. Active voluntary euthanasia is legal in Belgium, Luxembourg and the Netherlands. Passive voluntary euthanasia is legal throughout the US per '']''. When the patient brings about their own death with the assistance of a physician, the term ] is often used instead. Assisted suicide is legal in Switzerland and the U.S. states of California, Oregon, Washington, Montana and Vermont.


===Non-voluntary euthanasia===
Most recently, amid government roadblocks and controversy, ], a Floridian who was in a vegetative state since 1990, had her feeding tube removed in 2005. Her husband had won the right to take her off life support, which he claimed she would want but was difficult to confirm as she had no living will and the rest of her family claimed otherwise.<ref name="bartleby"/>
] is conducted when the consent of the patient is unavailable. Examples include ], which is illegal worldwide but decriminalised under certain specific circumstances in the Netherlands under the ]. Passive forms of non-voluntary euthanasia (i.e. withholding treatment) are legal in a number of countries under specified conditions.


==Arguments for and against voluntary euthanasia== ===Involuntary euthanasia===
] is conducted against the will of the patient.
Since ], the debate over euthanasia in Western countries has centered on voluntary euthanasia (VE) within regulated health care systems. In some cases, judicial decisions, legislation, and regulations have made VE an explicit option for patients and their guardians.<ref>See ] below for specific examples</ref> Proponents and critics of such VE policies offer the following reasons for and against official voluntary euthanasia policies:


===Reasons given for voluntary euthanasia:=== ===Passive and active euthanasia===
Voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary types can be further divided into passive or active variants.<ref>{{Cite journal |doi=10.1056/NEJM197501092920206 |author=Rachels J |s2cid=46465710 |title=Active and passive euthanasia |journal=N. Engl. J. Med. |volume=292 |issue=2 |pages=78–80 |date=January 1975 |pmid=1109443}}</ref> Passive euthanasia entails the withholding treatment necessary for the continuance of life.<ref name="Harris-2001"/> Active euthanasia entails the use of lethal substances or forces (such as administering a ]), and is more controversial. While some authors consider these terms to be misleading and unhelpful, they are nonetheless commonly used. In some cases, such as the administration of increasingly necessary, but toxic doses of ], there is a debate whether or not to regard the practice as active or passive.<ref name="Harris-2001"/>
* Choice: Proponents of VE emphasize that choice is a fundamental principle for liberal democracies and free market systems.<ref name="plato"/>
* Quality of Life: The pain and suffering a person feels during a disease, even with pain relievers, can be incomprehensible to a person who has not gone through it. Even without considering the physical pain, it is often difficult for patients to overcome the emotional pain of losing their independence. <ref name="plato"/> Moreover, despite modern painkillers, there is little available to deal with the problem of 'breathlessness', which makes many ailing patients feel they will suffocate.<ref>http://findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_qn4158/is_19990513/ai_n14231958/pg_2</ref>
* Economic costs and human resources: Today in many countries there is a shortage of hospital space. The energy of doctors and hospital beds could be used for people whose lives could be saved instead of continuing the life of those who want to die which increases the general quality of care and shortens hospital waiting lists. It is a burden to keep people alive past the point they can contribute to society.<ref>See also ]</ref>
* Pressure: All the arguments against voluntary euthanasia can be used by society to form a terrible and continuing psychological pressure on people to continue living for years against their better judgement. One example of this pressure is the risky and painful methods that those who genuinely wish to die would otherwise need to use, such as hanging.
* ]: Currently many if not most euthanasia proponents and laws tend to favor the dying or very unhealthy for access to euthanasia. However some highly controversial proponents claim that access should be even more widely available. For example, from a sociobiological viewpoint, genetic relatives may seek to keep an individual alive (Kin Selection), even against the individual's will. This would be especially so for individuals who are not actually dying anyway. More liberal voluntary euthanasia policies would empower the individual to counteract any such biased interest on the part of relatives. {{Fact|date=May 2007}}


== History ==
===Reasons given against voluntary euthanasia:===
]'', by ] (1787), depicting Socrates preparing to drink ], following his conviction for corrupting the youth of ]]]
Euthanasia was practiced in ] and ]: for example, ] was employed as a means of hastening death on the island of ], a technique also employed in ]. Euthanasia, in the sense of the deliberate hastening of a person's death, was supported by ], ] and ] in the ancient world, although ] appears to have ], writing "I will not prescribe a deadly drug to please someone, nor give advice that may cause his death" (noting there is some debate in the literature about whether or not this was intended to encompass euthanasia).<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Mystakidou | first1 = Kyriaki | last2 = Parpa | first2 = Efi | last3 = Tsilika | first3 = Eleni | last4 = Katsouda | first4 = Emanuela | last5 = Vlahos | first5 = Lambros | year = 2005 | title = The Evolution of Euthanasia and Its Perceptions in Greek Culture and Civilization | journal = Perspectives in Biology and Medicine | volume = 48 | issue = 1 | pages = 97–98 | doi = 10.1353/pbm.2005.0013 | pmid = 15681882 | s2cid = 44600176 }}</ref><ref name="stolberg">{{cite journal | last = Stolberg | first = Michael | s2cid = 6150428 | year = 2007 | title = Active Euthanasia in Pre-ModernSociety, 1500–1800: Learned Debates and Popular Practices | journal = Social History of Medicine | volume = 20 | pages = 206–07 | issue = 2 | doi = 10.1093/shm/hkm034 | pmid = 18605325 }}</ref><ref name="Gesundheit2006p623"/>


=== Early modern period ===
* Professional role: Critics argue that VE could unduly compromise the professional roles of health care employees, especially doctors. They point out that European physicians of previous centuries traditionally swore some variation of the ], which in its ] excluded euthanasia: "To please no one will I prescribe a deadly drug nor give advice which may cause his death.." However, since the 1970s, this oath has largely ].
The term ''euthanasia'', in the earlier sense of supporting someone as they died, was used for the first time by ]. In his work, ''Euthanasia medica'', he chose this ancient Greek word and, in doing so, distinguished between ''euthanasia interior'', the preparation of the soul for death, and ''euthanasia exterior'', which was intended to make the end of life easier and painless, in exceptional circumstances by shortening life. That the ancient meaning of an easy death came to the fore again in the ] can be seen from its definition in the 18th century ]:
* Moral: Some people consider euthanasia of some or all types to be morally unacceptable.<ref name="plato">http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/euthanasia-voluntary/ An overview of voluntary euthanasia</ref> This view usually treats euthanasia to be a type of ] and voluntary euthanasia as a type of ], the morality of which is the subject of active debate.
* Theological: Voluntary euthanasia often has been rejected as a violation of the sanctity of human life. Specifically, some Christians argue that human life ultimately belongs to God, so that humans ought not make the choice to end life. Orthodox Judaism takes basically the same approach, however, it is more open minded, and does, given certain circumstances, allow for euthanasia to be exercised under passive or non-aggressive means. Accordingly, some theologians and other religious thinkers consider VE (and ] generally) as sinful acts, i.e. unjustified killings.<ref>See ]</ref>
* Feasibility of implementation: Euthanasia can only be considered "voluntary" if a patient is mentally competent to make the decision, i.e., has a rational understanding of options and consequences. ] can be difficult to determine or even define.<ref name="plato"/>
* Necessity: If there is some reason to believe the cause of a patient's illness or suffering is or will soon be curable, the correct action is sometimes considered to be attempting to bring about a cure or engage in palliative care.<ref name="plato"/>
* Wishes of Family: Family members often desire to spend as much time with their loved ones as possible before they die. Therefore, the wishes of the family may outweigh the patient's right to control his or her own life.
* Consent under pressure: Given the economic grounds for voluntary euthanasia (VE), critics of VE are concerned that patients may experience psychological pressure to consent to voluntary euthanasia rather than be a financial burden on their families. <ref>"Terminally ill patients often fear being a burden to others and may feel they ought to request euthanasia to relieve their relatives from distress." letter to the editor of the ''Financial Times'' by Dr David Jeffrey, published 11 Jan 2003.</ref> Even where health costs are mostly covered by public monies, as in various European counties, VE critics are concerned that hospital personnel would have an economic incentive to advise or pressure people toward euthanasia consent.<ref> "If euthanasia became socially acceptable, the sick would no longer be able to trust either doctors or their relatives: many of those earnestly counselling a painless, 'dignified' death would be doing so mainly on financial grounds. Euthanasia would become a euphemism for assisted murder." ''FT WEEKEND - THE FRONT LINE: Don't take liberties with the right to die'' by Michael Prowse, Financial Times, 4th Jan 2003 </ref> While VE proponents concede that personal and even socialized economic costs may add to the motivations for consent, they point out that health systems offer sufficient exceptions so as to relieve the pressure on hospital personnel.{{Fact|date=May 2007}}


<blockquote>Euthanasia: a very gentle and quiet death, which happens without painful convulsions. The word comes from ευ, ''bene'', well, and θανατος, ''mors'', death.<ref>''Zedlers Universallexikon'', Vol. 08, p. 1150, published 1732–54.</ref></blockquote>
== Euthanasia and the Law ==
{{main|Euthanasia and the Law}}
During the 20th Century, efforts to change government policies on euthanasia have met limited success in Western countries. Country policies are described ] in alphabetical order, followed by the exceptional case of ]. Euthanasia policies have also been developed by a variety of NGOs, most notably medical associations and advocacy organizations.


The concept of euthanasia in the sense of alleviating the process of death goes back to the medical historian ], who drew on Bacon's philosophical ideas. According to Marx, a doctor had a moral duty to ease the suffering of death through encouragement, support and mitigation using medication. Such an "alleviation of death" reflected the contemporary '']'', but was brought into the medical canon of responsibility for the first time by Marx. Marx also stressed the distinction of the theological care of the soul of sick people from the physical care and medical treatment by doctors.<ref>{{NDB|16|327|328|Marx, Karl, Mediziner|Markwart Michler|116814357}}</ref><ref>Helge Dvorak: ''Biographisches Lexikon der Deutschen Burschenschaft.'' Vol. I, Sub-vol. 4, Heidelberg, 2000, pp. 40–41.</ref>
== Euthanasia and Religion ==
===Roman Catholic policy===
The Catholic policy on euthanasia rests on several core principles of Catholic ethics, including the ], the ] of the human person, concomitant ], due ] in ] remedies, the unavoidability of death, and the importance of ].<ref name="vatican-euth" /> The most important official Catholic statement is the 1980 ''Declaration on Euthanasia'' issued by the ].<ref name="vatican-euth">
{{cite web
|url = http://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19800505_euthanasia_en.html
|title = Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith. "Declaration on Euthanasia," May 5, 1980}}</ref>


Euthanasia in its modern sense has always been strongly opposed in the ] tradition. ] opposed both and argued that the practice of euthanasia contradicted our natural human instincts of survival,<ref> {{webarchive|url=http://webarchive.loc.gov/all/20120705164631/http://euthanasia.procon.org/view.resource.php?resourceID=000130 |date=5 July 2012 }} Euthanasia – ProCon.org. Last updated on: 23 July 2013. Retrieved 4 May 2014.</ref> as did Francois Ranchin (1565–1641), a French physician and professor of medicine, and Michael Boudewijns (1601–1681), a physician and teacher.<ref name="stolberg"/>{{rp|208}}<ref name="Gesundheit2006p623">{{cite journal | last1 = Gesundheit | first1 = Benjamin | last2 = Steinberg | first2 = Avraham | last3 = Glick | first3 = Shimon | last4 = Or | first4 = Reuven | last5 = Jotkovitz | first5 = Alan | year = 2006 | title= Euthanasia: An Overview and the Jewish Perspective | journal = ] | volume = 24 | doi = 10.1080/07357900600894898 | pmid = 16982468 | issue = 6 | pages = 621–9 | s2cid = 8906449 }}</ref> Other voices argued for euthanasia, such as ] in 1624,<ref>{{cite journal | last = Mannes | first = Marya | year = 1975 | title = Euthanasia vs. the Right to Life | journal = Baylor Law Review | volume = 27 | page = 69 }}</ref> and euthanasia continued to be practised. In 1678, the publication of Caspar Questel's ''De pulvinari morientibus non-subtrahend'', ("''On the pillow of which the dying should not be deprived''"), initiated debate on the topic. Questel described various customs which were employed at the time to hasten the death of the dying, (including the sudden removal of a pillow, which was believed to accelerate death), and argued against their use, as doing so was "against the laws of God and Nature".<ref name="stolberg"/>{{rp|209–211}} This view was shared by others who followed, including Philipp Jakob Spener, Veit Riedlin and ].<ref name="stolberg"/>{{rp|211}} Despite opposition, euthanasia continued to be practised, involving techniques such as bleeding, suffocation, and removing people from their beds to be placed on the cold ground.<ref name="stolberg"/>{{rp|211–214}}
In ], official pronouncements tend to strongly oppose ''active euthanasia,'' whether voluntary or not.<ref>"...no one is permitted to ask for this act of killing, either for himself or herself or for another person entrusted to his or her care, nor can he or she consent to it, either explicitly or implicitly. nor can any authority legitimately recommend or permit such an action."</ref>, while allowing dying to proceed without medical interventions that would be considered "extraordinary" or "disproportionate." Though the Church tends not to use the term, this policy might be equated to a limited form of passive euthanasia, although Church statements can be ambivalent. The ''Declaration on Euthanasia'' states that: <blockquote>"When inevitable death is imminent... it is permitted in conscience to take the decision to refuse forms of treatment that would only secure a precarious and burdensome prolongation of life, so long as the normal care due to a sick person in similar cases is not interrupted."</blockquote>The Declaration concludes that doctors, beyond providing medical skill, must above all provide patients "with the comfort of boundless kindness and heartfelt charity".


Suicide and euthanasia became more accepted during the ].<ref name="Gesundheit2006p623" /> ] wrote of euthanasia in '']'', although it is not clear if More was intending to endorse the practice.<ref name="stolberg"/>{{rp|208–209}} Other cultures have taken different approaches: for example, in Japan suicide has not traditionally been viewed as a sin, as it is used in cases of honor, and accordingly, the perceptions of euthanasia are different from those in other parts of the world.<ref>{{cite journal | last = Otani | first = Izumi | year = 2010 | title = "Good Manner of Dying" as a Normative Concept: "Autocide", "Granny Dumping" and Discussions on Euthanasia/Death with Dignity in Japan | journal = International Journal of Japanese Sociology | volume = 19 | issue = 1 | doi = 10.1111/j.1475-6781.2010.01136.x | pages = 49–63 }}</ref>
===Protestant policies===


===Beginnings of the contemporary euthanasia debate===
Protestant denominations vary widely on their approach to euthanasia and physician assisted death. Since the 1970s, Evangelical churches have worked with Roman Catholics on a ] approach, though the Evangelicals may be adopting a more exceptionless opposition. While liberal Protestant denominations have largely eschewed euthanasia, many individual advocates (e.g., ]) and euthanasia society activists have been Protestant clergy and laity. As physician assisted dying has obtained greater legal support, some liberal Protestant denominations have offered religious arguments and support for limited forms of euthanasia.{{Fact|date=May 2007}}
In the mid-1800s, the use of ] to treat "the pains of death" emerged, with ] recommending its use in 1848. A similar use of ] was revealed by Joseph Bullar in 1866. However, in neither case was it recommended that the use should be to hasten death. In 1870 Samuel Williams, a schoolteacher, initiated the contemporary euthanasia debate through a speech given at the Birmingham Speculative Club in England, which was subsequently published in a one-off publication entitled ''Essays of the Birmingham Speculative Club'', the collected works of a number of members of an amateur philosophical society.<ref name="Emanuel1994"/>{{rp|794}} Williams' proposal was to use chloroform to deliberately hasten the death of terminally ill patients:


{{blockquote|That in all cases of hopeless and painful illness, it should be the recognized duty of the medical attendant, whenever so desired by the patient, to administer chloroform or such other anaesthetic as may by-and-bye supersede chloroform – so as to destroy consciousness at once, and put the sufferer to a quick and painless death; all needful precautions being adopted to prevent any possible abuse of such duty; and means being taken to establish, beyond the possibility of doubt or question, that the remedy was applied at the express wish of the patient.|Samuel Williams (1872) | ''Euthanasia'' Williams and Northgate: London.<ref name="Emanuel1994"/>{{rp|794}} }}
===Jewish policies===
Not unlike the trend among Protestants, Jewish movements have become divided over euthanasia since the 1970s. Generally, ] thinkers oppose voluntary euthanasia, often vigorously,<ref>E.g., ], ]</ref> though there is some backing for voluntary passive euthanasia in limited circumstances.<ref>E.g., see writings of ], ], ], ]. See also the article by ] </ref> Likewise, within the ] movement, there has been increasing support for passive euthanasia (PAD)<ref>See ] and, for earlier speculation, ].</ref> In ] ], the preponderance of anti-euthanasia sentiment has shifted in recent years to increasing support for certain passive euthanasia (PAD) options.{{Fact|date=May 2007}}


The essay was favourably reviewed in '']'', but an editorial against the essay appeared in '']''.<ref name="Kemp">{{Cite book |publisher = Manchester University Press |isbn = 978-0-7190-6124-0 |title = Merciful Release |author = Nick Kemp |date = 7 September 2002 |id = 0719061245|ol = 10531689M }}</ref> From there it proved to be influential, and other writers came out in support of such views: Lionel Tollemache wrote in favour of euthanasia, as did ], the essayist and reformer who later became involved with the ], considering it a duty to society to "die voluntarily and painlessly" when one reaches the point of becoming a 'burden'.<ref name="Kemp" /><ref name="Dowbiggin2007">{{cite book|author=Ian Dowbiggin|title=A Concise History of Euthanasia: Life, Death, God, and Medicine|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CNigO7gMGkUC&pg=PA62|date=March 2007|publisher=Rowman & Littlefield|isbn=978-0-7425-3111-6|pages=51, 62–64}}</ref> ''Popular Science'' analyzed the issue in May 1873, assessing both sides of the argument.<ref>{{Cite journal | url = https://books.google.com/books?id=-B8DAAAAMBAJ&pg=PA90 | title = Popular Science | last1 = Corporation | first1 = Bonnier | date = May 1873}}</ref> Kemp notes that at the time, medical doctors did not participate in the discussion; it was "essentially a philosophical enterprise&nbsp;... tied inextricably to a number of objections to the Christian doctrine of the sanctity of human life".<ref name="Kemp" />
===Islamic policies===
Islam categorically forbids all forms of suicide and anything associated with suicide. It is forbidden for a ] to willfully plan, or come to know, the time of his own death in advance. If a ] were to decide in advance when he himself would die, then it is believed that this would be an insult to ]. All this is stated, for example, in Fredrick Forsyth's novel, ]. In fact, a Muslim who commits suicide is not even given burial rights. The precedent for all of this thinking comes from the ] having absolutely refused to bless the body of a person who had committed suicide, despite the fact that the person killed himself to relieve severe pain from incurable disease.{{Fact|date=September 2007}}


=== Early euthanasia movement in the United States ===
===Dharmic Religions===
{{Main|Euthanasia in the United States}}


], {{Circa|1913}}, the first prominent American to argue for permitting suicide in cases of chronic illness]]
In ], a monk can be expelled for praising the advantages of death, even if they simply describe the miseries of life or the bliss of the after-life in a way that might inspire a person to commit suicide or pine away to death. In caring for the terminally ill, one is forbidden to treat a patient so as to bring on death faster than would occur if the disease were allowed to run its natural course.<ref>], </ref>
The rise of the euthanasia movement in the United States coincided with the so-called ], a time of social and technological change that encompassed an "individualistic conservatism that praised laissez-faire economics, ], and ]", along with major ], industrialisation and conflict between corporations and labour unions.<ref name="Emanuel1994"/>{{rp|794}} It was also the period in which the modern hospital system was developed, which has been seen as a factor in the emergence of the euthanasia debate.<ref>{{cite journal | last = Pappas | first = Demetra | year = 1996 | title = Recent historical perspectives regarding medical euthanasia and physician assisted suicide | journal = British Medical Bulletin | volume = 52 | pages = 386–87 | issue = 2 | doi = 10.1093/oxfordjournals.bmb.a011554 | pmid=8759237| doi-access = free }}</ref>


] argued for euthanasia, stating in 1894 that where someone is suffering from a terminal illness, such as terminal cancer, they should have a right to end their pain through suicide. ] offered a similar approach, although, unlike Ingersoll, Adler did not reject religion. In fact, he argued from an ] framework. In 1891, Adler argued that those suffering from overwhelming pain should have the right to commit suicide, and, furthermore, that it should be permissible for a doctor to assist – thus making Adler the first "prominent American" to argue for suicide in cases where people were suffering from chronic illness.<ref name="Dowbiggin">{{cite book | last = Dowbiggin | first = Ian | author-link = Ian Dowbiggin | year = 2003 | title = A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America | publisher = ] | isbn = 978-0-19-515443-6 | pages = | url = https://archive.org/details/mercifulendeutha00dowb_0/page/10 }}</ref> Both Ingersoll and Adler argued for voluntary euthanasia of adults suffering from terminal ailments.<ref name="Dowbiggin"/> Dowbiggin argues that by breaking down prior moral objections to euthanasia and suicide, Ingersoll and Adler enabled others to stretch the definition of euthanasia.<ref name="Dowbiggin2003p13">{{cite book | last = Dowbiggin | first = Ian | author-link = Ian Dowbiggin | year = 2003 | title = A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America | publisher = ] | isbn = 978-0-19-515443-6 | page = | url = https://archive.org/details/mercifulendeutha00dowb_0/page/13 }}</ref>
==Euthanasia protocol==
{{Seealso|Lethal injection#Euthanasia protocol}}
[[Image:Euthanasia machine (Australia).JPG|thumb|240px|A machine that can facilitate euthanasia through heavy doses of drugs. The laptop screen leads the user through a series of steps and questions to ensure they are fully prepared. The final injection is then done by motors controlled by the computer.<ref>
{{cite web
|url = http://www.smh.com.au/articles/2003/01/10/1041990085855.html
|title = Nitschke suicide machine confiscated |date = 2003-01-10 |publisher = ]}}</ref>]]
Euthanasia can be accomplished either through an oral, intravenous, or intramuscular administration of drugs. In individuals who are incapable of swallowing lethal doses of medication, an intravenous route is preferred. The following is a Dutch protocol for parenteral (intravenous) administration to obtain euthanasia:


The first attempt to legalise euthanasia took place in the United States, when ] introduced legislation into the ] of ] in 1906.<ref name="Appel2004">{{cite journal | last = Appel | first = Jacob | author-link = Jacob M. Appel | year = 2004 | title = A Duty to Kill? A Duty to Die? Rethinking the Euthanasia Controversy of 1906 | journal = Bulletin of the History of Medicine | volume = 78 | issue = 3 | pages = 610–34 | doi = 10.1353/bhm.2004.0106 | pmid=15356372| s2cid = 24991992 }}</ref>{{rp|614}} Hunt did so at the behest of ], a wealthy heiress who was a major figure in the euthanasia movement during the early 20th century in the United States. Hall had watched her mother die after an extended battle with ], and had dedicated herself to ensuring that others would not have to endure the same suffering. Towards this end she engaged in an extensive letter writing campaign, recruited ] and ], and organised a debate on euthanasia at the annual meeting of the ] in 1905 – described by ] as the first significant public debate on the topic in the 20th century.<ref name="Appel2004"/>{{rp|614–616}}
Intravenous administration is the most reliable and rapid way to accomplish euthanasia and therefore can be safely recommended. A coma is first induced by intravenous administration of 20 mg/kg ] (Nesdonal) in a small volume (10 ml physiological saline). Then a triple intravenous dose of a non-depolarizing neuromuscular ] is given, such as 20 mg ] (Pavulon) or 20 mg ] (Norcuron). The muscle relaxant should preferably be given intravenously, in order to ensure optimal availability. Only for pancuronium bromide (Pavulon) are there substantial indications that the agent may also be given intramuscularly in a dosage of 40 mg.<ref>
{{cite web
|url = http://www.wweek.com/html/euthanasics.html
|title = Administration and Compounding Of Euthanasic Agents}}</ref>


Hunt's bill called for the administration of an ] to bring about a patient's death, so long as the person is of lawful age and sound mind, and was suffering from a fatal injury, an irrevocable illness, or great physical pain. It also required that the case be heard by a physician, required informed consent in front of three witnesses, and required the attendance of three physicians who had to agree that the patient's recovery was impossible. A motion to reject the bill outright was voted down, but the bill failed to pass, 79 to 23.<ref name="Emanuel1994">{{cite journal | last = Emanuel | first = Ezekiel | author-link = Ezekiel Emanuel | year = 1994 | title = The history of euthanasia debates in the United States and Britain | journal = Annals of Internal Medicine | volume = 121 | page = 796 | issue = 10 | doi = 10.7326/0003-4819-121-10-199411150-00010 | pmid = 7944057 | citeseerx = 10.1.1.732.724 | s2cid = 20754659 }}</ref>{{rp|796}}<ref name="Appel2004"/>{{rp|618–619}}
With regards to nonvoluntary euthanasia, the cases where the person could consent but was not asked are often viewed differently from those where the person could not consent. Some people raise issues regarding stereotypes of disability that can lead to non-disabled or less disabled people overestimating the person's suffering, or assuming it to be unchangeable when it could be changed. For example, many ] advocates responded to ] by pointing out that her parents had refused a hip surgery that could have greatly reduced or eliminated the physical pain Tracy experienced. Also, they point out that a severely disabled person need not be in emotional pain at their situation, and claim that the emotional pain, if present, is due to societal prejudice rather than the disability, analogous to a person of a particular ethnicity wanting to die because they have internalized negative stereotypes about their ethnic background. Another example of this is Keith McCormick, a New Zealander Paralympian who was "mercy-killed" by his caregiver, and Matthew Sutton.<ref>
{{cite web
|url = http://www.nzherald.co.nz/search/story.cfm?storyid=0002EB73-8358-1464-B02B83027AF1010E
|title = NZ Herald Story}}
<!----- broken link -----></ref><ref>
{{cite web
|url = http://www.abc.net.au/news/newsitems/200704/s1889400.htm
|title = Parents walk free after killing son |date = 2007-04-04 |publisher = ] News Online}}</ref>


Along with the Ohio euthanasia proposal, in 1906 Assemblyman Ross Gregory introduced a proposal to permit euthanasia to the ]. However, the Iowa legislation was broader in scope than that offered in Ohio. It allowed for the death of any person of at least ten years of age who suffered from an ailment that would prove fatal and cause extreme pain, should they be of sound mind and express a desire to artificially hasten their death. In addition, it allowed for infants to be euthanised if they were sufficiently deformed, and permitted guardians to request euthanasia on behalf of their wards. The proposed legislation also imposed penalties on physicians who refused to perform euthanasia when requested: a 6–12-month prison term and a fine of between $200 and $1,000. The proposal proved to be controversial.<ref name="Appel2004"/>{{rp|619–621}} It engendered considerable debate and failed to pass, having been withdrawn from consideration after being passed to the Committee on Public Health.<ref name="Appel2004"/>{{rp|623}}
With regards to voluntary euthanasia, many people argue that 'equal access' should apply to access to suicide as well, so therefore disabled people who cannot kill themselves should have access to voluntary euthanasia.


After 1906 the euthanasia debate reduced in intensity, resurfacing periodically, but not returning to the same level of debate until the 1930s in the United Kingdom.<ref name="Emanuel1994"/>{{rp|796}}
Others respond to this argument by pointing out that if a nondisabled person attempts suicide, all measures possible are taken to save their lives. Suicidal people are often given involuntary medical treatment so that they will not die. This argument states that it is due to societal prejudice, namely that disabled people are of lower worth and that any unhappiness must be due to the disability, which results in greater support of voluntary euthanasia by disabled people than suicide by nondisabled people.'''


Euthanasia opponent ] argues that the early membership of the ] (ESA) reflected how many perceived euthanasia at the time, often seeing it as a eugenics matter rather than an issue concerning individual rights.<ref name="Dowbiggin"/> Dowbiggin argues that not every eugenist joined the ESA "solely for eugenic reasons", but he postulates that there were clear ideological connections between the eugenics and euthanasia movements.<ref name="Dowbiggin"/>
==Euthanasia in the arts==
The films '']'' and '']'', as well as the book '']'', depict instances of government-sponsored euthanasia in order to strengthen their dystopian themes. The protagonist of '']'' is a brutually mutilated war veteran whose request for euthanasia furthers the work's anti-war message.


===1930s in Britain===
The recent films '']'' and '']'' argue more directly in favor of euthanasia by illustrating the suffering of their protagonists. These films have provoked debate and controversy in their home countries of Spain and the United States respectively.
The ] was founded in 1935 by ] (now called Dignity in Dying). The movement campaigned for the legalisation of euthanasia in Great Britain.


In January 1936, ] was given a fatal dose of morphine and ] to hasten his death. At the time he was suffering from cardio-respiratory failure, and the decision to end his life was made by his physician, ].<ref>{{cite journal | last = Ramsay | first = J H R | date = 28 May 2011 | title = A king, a doctor, and a convenient death | journal = ] | volume = 308 | issue = 1445 | pmid = 11644545 | doi = 10.1136/bmj.308.6941.1445 | page = 1445 | pmc = 2540387 }}</ref> Although this event was kept a secret for over 50 years, the death of George V coincided with proposed legislation in the ] to legalise euthanasia.<ref>{{cite journal | last = Gurney | first = Edward | year = 1972 | title = Is There a Right to Die – A Study of the Law of Euthanasia | journal = Cumberland-Samford Law Review | volume = 3 | page = 237 }}</ref>
A recurring character in ] by ] is a former war doctor who specializes in euthanasia. However, he is frequently prevented when the protagonist saves the patient instead.


=== Nazi Euthanasia Program ===
In the 1997 film "Critical Care," directed by Sidney Lumet, the plot centers around a doctor who is caught up in a complex lawsuit. The lawsuit involves the two daughters of the doctor's patient. One daughter, an empty-headed model, is trying to have her father be allowed to die. Her sister, who is pretending to be an Evangelical Christian, is trying to keep the father alive. It turns out that, corresponding to whether or not the father lives past a certain date, one of the daughters will receive her father's entire estate. In the end, the doctor resolves the issue by making the women split the money, allowing him to be unbiased in his decision to allow euthanasia or not. Ultimately, he allows his patient to die.
{{main|Aktion T4|Child euthanasia in Nazi Germany}}
], where over 18,000 people were killed]]
A 24 July 1939 killing of a severely disabled infant in ] was described in a ] "Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline" as the first "state-sponsored euthanasia".<ref name="July24"/> Parties that consented to the killing included Hitler's office, the parents, and the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses.<ref name="July24"> {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110805144040/http://www.bbc.co.uk/history/interactive/timelines/nazi_genocide_timeline/index_embed.shtml |date=5 August 2011 }} '']'' Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The first state-sanctioned euthanasia is carried out, after Hitler receives a petition from a child's parents, asking for the life of their severely disabled infant to be ended. This happens after the case has been considered by Hitler's office and by the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses, whose 'experts' have laid down the basis for the removal of disabled children to special 'paediatric clinics'. Here they can be either starved to death or given lethal injections. At least 5,200 infants will eventually be killed through this programme".</ref> '']'' noted that the killing of the disabled infant—whose name was ], born blind, with missing limbs, subject to convulsions, and reportedly "an idiot"— provided "the rationale for a secret Nazi decree that led to 'mercy killings' of almost 300,000 mentally and physically handicapped people".<ref name="casek1">{{Cite news|url=https://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/germany/1443967/Named-the-baby-boy-who-was-Nazis-first-euthanasia-victim.html|title=Named: the baby boy who was Nazis' first euthanasia victim|author=Irene Zoech|website=Telegraph.co.uk|access-date=4 July 2017|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170908201139/http://www.telegraph.co.uk/news/worldnews/europe/germany/1443967/Named-the-baby-boy-who-was-Nazis-first-euthanasia-victim.html|archive-date=8 September 2017|date=11 October 2003}}</ref> While Kretchmar's killing received parental consent, most of the 5,000 to 8,000 children killed afterwards were forcibly taken from their parents.<ref name="July24"/><ref name="casek1"/>


The "euthanasia campaign" of mass murder gathered momentum on 14 January 1940 when the "handicapped" were killed with gas vans and at killing centres, eventually leading to the deaths of 70,000 adult Germans.<ref name=January14> {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110805144040/http://www.bbc.co.uk/history/interactive/timelines/nazi_genocide_timeline/index_embed.shtml |date=5 August 2011 }} '']'' Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The 'euthanasia campaign' gathers momentum in Germany, as six special killing centres and gas vans, under an organisation code-named T4, are used in the murder of 'handicapped' adults. Over 70,000 Germans will eventually be killed in this act of mass murder – it is the first time poison bas will be used for such a purpose".</ref> was a campaign of ] by ] in ]. Its code name ] is derived from {{lang|de|]}}&nbsp;4, a street address of the Chancellery department which recruited and paid personnel associated with the program.<ref name="casek1" /> Professor ], author of ''The Nazi Doctors'' and a leading authority on the T4 program, contrasts this program with what he considers to be a genuine euthanasia. He explains that the Nazi version of "euthanasia" was based on the work of ], who published ''The Right to Death'' (Das Recht auf den Tod) in 1895. Lifton writes:
== See also ==
<!-- Please ensure links directly related to this topic and not already in the article or death template below -->
*], listing key sources in an anthology
*]
*]
*]
*]
*]
*Dr ], ], ] doctor, tried for murder in 1957 but claimed euthanasia. Acquitted.
*] - President of the World Federation of Right to Die Societies.
*]
*]
*], author, vice-president of EXIT (now the Voluntary Euthanasia Society).
*] (book)
*] (book by Jonathon Kellerman)
*] - Assists in the Japanese ritual ] (suicide)
*] and ] - Cases of ]
*] - Founder of the Voluntary Euthanasia Legalisation Society in Great Britain
*] - bioethicist, ]
*]
*]
*] - Nazi Germany's program to kill disabled people, justified as "euthanasia"
*] - physician to ], to whom he gave a lethal injection.


<blockquote>Jost argued that control over the death of the individual must ultimately belong to the social organism, the state. This concept is in direct opposition to the Anglo-American concept of euthanasia, which emphasizes the ''individual's'' 'right to die' or 'right to death' or 'right to his or her own death,' as the ultimate human claim. In contrast, Jost was pointing to the state's right to kill.&nbsp;... Ultimately the argument was biological: 'The rights to death the key to the fitness of life.' The state must own death—must kill—in order to keep the social organism alive and healthy.<ref>Basic Books 1986, 46</ref></blockquote>
==Notes and references==
===Notes===
<div class="references-small">
* '''<small>I</small>.''' {{Note_label|A|I|none}} The word ''euthanasia'' comes from the ] word ''ευθανασία'', meaning "good death". ''ευ''-, eu- (good) + ''θάνατος'', thanatos (death).
</div>


In modern terms, the use of "euthanasia" in the context of Aktion T4 is seen to be a ] to disguise a program of ], in which people were killed on the grounds of "disabilities, religious beliefs, and discordant individual values".<ref name="Michalsen2006">{{cite journal |vauthors=Michalsen A, Reinhart K |title="Euthanasia": A confusing term, abused under the Nazi regime and misused in present end-of-life debate |journal=Intensive Care Med |volume=32 |issue=9 |pages=1304–10 |date=September 2006 |pmid=16826394 |doi=10.1007/s00134-006-0256-9|s2cid=21032497 }}</ref> Compared to the discussions of euthanasia that emerged post-war, the Nazi program may have been worded in terms that appear similar to the modern use of "euthanasia", but there was no "mercy" and the patients were not necessarily terminally ill.<ref name="Michalsen2006" /> Despite these differences, historian and euthanasia opponent ] writes that "the origins of Nazi euthanasia, like those of the American euthanasia movement, predate the Third Reich and were intertwined with the history of eugenics and Social Darwinism, and with efforts to discredit traditional morality and ethics."<ref name="Dowbiggin"/>{{rp|65}}
===References===
<div class="references-small" style="-moz-column-count: 2; column-count: 2;"><references /></div>
<!-- Dead note "Moore": Moore, D. (2005 May 17). “Three in Four Americans Support Euthanasia.” The Gallup Organization. -->
<!-- Dead note "Werth": Werth Jr., James L.; Blevins, Dean; Toussaint, Karine L.; Durham, Martha R. The influence of cultural diversity on end-of-life care and decisions. The American Behavioral Scientist; Oct 2002; 46, 2; pg 204-219. -->


=== 1949 New York State Petition for Euthanasia and Catholic opposition ===
==Selected bibliography==
On 6 January 1949, the Euthanasia Society of America presented to the ] a petition to legalize euthanasia, signed by 379 leading Protestant and Jewish ministers, the largest group of religious leaders ever to have taken this stance. A similar petition had been sent to the New York Legislature in 1947, signed by approximately 1,000 New York physicians. ] religious leaders criticized the petition, saying that such a bill would "legalize a suicide-murder pact" and a "rationalization of the fifth commandment of God, 'Thou Shalt Not Kill.{{'"}}<ref name="Mercy Killing">]. "Ministers Ask Mercy Killing." 6 January 1949.</ref> The Right Reverend Robert E. McCormick stated that:
=== Neutral (approx.) ===
{{Blockquote|The ultimate object of the Euthanasia Society is based on the Totalitarian principle that the state is supreme and that the individual does not have the right to live if his continuance in life is a burden or hindrance to the state. The Nazis followed this principle and compulsory Euthanasia was practiced as a part of their program during the recent war. We American citizens of New York State must ask ourselves this question: "Are we going to finish Hitler's job?"<ref name="Mercy Killing"/>}}
<div class="references-small">
The petition brought tensions between the American Euthanasia Society and the Catholic Church to a head that contributed to a climate of anti-Catholic sentiment generally, regarding issues such as birth control, eugenics, and population control. However, the petition did not result in any legal changes.<ref name="Dowbiggin"/>
* Battin, Margaret P., Rhodes, Rosamond, and Silvers, Anita, eds. ''Physician assisted suicide: expanding the debate''. NY: Routledge, 1998.


==Debate==
* Emanuel, Ezekiel J. 2004. "The history of euthanasia debates in the United States and Britain" in ''Death and dying: a reader'', edited by T. A. Shannon. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.
Historically, the euthanasia debate has tended to focus on a number of key concerns. According to euthanasia opponent ], proponents of euthanasia have presented four main arguments: a) that people have a right to ], and thus should be allowed to choose their own fate; b) assisting a subject to die might be a better choice than requiring that they continue to suffer; c) the distinction between passive euthanasia, which is often permitted, and active euthanasia, which is not substantive (or that the underlying principle–the ]–is unreasonable or unsound); and d) permitting euthanasia will not necessarily lead to unacceptable consequences. Pro-euthanasia activists often point to countries like the ] and ], and states like ], where euthanasia has been legalized, to argue that it is mostly unproblematic.


Similarly, Emanuel argues that there are four major arguments presented by opponents of euthanasia: a) not all deaths are painful; b) alternatives, such as cessation of active treatment, combined with the use of effective pain relief, are available; c) the distinction between active and passive euthanasia is morally significant; and d) legalising euthanasia will place society on a ],<ref>{{Cite book |publisher = Times Books |isbn = 978-0-8129-2790-0 |location = New York |title = Forced Exit |author = Wesley J. Smith |edition = Forced exit |date = 1997 |id = 0812927907|ol = 1006883M |url = https://archive.org/details/forcedexitslippe00smit }}</ref> which will lead to unacceptable consequences.<ref name="Emanuel1994"/>{{rp|797–8}} In fact, in ], in 2013, pain was not one of the top five reasons people sought euthanasia. Top reasons were a loss of dignity, and a fear of burdening others.<ref name=usa151020>{{cite web|url=https://www.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/10/20/california-physician-assisted-suicide-belgium-netherlands-editorials-debates/74296214|title=The vulnerable will be the victims: Opposing view|website=Usatoday.com|access-date=4 July 2017|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170909185538/https://www.usatoday.com/story/opinion/2015/10/20/california-physician-assisted-suicide-belgium-netherlands-editorials-debates/74296214/|archive-date=9 September 2017}}</ref>
{{cite book |author=Dennis J. Horan, David Mall, eds. |title=Death, dying, and euthanasia |publisher=University Publications of America |location=Frederick, MD |year=1977 |pages= |isbn=0-89093-139-9 |oclc= |doi=}}


In the United States in 2013, 47% nationwide supported doctor-assisted suicide. This included 32% of Latinos, 29% of African-Americans.<ref name=usa151020/> Some US disability rights organizations have also opposed bills legalizing assisted suicide.<ref>{{Cite web |url=https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2015/06/disability-rights-assisted-suicide-california/397235/ |title=Why Disability-Rights Advocates Are Fighting Doctor-Assisted Suicide |date=2015-06-30 |access-date=2023-05-27 |website=] |last=Gorman |first=Anna |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150701182950/https://www.theatlantic.com/health/archive/2015/06/disability-rights-assisted-suicide-california/397235/ |archive-date=2015-07-01 |url-status=live}}</ref>
* Kopelman, Loretta M., deVille, Kenneth A., eds. ''Physician-assisted suicide: What are the issues?'' Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001. (E.g., Engelhardt on secular bioethics)


A 2015 ] poll in the United Kingdom found broad public support for assisted dying; 82% of people supported the introduction of assisted dying laws, including 86% of people with disabilities.<ref>{{cite web |title=Dignity in Dying Poll – Populous |url=https://www.populus.co.uk/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/DIGNITY-IN-DYING-Populus-poll-March-2015-data-tables-with-full-party-crossbreaks.compressed.pdf |access-date=4 August 2018 |archive-date=8 November 2016 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20161108235559/http://www.populus.co.uk/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/DIGNITY-IN-DYING-Populus-poll-March-2015-data-tables-with-full-party-crossbreaks.compressed.pdf |url-status=dead }}</ref>
* Magnusson, Roger S. “The sanctity of life and the right to die: social and jurisprudential aspects of the euthanasia debate in Australia and the United States” in Pacific Rim Law & Policy Journal (6:1), January 1997.


An alternative approach to the question is seen in the ] movement which promotes ] for the dying and terminally ill. This has pioneered the use of pain-relieving drugs in a holistic atmosphere in which the patient's spiritual care ranks alongside physical care. It 'intends neither to hasten nor postpone death'.<ref>{{cite web |title=Position statement on hospice care and assisted dying (assisted suicide) and recommendations |url=https://www.hospiceuk.org/docs/default-source/Policy-and-Campaigns/hospice-uk-assited-dying-position.pdf |website=Hospice UK |access-date=11 March 2021}}</ref>
* Palmer, “Dr. Adams’ Trial for Murder” in The Criminal Law Review. (Reporting on R. v. Adams with Devlin J. at 375f.) 365-377, 1957.


==Legal status==
* PCSEPMBBR, United States. President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. 1983. Deciding to forego life-sustaining treatment: a report on the ethical, medical, and legal issues in treatment decisions. Washington, DC: President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research: For sale by the Supt. of Docs. U.S. G.P.O.
{{globalize|section|date=November 2011}}
{{Main|Legality of euthanasia}}
[[File:Legality of euthanasia.svg|thumb|350px|right|Current status of euthanasia around the world:
{{Legend|#0000ffff|Active voluntary euthanasia legal (], ], ], ], the ], ], ],{{refn|group=note|name=PortugalNote|'''Portugal''': Law not yet in force, awaits regulation to be implemented. The law legalizing euthanasia, Law n.º 22/2023, of 22 May,<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://diariodarepublica.pt/dr/detalhe/lei/22-2023-213498831|title=Law n.º 22/2023, of 22 May, published on the 1st Series of Diário da República, n.º 101, of 25 May 2023, in Portuguese, retrieved 25 May 2023.}}</ref> states in Article 31 that the regulation must be approved within 90 days of the publishing of the law, which would have been 23 August 2023. However, the regulation has not yet been approved by the government. On 24 November 2023, the Ministry of Health stated that the regulation of the law would be the responsibility of the new government elected in the 10 March 2024 elections.<ref>{{cite news |last1=Caeiro |first1=Tiago |title=Eutanásia não avança para já. Ministério da Saúde deixa regulamentação para o próximo governo |url=https://observador.pt/2023/11/24/eutanasia-nao-avanca-para-ja-ministerio-da-saude-deixa-regulamentacao-para-o-proximo-governo/ |trans-title=Euthanasia is not moving forward for now. Ministry of Health leaves regulation to the next government |access-date=14 January 2024 |work=Observador |date=24 November 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231202164552/https://observador.pt/2023/11/24/eutanasia-nao-avanca-para-ja-ministerio-da-saude-deixa-regulamentacao-para-o-proximo-governo/ |archive-date=2 December 2023 |language=Portuguese}}</ref> The law, according to its Article 34, will only enter into force 30 days after the regulation is published.}} ] and the Australian states of ], ], ], ], ] and ])}}
{{Legend|#00afffff|Passive euthanasia legal (refusal of treatment / withdrawal of life support)}}
{{Legend|#ddddddff|Active euthanasia illegal, passive euthanasia not legislated or regulated}}
{{Legend|#c60000ff|All forms of euthanasia illegal}}
]]
]


Eligibility for euthanasia varies across jurisdictions where it is legal.<ref name="Davis 2019">{{cite web | last=Davis | first=Nicola | title=Euthanasia and assisted dying rates are soaring. But where are they legal? | website=the Guardian | date=2019-07-15 | url=https://www.theguardian.com/news/2019/jul/15/euthanasia-and-assisted-dying-rates-are-soaring-but-where-are-they-legal | access-date=2024-05-06 | archive-date=26 March 2021 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210326011925/https://www.theguardian.com/news/2019/jul/15/euthanasia-and-assisted-dying-rates-are-soaring-but-where-are-they-legal | url-status=live }}</ref> Some countries such as Belgium and the Netherlands allow ].<ref name="Scopetti Morena Padovano Manetti 2023 p. 1470">{{cite journal | last1=Scopetti | first1=Matteo | last2=Morena | first2=Donato | last3=Padovano | first3=Martina | last4=Manetti | first4=Federico | last5=Di Fazio | first5=Nicola | last6=Delogu | first6=Giuseppe | last7=Ferracuti | first7=Stefano | last8=Frati | first8=Paola | last9=Fineschi | first9=Vittorio | title=Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in Mental Disorders: Ethical Positions in the Debate between Proportionality, Dignity, and the Right to Die | journal=Healthcare | publisher=MDPI AG | volume=11 | issue=10 | date=2023-05-18 | issn=2227-9032 | doi=10.3390/healthcare11101470 | doi-access=free | page=1470| pmid=37239756 | pmc=10218690 }}</ref>
*Robertson, John. 1977. Involuntary euthanasia of defective newborns: a legal analysis. In Death, dying, and euthanasia, edited by D. J. Horan and D. Mall. Washington: University Publications of America. Original edition, Stanford Law Review 27 (1975) 213-269.


West's ''Encyclopedia of American Law'' states that "a 'mercy killing' or euthanasia is generally considered to be a criminal homicide" and is normally used as a synonym of homicide committed at a request made by the patient.<ref name=WEAL>{{cite book |title=West's Encyclopedia of American Law, Vol. 4 |date=1998 |publisher=West Publishing Company |isbn=9780314201577 |page=24}}</ref><ref name="Tomas_Valiente_1997"/>
* Stone, T. Howard, and Winslade, William J. “Physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia in the United States” in ''Journal of Legal Medicine'' (16:481-507), December 1995.
</div>
=== Viewpoints ===
<div class="references-small">
{{cite book |author=Giorgio Agamben; translated by Daniel Heller-Roazen |title=Homo sacer: sovereign power and bare life |publisher=Stanford University Press |location=Stanford, Calif |year=1998 |pages= |isbn=0-8047-3218-3 |oclc= |doi=}}


The judicial sense of the term "]" includes any intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, even to relieve intractable suffering.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Harris |first1=N. |title=The Euthanasia Debate |journal=Journal of the Royal Army Medical Corps |date=1 October 2001 |volume=147 |issue=3 |pages=367–370 |doi=10.1136/jramc-147-03-22|pmid=11766225 |s2cid=298551 |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref name="Tomas_Valiente_1997">Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997</ref><ref name="Mohanty">{{Cite journal|title=Variants of homicide: a review |author=Manoj Kumar Mohanty |journal=Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine |date=August 2004 |volume=11 |pmid=15363757 |issue=4 |pages=214–18 |doi=10.1016/j.jcfm.2004.04.006}}</ref> Not all homicide is unlawful.<ref name="homicide">{{cite web|url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/homicide|title=the definition of homicide|website=Dictionary.com|access-date=4 July 2017|archive-date=3 March 2016|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160303230433/http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/homicide|url-status=live}}</ref> Two designations of homicide that carry no criminal punishment are justifiable and excusable homicide.<ref name="homicide"/> In most countries this is not the status of euthanasia. The term "euthanasia" is usually confined to the active variety; the University of Washington website states that "euthanasia generally means that the physician would act directly, for instance by giving a lethal injection, to end the patient's life".<ref name="University of Washington">{{cite web|url=http://depts.washington.edu/bioethx/topics/pas.html|title=Physician-Assisted Suicide: Ethical Topic in Medicine|website=depts.washington.edu|access-date=4 July 2017|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170413165103/http://depts.washington.edu/bioethx/topics/pas.html|archive-date=13 April 2017}}</ref> ] is thus not classified as euthanasia by ], where it is legal under the ], and despite its name, it is not legally classified as suicide either.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.leg.state.or.us/comm/commsrvs/background_briefs2004/Health%20Care/FG_Physician_Assisted_Suicide2004.pdf|title=Physician Assisted Suicide|last=Taylor|first=Bill|date=7 July 2017|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20041204223955/http://www.leg.state.or.us/comm/commsrvs/background_briefs2004/Health%20Care/FG_Physician_Assisted_Suicide2004.pdf|archive-date=4 December 2004|access-date=7 July 2017}}</ref> Unlike physician-assisted suicide, withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatments with patient consent (voluntary) is almost unanimously considered, at least in the United States, to be legal.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://ajrccm.atsjournals.org/cgi/content/full/162/6/2029|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20030813033538/http://ajrccm.atsjournals.org/cgi/content/full/162/6/2029|url-status=dead|title="Legal Aspects of Withholding and Withdrawing Life Support from Critically Ill Patients in the United States and Providing Palliative Care to Them", ''Am. J. Respir. Crit. Care Med.'', Volume 162, Number 6, December 2000.|archivedate=13 August 2003}}</ref> The use of pain medication to relieve suffering, even if it hastens death, has been held as legal in several court decisions.<ref name="University of Washington"/>
{{cite book |author=Raphael Cohen-Almagor |title=The right to die with dignity: an argument in ethics, medicine, and law |publisher=Rutgers University Press |location=New Brunswick, N.J |year=2001 |pages= |isbn=0-8135-2986-7 |oclc= |doi=}}


Some governments around the world have legalized voluntary euthanasia but most commonly it is still considered to be criminal homicide. In the Netherlands and Belgium, where euthanasia has been legalized, it still remains homicide although it is not prosecuted and not punishable if the perpetrator (the doctor) meets certain legal conditions.<ref>{{Cite journal|author=Oluyemisi Bamgbose |title=Euthanasia: Another Face of Murder |journal=International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology |volume=48 |issue=1 |year=2004 |pages=111–21 |doi=10.1177/0306624X03256662 |pmid=14969121|citeseerx=10.1.1.631.618 |s2cid=32664881 }}</ref><ref>Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee : Netherlands. 27 August 2001</ref><ref>Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, ''La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda'', Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|author=R Cohen-Almagor |title=Belgian euthanasia law: a critical analysis |journal=J. Med. Ethics |year=2009 |volume=35 |pages=436–39 |doi=10.1136/jme.2008.026799 |pmid=19567694 |issue=7|citeseerx=10.1.1.508.6943 |s2cid=44968015 }}</ref>
Appel, Jacob. 2007. A Suicide Right for the Mentally Ill? A Swiss Case Opens a New Debate. Hastings Center Report, Vol. 37, No. 3.


In a historic judgment, the ] legalized passive euthanasia. The apex court remarked in the judgment that the ] values liberty, dignity, autonomy, and privacy. A bench headed by ] ] delivered a unanimous judgment.<ref>{{cite news | url = http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/sc-recognises-living-will-by-terminally-ill-patients-for-passive-euthanasia/article22991873.ece | title = Euthanasia and beyond: on the Supreme Court's verdict SC Constitution Bench holds passive euthanasia, living wills permissible | newspaper = ] | location = ] | date = 9 March 2018 | access-date = 9 March 2018 | url-status = live | archive-url = https://web.archive.org/web/20180605032828/http://www.thehindu.com/news/national/sc-recognises-living-will-by-terminally-ill-patients-for-passive-euthanasia/article22991873.ece | archive-date = 5 June 2018}}</ref>
Dworkin, R. M. Life's Dominion: An Argument About Abortion, Euthanasia, and Individual Freedom. New York: Knopf, 1993.


==Health professionals' sentiment==
Fletcher, Joseph F. 1954. Morals and medicine; the moral problems of: the patient's right to know the truth, contraception, artificial insemination, sterilization, euthanasia. Princeton, N.J.K.: Princeton University Press.
A 2010 survey in the United States of more than 10,000 physicians found that 16.3% of physicians would consider halting life-sustaining therapy because the family demanded it, even if they believed that it was premature. Approximately 54.5% would not, and the remaining 29.2% responded "it depends".<ref name=kane>{{cite web |author=Leslie Kane, MA |url=http://www.medscape.com/viewarticle/731485_2 |title=Exclusive Ethics Survey Results: Doctors Struggle With Tougher-Than-Ever Dilemmas |website=Medscape.com |access-date=6 July 2017 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170814134456/http://www.medscape.com/viewarticle/731485_2 |archive-date=14 August 2017}}</ref> The study also found that 45.8% of physicians agreed that physician-assisted suicide should be allowed in some cases; 40.7% did not, and the remaining 13.5% felt it depended.<ref name=kane/>


In the United Kingdom, the assisted dying campaign group ] cites research in which 54% of general practitioners support or are neutral towards a law change on assisted dying.<ref>{{cite web |title=Public opinion – Dignity in Dying |url=https://www.dignityindying.org.uk/assisted-dying/public-opinion/ |access-date=3 August 2018 |archive-date=14 May 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190514142940/https://www.dignityindying.org.uk/assisted-dying/public-opinion/ |url-status=live }}</ref> Similarly, a 2017 ] poll reported in the ] stated that 55% of doctors believe assisted dying, in defined circumstances, should be legalised in the UK.<ref>{{cite web |title=Assisted dying case 'stronger than ever' with majority of doctors now in support |url=https://inews.co.uk/news/health/assisted-dying-debate-bmj-doctors-majority-support/ |access-date=3 August 2018 |date=7 February 2018 |archive-date=15 May 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190515040235/https://inews.co.uk/news/health/assisted-dying-debate-bmj-doctors-majority-support/ |url-status=live }}</ref>
{{cite book |author=Derek Humphry, Ann Wickett |title=The right to die: understanding euthanasia |publisher=Harper & Row |location=San Francisco |year=1986 |pages= |isbn=0-06-015578-7 |oclc= |doi=}}


In 2019, the World Medical Association issued a statement during its 70th Assembly declaring itself opposed to euthanasia and assisted suicide.<ref>{{Cite web |date=October 2019 |title=WMA Declaration on Euthanasia and Physician-assisted Suicide |url=https://www.wma.net/policies-post/declaration-on-euthanasia-and-physician-assisted-suicide/ }}</ref>
Kamisar, Yale. 1977. Some non-religious views against proposed 'mercy-killing' legislation. In Death, dying, and euthanasia, edited by D. J. Horan and D. Mall. Washington: University Publications of America. Original edition, Minnesota Law Review 42:6 (May 1958).


==Religious views==
Kelly, Gerald. “The duty of using artificial means of preserving life” in Theological Studies (11:203-220), 1950.
{{main|Religious views on euthanasia}}


===Christianity===
Panicola, Michael. 2004. Catholic teaching on prolonging life: setting the record straight. In Death and dying: a reader, edited by T. A. Shannon. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers.


====Broadly against====
Paterson, Craig. Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia: An Natural Law Ethics Approach. Aldershot, Hampshire: Ashgate, 2008.
The Roman Catholic Church condemns euthanasia and assisted suicide as morally wrong. As paragraph 2324 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church states, "Intentional euthanasia, whatever its forms or motives, is murder. It is gravely contrary to the dignity of the human person and to the respect due to the living God, his Creator". Because of this, per the ], the practice is unacceptable within the Church.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith |date=May 5, 1980 |title=Declaration on Euthanasia |url=https://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19800505_euthanasia_en.html |access-date=2023-05-27 |website=www.vatican.va |archive-date=16 June 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230616041716/https://www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations/cfaith/documents/rc_con_cfaith_doc_19800505_euthanasia_en.html |url-status=live }}</ref> The ], along with other Eastern Orthodox Churches, also opposes euthanasia stating that "euthanasia is the deliberate cessation of human life, and, as such, must be condemned as murder."<ref name="orthodoxchristian.info">{{cite web|url=http://www.orthodoxchristian.info/pages/Euthanasia.htm|title=The Orthodox Christian view on Euthanasia|website=www.orthodoxchristian.info|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170812133422/http://www.orthodoxchristian.info/pages/Euthanasia.htm|archive-date=12 August 2017}}</ref>


Many non-Catholic churches in the United States take a stance against euthanasia. Among Protestant denominations, the Episcopal Church passed a resolution in 1991 opposing euthanasia and assisted suicide stating that it is "morally wrong and unacceptable to take a human life to relieve the suffering caused by incurable illnesses."<ref name="orthodoxchristian.info"/> Protestant and other non-Catholic churches which oppose euthanasia include:
Rachels, James. The End of Life: Euthanasia and Morality. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.


{{div col|colwidth=30em}}
Sacred congregation for the doctrine of the faith. 1980. The declaration on euthanasia. Vatican City: The Vatican.
* ]<ref name="ag.org">{{cite web|url=https://ag.org/Beliefs/Topics-Index/Medical-Euthanasia-and-Extraordinary-Support-to-Sustain-Life|title=Assemblies of God (USA) Official Web Site – Medical: Euthanasia, and Extraordinary Support to Sustain Life|website=ag.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170814145809/https://ag.org/Beliefs/Topics-Index/Medical-Euthanasia-and-Extraordinary-Support-to-Sustain-Life|archive-date=14 August 2017}}</ref>
</div>
* ]<ref name="auto">{{cite web|url=https://www.churchofjesuschrist.org/study/manual/handbook-2-administering-the-church/selected-church-policies-and-guidelines/selected-church-policies|title=21. Selected Church Policies and Guidelines|website=ChurchofJesusChrist.org|access-date=16 July 2019|archive-date=21 October 2014|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141021203917/https://www.lds.org/handbook/handbook-2-administering-the-church/selected-church-policies|url-status=live}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.crivoice.org/creednazarene.html#Euthanasia_|title=The Church of the Nazarene, Doctrinal and Ethical Positions|website=www.crivoice.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171108191323/http://www.crivoice.org/creednazarene.html#Euthanasia_|archive-date=8 November 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web |url=http://download.elca.org/ELCA%20Resource%20Repository/End_Life_DecisionsSM.pdf |title=Error |access-date=28 March 2018 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160418054502/http://download.elca.org/ELCA%20Resource%20Repository/End_Life_DecisionsSM.pdf |archive-date=18 April 2016}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://euthanasia.procon.org/view.answers.php?questionID=000154|title=What Are Christian Perspectives on Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide? - Euthanasia - ProCon.org|website=euthanasia.procon.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170815061214/http://euthanasia.procon.org/view.answers.php?questionID=000154|archive-date=15 August 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.lcms.org/about/beliefs/faqs/lcms-views|title=LCMS Views – Frequently Asked Questions – The Lutheran Church—Missouri Synod|website=www.lcms.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170814142432/https://www.lcms.org/about/beliefs/faqs/lcms-views|archive-date=14 August 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.rca.org/physicianassistedsuicide|title=General Synod Statements: Physician-Assisted Suicide – Reformed Church in America|website=www.rca.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170319191005/https://www.rca.org/physicianassistedsuicide|archive-date=19 March 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.salvationarmy.org/ihq/ipseuthanasia|title=The Salvation Army International – Positional Statement: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide|website=www.salvationarmy.org|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170814174417/http://www.salvationarmy.org/ihq/ipseuthanasia|archive-date=14 August 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref name="ag.org"/>
* ]<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.sbc.net/resolutions/493|title=Southern Baptist Convention > Resolution on Euthanasia And Assisted Suicide|website=www.sbc.net|url-status=live|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171009015714/http://www.sbc.net/resolutions/493|archive-date=9 October 2017}}</ref>
* ]<ref name="orthodoxchristian.info"/>
{{div col end}}

====Partially in favor of====
The ] accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is strongly against active euthanasia, and has led opposition against recent attempts to legalise it.<ref>Why the Church of England Supports the Current Law on Assisted Suicide. Dr Brendan McCarthy Archbishops' Council Church House, London 2015</ref> The ] accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is in general against active euthanasia, with growing acceptance now that active euthanasia has been partly legalised in Canada.<ref>Submission to The Special Joint Committee on Physician-Assisted Dying. Rev. Jordan Cantwell Moderator of The United Church of Canada. 2016</ref> The ] take a liberal stance on euthanasia and allow the decision to lie with individuals.<ref name="Ozzano Giorgi 2015 p. 178">{{cite book | last1=Ozzano | first1=L. | last2=Giorgi | first2=A. | title=European Culture Wars and the Italian Case: Which side are you on? | publisher=Taylor & Francis | series=Routledge Studies in Religion and Politics | year=2015 | isbn=978-1-317-36548-8 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=fdyPCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA178 | access-date=2023-05-05 | page=178 | archive-date=13 May 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230513113441/https://books.google.com/books?id=fdyPCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA178 | url-status=live }}</ref><ref name="Garnier 2022 p. 135">{{cite book | last=Garnier | first=T. | title=From God to Climate Change: The journey of Albert Garnier's 30-year mission in China to scientist son Ben's fight with the riddle of the world | publisher=Paragon Publishing | year=2022 | isbn=978-1-78222-969-8 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7--hEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA135 | access-date=2023-05-05 | page=135 | archive-date=13 May 2023 | archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230513113440/https://books.google.com/books?id=7--hEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA135 | url-status=live }}</ref>

===Islam===
Euthanasia is a complex issue in Islamic theology; however, in general it is considered contrary to ] and ]. Among interpretations of the ] and ], the early termination of life is a crime, be it by suicide or helping one commit suicide. The various positions on the cessation of medical treatment are mixed and considered a different class of action than direct termination of life, especially if the patient is suffering. Suicide and euthanasia are both crimes in almost all ].<ref>Islamic Perspectives, Euthanasia (Qatl al-raḥma). Abulfadl Mohsin Ebrahim. Journal of the Islamic Medical Association of North America 2007 Volume 4.</ref>

===Judaism===

There is much debate on the topic of euthanasia in Judaic theology, ethics, and general opinion (especially in Israel and the United States). Passive euthanasia was declared legal by ] under certain conditions and has reached some level of acceptance. Active euthanasia remains illegal; however, the topic is actively under debate with no clear consensus through legal, ethical, theological and spiritual perspectives.<ref>Death and Euthanasia in Jewish Law: Essays and Responses. W Jacob and M. Zemer. Pitsburg and Tel Aviv. Rodef Shalom Press. 1995</ref>

=== Hinduism ===
Although there is no absolute consensus, Hinduism generally views euthanasia as a serious act that conflicts with core principles such as Dharma (duty), Karma (actions and their consequences), and Ahimsa (non-violence).<ref>{{Cite web |title=BBC - Religions - Hinduism: Euthanasia, assisted dying and Suicide |url=https://www.bbc.co.uk/religion/religions/hinduism/hinduethics/euthanasia.shtml |access-date=2024-12-22 |website=www.bbc.co.uk |language=en-GB}}</ref>

==See also==
* {{Look from|Euthanasia in}} – lists many countries with notable positions
* {{Look from|Assisted suicide in}} – lists some countries with notable positions
* ]
{{Div col|colwidth=20em}}
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
{{Div col end}}

== Notes ==
{{Reflist|group=note}}

==References==
{{Reflist}}

==Further reading==
* {{cite encyclopedia |last= Fry-Revere |first= Sigrid|author-link=Sigrid Fry-Revere |editor-first=Ronald |editor-last=Hamowy |editor-link=Ronald Hamowy |encyclopedia=The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism |chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=yxNgXs3TkJYC |year=2008 |publisher= ], ] |location= Thousand Oaks, CA |doi=10.4135/9781412965811.n98 |isbn= 978-1412965804 |oclc=750831024| lccn = 2008009151 |pages= 156–58 |chapter= Euthanasia}}
* {{Cite book| publisher = Exit International US Ltd| isbn = 978-0-9788788-0-1| last = Nitschke| first = Philip |author2=Fiona Stewart |author3=Philip Nitschke |author4=Fiona Stewart| title = The Peaceful Pill Handbook| year = 2006}}
* {{Cite book| publisher = Oxford University Press| isbn = 978-0-19-286070-5| last = Rachels| first = James| title = The end of life: Euthanasia and Morality| year = 1986| url-access = registration| url = https://archive.org/details/endoflifeeuthana0000rach}}
* {{cite book|last=Torr|first=James D.|title=Euthanasia: opposing viewpoints|url=https://archive.org/details/euthanasia00jame|url-access=registration|year=2000|publisher=Greenhaven Press|location=San Diego|isbn=978-0-7377-0127-2}}


==External links== ==External links==
{{wiktionary|Euthanasia}} {{Wikinews category|Euthanasia}}
* {{Commons category-inline}}
===Neutral===
* {{Wiktionary inline|euthanasia}}
<div class="references-small">
* {{Wikiquote inline}}
* - various religious views of euthanasia
* from '']''
* - a UK site that looks at the issues, case studies and ethical and Christian responses

* - many views of euthanasia, for, against, and religious, from the BBC
* - "Should euthanasia be legal?" - Pros, cons, history, laws, polls, and biographies of key players in debate
* - Analysis of public opinion and policy alternatives from Public Agenda Online
* - FAQ brochures explaining Dutch policy on euthanasia {{en icon}}
* - Information on Dutch euthanasia legislation {{en icon}}
</div>
===Support===
<div class="references-small">
*
* international information on voluntary euthanasia, assisted suicide, and self-deliverance
* provides guides to self-deliverance for the terminally and hopelessly ill to end their suffering
* - provides education, support and advocacy for the choice-in-dying movement
* - leading campaigning organisation promoting patient choice at the end of life
*
*
* - Presents pro-choice arguments from a Biblical perspective.
* - Atheist Foundation of Australia Inc
*
* Dr Philip Nitschke - (Australian) Euthanasia law reform advocacy website, currently based in New Zealand.
*
* - Roger Graham. Founder of Assisted Euthanasia Society of Paradise (AESOP), expelled from Cambodia for proposing Euthanasia Tourism, advocate for a Compassionate Law, an activist for Euthanasia since 1971.
</div>
===Opposition===
<div class="references-small">
*
* (the disability rights group opposing Assisted Suicide)
*
*
* - Care, NOT Killing: a UK alliance promoting palliative care, opposing euthanasia and assisted suicide
*
*
*- many resources
*
*
*
*
*
</div>{{-}}
{{Death}} {{Death}}
{{American social conservatism}}
{{Suicide navbox}}


{{Authority control}}
]
]
]
]
]


]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]
]

{{Link FA|id}}

Latest revision as of 13:45, 6 January 2025

Intentionally ending a life to relieve pain and suffering This article is about euthanasia of humans. For humane killings of other animals, see Animal euthanasia. For the killing of mortally wounded animals or humans, see Coup de grâce. For the Megadeth album, see Youthanasia.

Part of a series on
Euthanasia
Types
Views
Groups
People
Books
Jurisdictions
Laws
Alternatives
Other issues
Part of a series on
Homicide
Murder

Note: Varies by jurisdiction

Manslaughter
Non-criminal homicide

Note: Varies by jurisdiction

Family
Other

Euthanasia (from Greek: εὐθανασία, lit.'good death': εὖ, eu, 'well, good' + θάνατος, thanatos, 'death') is the practice of intentionally ending life to eliminate pain and suffering.

Different countries have different euthanasia laws. The British House of Lords select committee on medical ethics defines euthanasia as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life to relieve intractable suffering". In the Netherlands and Belgium, euthanasia is understood as "termination of life by a doctor at the request of a patient". The Dutch law, however, does not use the term 'euthanasia' but includes the concept under the broader definition of "assisted suicide and termination of life on request".

Euthanasia is categorised in different ways, which include voluntary, non-voluntary, and involuntary. Voluntary euthanasia is when a person wishes to have their life ended and is legal in a growing number of countries. Non-voluntary euthanasia occurs when a patient's consent is unavailable and is legal in some countries under certain limited conditions, in both active and passive forms. Involuntary euthanasia, which is done without asking for consent or against the patient's will, is illegal in all countries and is usually considered murder.

As of 2006, euthanasia had become the most active area of research in bioethics. In some countries, divisive public controversy occurs over the moral, ethical, and legal issues associated with euthanasia. Passive euthanasia (known as "pulling the plug") is legal under some circumstances in many countries. Active euthanasia, however, is legal or de facto legal in only a handful of countries (for example, Belgium, Canada, and Switzerland), which limit it to specific circumstances and require the approval of counsellors, doctors, or other specialists. In some countries—such as Nigeria, Saudi Arabia, and Pakistan—support for active euthanasia is almost nonexistent.

Definition

Current usage

As of 2024, dictionary definitions focus on euthanasia as the act of killing someone to prevent further suffering. There is no sense of whether the person agrees or is proactive in the situation.

Past discussions on key elements

In 1974 euthanasia was defined as the "painless inducement of a quick death". However, it is argued that this approach fails to properly define euthanasia, as it leaves open a number of possible actions that would meet the requirements of the definition but would not be seen as euthanasia. In particular, these include situations where a person kills another, painlessly, but for no reason beyond that of personal gain, or accidental deaths that are quick and painless but not intentional.

Another approach incorporated the notion of suffering into the definition. The definition offered by the Oxford English Dictionary incorporates suffering as a necessary condition with "the painless killing of a patient suffering from an incurable and painful disease or in an irreversible coma", This approach is included in Marvin Khol and Paul Kurtz's definition of it as "a mode or act of inducing or permitting death painlessly as a relief from suffering". Counterexamples can be given: such definitions may encompass killing a person suffering from an incurable disease for personal gain (such as to claim an inheritance), and commentators such as Tom Beauchamp and Arnold Davidson have argued that doing so would constitute "murder simpliciter" rather than euthanasia.

The third element incorporated into many definitions is that of intentionality: the death must be intended rather than accidental, and the intent of the action must be a "merciful death". Michael Wreen argued that "the principal thing that distinguishes euthanasia from intentional killing simpliciter is the agent's motive: it must be a good motive insofar as the good of the person killed is concerned." Similarly, Heather Draper speaks to the importance of motive, arguing that "the motive forms a crucial part of arguments for euthanasia, because it must be in the best interests of the person on the receiving end." Definitions such as those offered by the House of Lords Select committee on Medical Ethics take this path, where euthanasia is defined as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, to relieve intractable suffering." Beauchamp and Davidson also highlight Baruch Brody's "an act of euthanasia is one in which one person ... (A) kills another person (B) for the benefit of the second person, who actually does benefit from being killed".

Draper argued that any definition of euthanasia must incorporate four elements: an agent and a subject; an intention; causal proximity, such that the actions of the agent lead to the outcome; and an outcome. Based on this, she offered a definition incorporating those elements, stating that euthanasia "must be defined as death that results from the intention of one person to kill another person, using the most gentle and painless means possible, that is motivated solely by the best interests of the person who dies." Prior to Draper, Beauchamp and Davidson had also offered a definition that included these elements. Their definition specifically discounts fetuses to distinguish between abortions and euthanasia:

In summary, we have argued ... that the death of a human being, A, is an instance of euthanasia if and only if (1) A's death is intended by at least one other human being, B, where B is either the cause of death or a causally relevant feature of the event resulting in death (whether by action or by omission); (2) there is either sufficient current evidence for B to believe that A is acutely suffering or irreversibly comatose, or there is sufficient current evidence related to A's present condition such that one or more known causal laws supports B's belief that A will be in a condition of acute suffering or irreversible comatoseness; (3) (a) B's primary reason for intending A's death is cessation of A's (actual or predicted future) suffering or irreversible comatoseness, where B does not intend A's death for a different primary reason, though there may be other relevant reasons, and (b) there is sufficient current evidence for either A or B that causal means to A's death will not produce any more suffering than would be produced for A if B were not to intervene; (4) the causal means to the event of A's death are chosen by A or B to be as painless as possible, unless either A or B has an overriding reason for a more painful causal means, where the reason for choosing the latter causal means does not conflict with the evidence in 3b; (5) A is a nonfetal organism.

Wreen, in part responding to Beauchamp and Davidson, offered a six-part definition:

Person A committed an act of euthanasia if and only if (1) A killed B or let her die; (2) A intended to kill B; (3) the intention specified in (2) was at least partial cause of the action specified in (1); (4) the causal journey from the intention specified in (2) to the action specified in (1) is more or less in accordance with A's plan of action; (5) A's killing of B is a voluntary action; (6) the motive for the action specified in (1), the motive standing behind the intention specified in (2), is the good of the person killed.

Wreen also considered a seventh requirement: "(7) The good specified in (6) is, or at least includes, the avoidance of evil", although, as Wreen noted in the paper, he was not convinced that the restriction was required.

In discussing his definition, Wreen noted the difficulty of justifying euthanasia when faced with the notion of the subject's "right to life". In response, Wreen argued that euthanasia has to be voluntary and that "involuntary euthanasia is, as such, a great wrong". Other commentators incorporate consent more directly into their definitions. For example, in a discussion of euthanasia presented in 2003 by the European Association of Palliative Care (EPAC) Ethics Task Force, the authors offered: "Medicalized killing of a person without the person's consent, whether nonvoluntary (where the person is unable to consent) or involuntary (against the person's will), is not euthanasia: it is murder. Hence, euthanasia can be voluntary only." Although the EPAC Ethics Task Force argued that both non-voluntary and involuntary euthanasia could not be included in the definition of euthanasia, there is discussion in the literature about excluding one but not the other.

Historical use

"Euthanasia" has had different meanings depending on usage. The first apparent usage of the term "euthanasia" belongs to the historian Suetonius, who described how the Emperor Augustus, "dying quickly and without suffering in the arms of his wife, Livia, experienced the 'euthanasia' he had wished for." The word "euthanasia" was first used in a medical context by Francis Bacon in the 17th century to refer to an easy, painless, happy death, during which it was a "physician's responsibility to alleviate the 'physical sufferings' of the body." Bacon referred to an "outward euthanasia"—the term "outward" he used to distinguish from a spiritual concept—the euthanasia "which regards the preparation of the soul."

Classification

Euthanasia may be classified into three types, according to whether a person gives informed consent: voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary.

There is a debate within the medical and bioethics literature about whether or not the non-voluntary (and by extension, involuntary) killing of patients can be regarded as euthanasia, irrespective of intent or the patient's circumstances. In the definitions offered by Beauchamp and Davidson and, later, by Wreen, consent on the part of the patient was not considered one of their criteria, although it may have been required to justify euthanasia. However, others see consent as essential.

Voluntary euthanasia

See also: Right to die

Voluntary euthanasia is conducted with the consent of the patient. Active voluntary euthanasia is legal in Belgium, Luxembourg and the Netherlands. Passive voluntary euthanasia is legal throughout the US per Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health. When the patient brings about their own death with the assistance of a physician, the term assisted suicide is often used instead. Assisted suicide is legal in Switzerland and the U.S. states of California, Oregon, Washington, Montana and Vermont.

Non-voluntary euthanasia

Non-voluntary euthanasia is conducted when the consent of the patient is unavailable. Examples include child euthanasia, which is illegal worldwide but decriminalised under certain specific circumstances in the Netherlands under the Groningen Protocol. Passive forms of non-voluntary euthanasia (i.e. withholding treatment) are legal in a number of countries under specified conditions.

Involuntary euthanasia

Involuntary euthanasia is conducted against the will of the patient.

Passive and active euthanasia

Voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary types can be further divided into passive or active variants. Passive euthanasia entails the withholding treatment necessary for the continuance of life. Active euthanasia entails the use of lethal substances or forces (such as administering a lethal injection), and is more controversial. While some authors consider these terms to be misleading and unhelpful, they are nonetheless commonly used. In some cases, such as the administration of increasingly necessary, but toxic doses of painkillers, there is a debate whether or not to regard the practice as active or passive.

History

The Death of Socrates, by Jacques-Louis David (1787), depicting Socrates preparing to drink hemlock, following his conviction for corrupting the youth of Athens

Euthanasia was practiced in Ancient Greece and Rome: for example, hemlock was employed as a means of hastening death on the island of Kea, a technique also employed in Massalia. Euthanasia, in the sense of the deliberate hastening of a person's death, was supported by Socrates, Plato and Seneca the Elder in the ancient world, although Hippocrates appears to have spoken against the practice, writing "I will not prescribe a deadly drug to please someone, nor give advice that may cause his death" (noting there is some debate in the literature about whether or not this was intended to encompass euthanasia).

Early modern period

The term euthanasia, in the earlier sense of supporting someone as they died, was used for the first time by Francis Bacon. In his work, Euthanasia medica, he chose this ancient Greek word and, in doing so, distinguished between euthanasia interior, the preparation of the soul for death, and euthanasia exterior, which was intended to make the end of life easier and painless, in exceptional circumstances by shortening life. That the ancient meaning of an easy death came to the fore again in the early modern period can be seen from its definition in the 18th century Zedlers Universallexikon:

Euthanasia: a very gentle and quiet death, which happens without painful convulsions. The word comes from ευ, bene, well, and θανατος, mors, death.

The concept of euthanasia in the sense of alleviating the process of death goes back to the medical historian Karl Friedrich Heinrich Marx, who drew on Bacon's philosophical ideas. According to Marx, a doctor had a moral duty to ease the suffering of death through encouragement, support and mitigation using medication. Such an "alleviation of death" reflected the contemporary zeitgeist, but was brought into the medical canon of responsibility for the first time by Marx. Marx also stressed the distinction of the theological care of the soul of sick people from the physical care and medical treatment by doctors.

Euthanasia in its modern sense has always been strongly opposed in the Judeo-Christian tradition. Thomas Aquinas opposed both and argued that the practice of euthanasia contradicted our natural human instincts of survival, as did Francois Ranchin (1565–1641), a French physician and professor of medicine, and Michael Boudewijns (1601–1681), a physician and teacher. Other voices argued for euthanasia, such as John Donne in 1624, and euthanasia continued to be practised. In 1678, the publication of Caspar Questel's De pulvinari morientibus non-subtrahend, ("On the pillow of which the dying should not be deprived"), initiated debate on the topic. Questel described various customs which were employed at the time to hasten the death of the dying, (including the sudden removal of a pillow, which was believed to accelerate death), and argued against their use, as doing so was "against the laws of God and Nature". This view was shared by others who followed, including Philipp Jakob Spener, Veit Riedlin and Johann Georg Krünitz. Despite opposition, euthanasia continued to be practised, involving techniques such as bleeding, suffocation, and removing people from their beds to be placed on the cold ground.

Suicide and euthanasia became more accepted during the Age of Enlightenment. Thomas More wrote of euthanasia in Utopia, although it is not clear if More was intending to endorse the practice. Other cultures have taken different approaches: for example, in Japan suicide has not traditionally been viewed as a sin, as it is used in cases of honor, and accordingly, the perceptions of euthanasia are different from those in other parts of the world.

Beginnings of the contemporary euthanasia debate

In the mid-1800s, the use of morphine to treat "the pains of death" emerged, with John Warren recommending its use in 1848. A similar use of chloroform was revealed by Joseph Bullar in 1866. However, in neither case was it recommended that the use should be to hasten death. In 1870 Samuel Williams, a schoolteacher, initiated the contemporary euthanasia debate through a speech given at the Birmingham Speculative Club in England, which was subsequently published in a one-off publication entitled Essays of the Birmingham Speculative Club, the collected works of a number of members of an amateur philosophical society. Williams' proposal was to use chloroform to deliberately hasten the death of terminally ill patients:

That in all cases of hopeless and painful illness, it should be the recognized duty of the medical attendant, whenever so desired by the patient, to administer chloroform or such other anaesthetic as may by-and-bye supersede chloroform – so as to destroy consciousness at once, and put the sufferer to a quick and painless death; all needful precautions being adopted to prevent any possible abuse of such duty; and means being taken to establish, beyond the possibility of doubt or question, that the remedy was applied at the express wish of the patient.

— Samuel Williams (1872), Euthanasia Williams and Northgate: London.

The essay was favourably reviewed in The Saturday Review, but an editorial against the essay appeared in The Spectator. From there it proved to be influential, and other writers came out in support of such views: Lionel Tollemache wrote in favour of euthanasia, as did Annie Besant, the essayist and reformer who later became involved with the National Secular Society, considering it a duty to society to "die voluntarily and painlessly" when one reaches the point of becoming a 'burden'. Popular Science analyzed the issue in May 1873, assessing both sides of the argument. Kemp notes that at the time, medical doctors did not participate in the discussion; it was "essentially a philosophical enterprise ... tied inextricably to a number of objections to the Christian doctrine of the sanctity of human life".

Early euthanasia movement in the United States

Main article: Euthanasia in the United States
Felix Adler, c. 1913, the first prominent American to argue for permitting suicide in cases of chronic illness

The rise of the euthanasia movement in the United States coincided with the so-called Gilded Age, a time of social and technological change that encompassed an "individualistic conservatism that praised laissez-faire economics, scientific method, and rationalism", along with major depressions, industrialisation and conflict between corporations and labour unions. It was also the period in which the modern hospital system was developed, which has been seen as a factor in the emergence of the euthanasia debate.

Robert Ingersoll argued for euthanasia, stating in 1894 that where someone is suffering from a terminal illness, such as terminal cancer, they should have a right to end their pain through suicide. Felix Adler offered a similar approach, although, unlike Ingersoll, Adler did not reject religion. In fact, he argued from an Ethical Culture framework. In 1891, Adler argued that those suffering from overwhelming pain should have the right to commit suicide, and, furthermore, that it should be permissible for a doctor to assist – thus making Adler the first "prominent American" to argue for suicide in cases where people were suffering from chronic illness. Both Ingersoll and Adler argued for voluntary euthanasia of adults suffering from terminal ailments. Dowbiggin argues that by breaking down prior moral objections to euthanasia and suicide, Ingersoll and Adler enabled others to stretch the definition of euthanasia.

The first attempt to legalise euthanasia took place in the United States, when Henry Hunt introduced legislation into the General Assembly of Ohio in 1906. Hunt did so at the behest of Anna Sophina Hall, a wealthy heiress who was a major figure in the euthanasia movement during the early 20th century in the United States. Hall had watched her mother die after an extended battle with liver cancer, and had dedicated herself to ensuring that others would not have to endure the same suffering. Towards this end she engaged in an extensive letter writing campaign, recruited Lurana Sheldon and Maud Ballington Booth, and organised a debate on euthanasia at the annual meeting of the American Humane Association in 1905 – described by Jacob Appel as the first significant public debate on the topic in the 20th century.

Hunt's bill called for the administration of an anesthetic to bring about a patient's death, so long as the person is of lawful age and sound mind, and was suffering from a fatal injury, an irrevocable illness, or great physical pain. It also required that the case be heard by a physician, required informed consent in front of three witnesses, and required the attendance of three physicians who had to agree that the patient's recovery was impossible. A motion to reject the bill outright was voted down, but the bill failed to pass, 79 to 23.

Along with the Ohio euthanasia proposal, in 1906 Assemblyman Ross Gregory introduced a proposal to permit euthanasia to the Iowa legislature. However, the Iowa legislation was broader in scope than that offered in Ohio. It allowed for the death of any person of at least ten years of age who suffered from an ailment that would prove fatal and cause extreme pain, should they be of sound mind and express a desire to artificially hasten their death. In addition, it allowed for infants to be euthanised if they were sufficiently deformed, and permitted guardians to request euthanasia on behalf of their wards. The proposed legislation also imposed penalties on physicians who refused to perform euthanasia when requested: a 6–12-month prison term and a fine of between $200 and $1,000. The proposal proved to be controversial. It engendered considerable debate and failed to pass, having been withdrawn from consideration after being passed to the Committee on Public Health.

After 1906 the euthanasia debate reduced in intensity, resurfacing periodically, but not returning to the same level of debate until the 1930s in the United Kingdom.

Euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin argues that the early membership of the Euthanasia Society of America (ESA) reflected how many perceived euthanasia at the time, often seeing it as a eugenics matter rather than an issue concerning individual rights. Dowbiggin argues that not every eugenist joined the ESA "solely for eugenic reasons", but he postulates that there were clear ideological connections between the eugenics and euthanasia movements.

1930s in Britain

The Voluntary Euthanasia Legalisation Society was founded in 1935 by Charles Killick Millard (now called Dignity in Dying). The movement campaigned for the legalisation of euthanasia in Great Britain.

In January 1936, King George V was given a fatal dose of morphine and cocaine to hasten his death. At the time he was suffering from cardio-respiratory failure, and the decision to end his life was made by his physician, Lord Dawson. Although this event was kept a secret for over 50 years, the death of George V coincided with proposed legislation in the House of Lords to legalise euthanasia.

Nazi Euthanasia Program

Main articles: Aktion T4 and Child euthanasia in Nazi Germany
Hartheim Euthanasia Centre, where over 18,000 people were killed

A 24 July 1939 killing of a severely disabled infant in Nazi Germany was described in a BBC "Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline" as the first "state-sponsored euthanasia". Parties that consented to the killing included Hitler's office, the parents, and the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses. The Telegraph noted that the killing of the disabled infant—whose name was Gerhard Kretschmar, born blind, with missing limbs, subject to convulsions, and reportedly "an idiot"— provided "the rationale for a secret Nazi decree that led to 'mercy killings' of almost 300,000 mentally and physically handicapped people". While Kretchmar's killing received parental consent, most of the 5,000 to 8,000 children killed afterwards were forcibly taken from their parents.

The "euthanasia campaign" of mass murder gathered momentum on 14 January 1940 when the "handicapped" were killed with gas vans and at killing centres, eventually leading to the deaths of 70,000 adult Germans. was a campaign of mass murder by involuntary euthanasia in Nazi Germany. Its code name Aktion T4 is derived from Tiergartenstraße 4, a street address of the Chancellery department which recruited and paid personnel associated with the program. Professor Robert Jay Lifton, author of The Nazi Doctors and a leading authority on the T4 program, contrasts this program with what he considers to be a genuine euthanasia. He explains that the Nazi version of "euthanasia" was based on the work of Adolf Jost, who published The Right to Death (Das Recht auf den Tod) in 1895. Lifton writes:

Jost argued that control over the death of the individual must ultimately belong to the social organism, the state. This concept is in direct opposition to the Anglo-American concept of euthanasia, which emphasizes the individual's 'right to die' or 'right to death' or 'right to his or her own death,' as the ultimate human claim. In contrast, Jost was pointing to the state's right to kill. ... Ultimately the argument was biological: 'The rights to death the key to the fitness of life.' The state must own death—must kill—in order to keep the social organism alive and healthy.

In modern terms, the use of "euthanasia" in the context of Aktion T4 is seen to be a euphemism to disguise a program of genocide, in which people were killed on the grounds of "disabilities, religious beliefs, and discordant individual values". Compared to the discussions of euthanasia that emerged post-war, the Nazi program may have been worded in terms that appear similar to the modern use of "euthanasia", but there was no "mercy" and the patients were not necessarily terminally ill. Despite these differences, historian and euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin writes that "the origins of Nazi euthanasia, like those of the American euthanasia movement, predate the Third Reich and were intertwined with the history of eugenics and Social Darwinism, and with efforts to discredit traditional morality and ethics."

1949 New York State Petition for Euthanasia and Catholic opposition

On 6 January 1949, the Euthanasia Society of America presented to the New York State Legislature a petition to legalize euthanasia, signed by 379 leading Protestant and Jewish ministers, the largest group of religious leaders ever to have taken this stance. A similar petition had been sent to the New York Legislature in 1947, signed by approximately 1,000 New York physicians. Roman Catholic religious leaders criticized the petition, saying that such a bill would "legalize a suicide-murder pact" and a "rationalization of the fifth commandment of God, 'Thou Shalt Not Kill.'" The Right Reverend Robert E. McCormick stated that:

The ultimate object of the Euthanasia Society is based on the Totalitarian principle that the state is supreme and that the individual does not have the right to live if his continuance in life is a burden or hindrance to the state. The Nazis followed this principle and compulsory Euthanasia was practiced as a part of their program during the recent war. We American citizens of New York State must ask ourselves this question: "Are we going to finish Hitler's job?"

The petition brought tensions between the American Euthanasia Society and the Catholic Church to a head that contributed to a climate of anti-Catholic sentiment generally, regarding issues such as birth control, eugenics, and population control. However, the petition did not result in any legal changes.

Debate

Historically, the euthanasia debate has tended to focus on a number of key concerns. According to euthanasia opponent Ezekiel Emanuel, proponents of euthanasia have presented four main arguments: a) that people have a right to self-determination, and thus should be allowed to choose their own fate; b) assisting a subject to die might be a better choice than requiring that they continue to suffer; c) the distinction between passive euthanasia, which is often permitted, and active euthanasia, which is not substantive (or that the underlying principle–the doctrine of double effect–is unreasonable or unsound); and d) permitting euthanasia will not necessarily lead to unacceptable consequences. Pro-euthanasia activists often point to countries like the Netherlands and Belgium, and states like Oregon, where euthanasia has been legalized, to argue that it is mostly unproblematic.

Similarly, Emanuel argues that there are four major arguments presented by opponents of euthanasia: a) not all deaths are painful; b) alternatives, such as cessation of active treatment, combined with the use of effective pain relief, are available; c) the distinction between active and passive euthanasia is morally significant; and d) legalising euthanasia will place society on a slippery slope, which will lead to unacceptable consequences. In fact, in Oregon, in 2013, pain was not one of the top five reasons people sought euthanasia. Top reasons were a loss of dignity, and a fear of burdening others.

In the United States in 2013, 47% nationwide supported doctor-assisted suicide. This included 32% of Latinos, 29% of African-Americans. Some US disability rights organizations have also opposed bills legalizing assisted suicide.

A 2015 Populus poll in the United Kingdom found broad public support for assisted dying; 82% of people supported the introduction of assisted dying laws, including 86% of people with disabilities.

An alternative approach to the question is seen in the hospice movement which promotes palliative care for the dying and terminally ill. This has pioneered the use of pain-relieving drugs in a holistic atmosphere in which the patient's spiritual care ranks alongside physical care. It 'intends neither to hasten nor postpone death'.

Legal status

Globe icon.The examples and perspective in this section may not represent a worldwide view of the subject. You may improve this section, discuss the issue on the talk page, or create a new section, as appropriate. (November 2011) (Learn how and when to remove this message)
Main article: Legality of euthanasia
Current status of euthanasia around the world:   Active voluntary euthanasia legal (Belgium, Canada, Colombia, Luxembourg, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Portugal, Spain and the Australian states of New South Wales, Queensland, South Australia, Tasmania, Victoria and Western Australia)   Passive euthanasia legal (refusal of treatment / withdrawal of life support)   Active euthanasia illegal, passive euthanasia not legislated or regulated   All forms of euthanasia illegal
Rates of euthanasia and assisted suicide (EAS) have increased substantially in developed countries, with wide variance in the rates of increase.

Eligibility for euthanasia varies across jurisdictions where it is legal. Some countries such as Belgium and the Netherlands allow euthanasia for mental illness.

West's Encyclopedia of American Law states that "a 'mercy killing' or euthanasia is generally considered to be a criminal homicide" and is normally used as a synonym of homicide committed at a request made by the patient.

The judicial sense of the term "homicide" includes any intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, even to relieve intractable suffering. Not all homicide is unlawful. Two designations of homicide that carry no criminal punishment are justifiable and excusable homicide. In most countries this is not the status of euthanasia. The term "euthanasia" is usually confined to the active variety; the University of Washington website states that "euthanasia generally means that the physician would act directly, for instance by giving a lethal injection, to end the patient's life". Physician-assisted suicide is thus not classified as euthanasia by the US State of Oregon, where it is legal under the Oregon Death with Dignity Act, and despite its name, it is not legally classified as suicide either. Unlike physician-assisted suicide, withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatments with patient consent (voluntary) is almost unanimously considered, at least in the United States, to be legal. The use of pain medication to relieve suffering, even if it hastens death, has been held as legal in several court decisions.

Some governments around the world have legalized voluntary euthanasia but most commonly it is still considered to be criminal homicide. In the Netherlands and Belgium, where euthanasia has been legalized, it still remains homicide although it is not prosecuted and not punishable if the perpetrator (the doctor) meets certain legal conditions.

In a historic judgment, the Supreme Court of India legalized passive euthanasia. The apex court remarked in the judgment that the Constitution of India values liberty, dignity, autonomy, and privacy. A bench headed by Chief Justice Dipak Misra delivered a unanimous judgment.

Health professionals' sentiment

A 2010 survey in the United States of more than 10,000 physicians found that 16.3% of physicians would consider halting life-sustaining therapy because the family demanded it, even if they believed that it was premature. Approximately 54.5% would not, and the remaining 29.2% responded "it depends". The study also found that 45.8% of physicians agreed that physician-assisted suicide should be allowed in some cases; 40.7% did not, and the remaining 13.5% felt it depended.

In the United Kingdom, the assisted dying campaign group Dignity in Dying cites research in which 54% of general practitioners support or are neutral towards a law change on assisted dying. Similarly, a 2017 Doctors.net.uk poll reported in the British Medical Journal stated that 55% of doctors believe assisted dying, in defined circumstances, should be legalised in the UK.

In 2019, the World Medical Association issued a statement during its 70th Assembly declaring itself opposed to euthanasia and assisted suicide.

Religious views

Main article: Religious views on euthanasia

Christianity

Broadly against

The Roman Catholic Church condemns euthanasia and assisted suicide as morally wrong. As paragraph 2324 of the Catechism of the Catholic Church states, "Intentional euthanasia, whatever its forms or motives, is murder. It is gravely contrary to the dignity of the human person and to the respect due to the living God, his Creator". Because of this, per the Declaration on Euthanasia, the practice is unacceptable within the Church. The Orthodox Church in America, along with other Eastern Orthodox Churches, also opposes euthanasia stating that "euthanasia is the deliberate cessation of human life, and, as such, must be condemned as murder."

Many non-Catholic churches in the United States take a stance against euthanasia. Among Protestant denominations, the Episcopal Church passed a resolution in 1991 opposing euthanasia and assisted suicide stating that it is "morally wrong and unacceptable to take a human life to relieve the suffering caused by incurable illnesses." Protestant and other non-Catholic churches which oppose euthanasia include:

Partially in favor of

The Church of England accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is strongly against active euthanasia, and has led opposition against recent attempts to legalise it. The United Church of Canada accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is in general against active euthanasia, with growing acceptance now that active euthanasia has been partly legalised in Canada. The Waldensians take a liberal stance on euthanasia and allow the decision to lie with individuals.

Islam

Euthanasia is a complex issue in Islamic theology; however, in general it is considered contrary to Islamic law and holy texts. Among interpretations of the Qur'an and Hadith, the early termination of life is a crime, be it by suicide or helping one commit suicide. The various positions on the cessation of medical treatment are mixed and considered a different class of action than direct termination of life, especially if the patient is suffering. Suicide and euthanasia are both crimes in almost all Muslim majority countries.

Judaism

There is much debate on the topic of euthanasia in Judaic theology, ethics, and general opinion (especially in Israel and the United States). Passive euthanasia was declared legal by Israel's highest court under certain conditions and has reached some level of acceptance. Active euthanasia remains illegal; however, the topic is actively under debate with no clear consensus through legal, ethical, theological and spiritual perspectives.

Hinduism

Although there is no absolute consensus, Hinduism generally views euthanasia as a serious act that conflicts with core principles such as Dharma (duty), Karma (actions and their consequences), and Ahimsa (non-violence).

See also

Notes

  1. Portugal: Law not yet in force, awaits regulation to be implemented. The law legalizing euthanasia, Law n.º 22/2023, of 22 May, states in Article 31 that the regulation must be approved within 90 days of the publishing of the law, which would have been 23 August 2023. However, the regulation has not yet been approved by the government. On 24 November 2023, the Ministry of Health stated that the regulation of the law would be the responsibility of the new government elected in the 10 March 2024 elections. The law, according to its Article 34, will only enter into force 30 days after the regulation is published.

References

  1. Kuhse, Helga. "Euthanasia Fact Sheet". The World Federation of Right to Die Societies. Archived from the original on 5 August 2017. Retrieved 6 July 2017. 'Euthanasia' is a compound of two Greek words – eu and thanatos meaning, literally, 'a good death'. Today, 'euthanasia' is generally understood to mean the bringing about of a good death – 'mercy killing,' where one person, A, ends the life of another person, B, for the sake of B."
  2. "Voluntary Euthanasia". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on 11 June 2019. Retrieved 7 May 2019. When a person performs an act of euthanasia, she brings about the death of another person because she believes the latter's present existence is so bad that he would be better off dead, or believes that unless she intervenes and ends his life, his life will very soon become so bad that he would be better off dead.
  3. ^ Harris, NM. (October 2001). "The euthanasia debate". J R Army Med Corps. 147 (3): 367–70. doi:10.1136/jramc-147-03-22. PMID 11766225.
  4. Euthanasia and assisted suicide Archived 19 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC. Last reviewed June 2011. Accessed 25 July 2011. Archived from the original
  5. Carr, Claudia (2014). Unlocking Medical Law and Ethics (2nd ed.). Routledge. p. 374. ISBN 9781317743514. Retrieved 2 February 2018.
  6. Voluntary and involuntary euthanasia Archived 5 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 12 February 2012. Archived from the original
  7. Borry P, Schotsmans P, Dierickx K (April 2006). "Empirical research in bioethical journals. A quantitative analysis". J Med Ethics. 32 (4): 240–45. doi:10.1136/jme.2004.011478. PMC 2565792. PMID 16574880.
  8. "Dictionary.com | Meanings & Definitions of English Words". Dictionary.com.
  9. "EUTHANASIA | English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary".
  10. Kohl, Marvin (1974). The Morality of Killing. New York: Humanities Press. p. 94. ISBN 9780391001954., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 294. A similar definition is offered by Blackburn (1994) with "the action of causing the quick and painless death of a person, or not acting to prevent it when prevention was within the agent's powers."
  11. ^ Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 294–312. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  12. ^ Draper, Heather (1998). "Euthanasia". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics. Vol. 2. Academic Press.
  13. "euthanasia". Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford University Press. April 2010. Archived from the original on 21 August 2011. Retrieved 26 April 2011.
  14. Kohl, Marvin; Kurtz, Paul (1975). "A Plea for Beneficient Euthanasia". In Kohl, Marvin (ed.). Beneficient Euthanasia. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. p. 94., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.
  15. Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53 . doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  16. Brody, Baruch (1975). "Voluntary Euthanasia and the Law". In Kohl, Marvin (ed.). Beneficient Euthanasia. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. p. 94., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.
  17. Draper, Heather (1998). "Euthanasia". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics. Vol. 2. Academic Press. p. 176.
  18. Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 303. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  19. Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 304. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  20. Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–40. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  21. ^ Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53 . doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  22. Materstvedt, Lars Johan; Clark, David; Ellershaw, John; Førde, Reidun; Boeck Gravgaard, Anne-Marie; Müller-Busch, Christof; Porta i Sales, Josep; Rapin, Charles-Henri (2003). "Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a view from an EAPC Ethics Task Force". Palliative Medicine. 17 (2): 97–101. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.514.5064. doi:10.1191/0269216303pm673oa. PMID 12701848. S2CID 1498250.
  23. Philippe Letellier, chapter: History and Definition of a Word, in Euthanasia: Ethical and Human Aspects By Council of Europe
  24. Francis Bacon: The Major Works by Francis Bacon, edited by Brian Vickers, p. 630.
  25. Perrett RW (October 1996). "Buddhism, euthanasia and the sanctity of life". J Med Ethics. 22 (5): 309–13. doi:10.1136/jme.22.5.309. PMC 1377066. PMID 8910785.
  26. LaFollette, Hugh (2002). Ethics in practice: an anthology. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 25–26. ISBN 978-0-631-22834-9.
  27. Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  28. Rachels J (January 1975). "Active and passive euthanasia". N. Engl. J. Med. 292 (2): 78–80. doi:10.1056/NEJM197501092920206. PMID 1109443. S2CID 46465710.
  29. Mystakidou, Kyriaki; Parpa, Efi; Tsilika, Eleni; Katsouda, Emanuela; Vlahos, Lambros (2005). "The Evolution of Euthanasia and Its Perceptions in Greek Culture and Civilization". Perspectives in Biology and Medicine. 48 (1): 97–98. doi:10.1353/pbm.2005.0013. PMID 15681882. S2CID 44600176.
  30. ^ Stolberg, Michael (2007). "Active Euthanasia in Pre-ModernSociety, 1500–1800: Learned Debates and Popular Practices". Social History of Medicine. 20 (2): 206–07. doi:10.1093/shm/hkm034. PMID 18605325. S2CID 6150428.
  31. ^ Gesundheit, Benjamin; Steinberg, Avraham; Glick, Shimon; Or, Reuven; Jotkovitz, Alan (2006). "Euthanasia: An Overview and the Jewish Perspective". Cancer Investigation. 24 (6): 621–9. doi:10.1080/07357900600894898. PMID 16982468. S2CID 8906449.
  32. Zedlers Universallexikon, Vol. 08, p. 1150, published 1732–54.
  33. Markwart Michler (1990), "Marx, Karl, Mediziner", Neue Deutsche Biographie (in German), vol. 16, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 327–328; (full text online)
  34. Helge Dvorak: Biographisches Lexikon der Deutschen Burschenschaft. Vol. I, Sub-vol. 4, Heidelberg, 2000, pp. 40–41.
  35. "Historical Timeline: History of Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide," Archived 5 July 2012 at the Library of Congress Web Archives Euthanasia – ProCon.org. Last updated on: 23 July 2013. Retrieved 4 May 2014.
  36. Mannes, Marya (1975). "Euthanasia vs. the Right to Life". Baylor Law Review. 27: 69.
  37. Otani, Izumi (2010). ""Good Manner of Dying" as a Normative Concept: "Autocide", "Granny Dumping" and Discussions on Euthanasia/Death with Dignity in Japan". International Journal of Japanese Sociology. 19 (1): 49–63. doi:10.1111/j.1475-6781.2010.01136.x.
  38. ^ Emanuel, Ezekiel (1994). "The history of euthanasia debates in the United States and Britain". Annals of Internal Medicine. 121 (10): 796. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.732.724. doi:10.7326/0003-4819-121-10-199411150-00010. PMID 7944057. S2CID 20754659.
  39. ^ Nick Kemp (7 September 2002). Merciful Release. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-0-7190-6124-0. OL 10531689M. 0719061245.
  40. Ian Dowbiggin (March 2007). A Concise History of Euthanasia: Life, Death, God, and Medicine. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 51, 62–64. ISBN 978-0-7425-3111-6.
  41. Corporation, Bonnier (May 1873). "Popular Science". {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  42. Pappas, Demetra (1996). "Recent historical perspectives regarding medical euthanasia and physician assisted suicide". British Medical Bulletin. 52 (2): 386–87. doi:10.1093/oxfordjournals.bmb.a011554. PMID 8759237.
  43. ^ Dowbiggin, Ian (2003). A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America. Oxford University Press. pp. 10–13. ISBN 978-0-19-515443-6.
  44. Dowbiggin, Ian (2003). A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America. Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-515443-6.
  45. ^ Appel, Jacob (2004). "A Duty to Kill? A Duty to Die? Rethinking the Euthanasia Controversy of 1906". Bulletin of the History of Medicine. 78 (3): 610–34. doi:10.1353/bhm.2004.0106. PMID 15356372. S2CID 24991992.
  46. Ramsay, J H R (28 May 2011). "A king, a doctor, and a convenient death". British Medical Journal. 308 (1445): 1445. doi:10.1136/bmj.308.6941.1445. PMC 2540387. PMID 11644545.
  47. Gurney, Edward (1972). "Is There a Right to Die – A Study of the Law of Euthanasia". Cumberland-Samford Law Review. 3: 237.
  48. ^ Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline: 24 July 1939 Archived 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The first state-sanctioned euthanasia is carried out, after Hitler receives a petition from a child's parents, asking for the life of their severely disabled infant to be ended. This happens after the case has been considered by Hitler's office and by the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses, whose 'experts' have laid down the basis for the removal of disabled children to special 'paediatric clinics'. Here they can be either starved to death or given lethal injections. At least 5,200 infants will eventually be killed through this programme".
  49. ^ Irene Zoech (11 October 2003). "Named: the baby boy who was Nazis' first euthanasia victim". Telegraph.co.uk. Archived from the original on 8 September 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  50. Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline: 14 January 1940 Archived 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The 'euthanasia campaign' gathers momentum in Germany, as six special killing centres and gas vans, under an organisation code-named T4, are used in the murder of 'handicapped' adults. Over 70,000 Germans will eventually be killed in this act of mass murder – it is the first time poison bas will be used for such a purpose".
  51. Basic Books 1986, 46
  52. ^ Michalsen A, Reinhart K (September 2006). ""Euthanasia": A confusing term, abused under the Nazi regime and misused in present end-of-life debate". Intensive Care Med. 32 (9): 1304–10. doi:10.1007/s00134-006-0256-9. PMID 16826394. S2CID 21032497.
  53. ^ The Moncton Transcript. "Ministers Ask Mercy Killing." 6 January 1949.
  54. Wesley J. Smith (1997). Forced Exit (Forced exit ed.). New York: Times Books. ISBN 978-0-8129-2790-0. OL 1006883M. 0812927907.
  55. ^ "The vulnerable will be the victims: Opposing view". Usatoday.com. Archived from the original on 9 September 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  56. Gorman, Anna (30 June 2015). "Why Disability-Rights Advocates Are Fighting Doctor-Assisted Suicide". The Atlantic. Archived from the original on 1 July 2015. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
  57. "Dignity in Dying Poll – Populous" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 November 2016. Retrieved 4 August 2018.
  58. "Position statement on hospice care and assisted dying (assisted suicide) and recommendations" (PDF). Hospice UK. Retrieved 11 March 2021.
  59. "Law n.º 22/2023, of 22 May, published on the 1st Series of Diário da República, n.º 101, of 25 May 2023, in Portuguese, retrieved 25 May 2023".
  60. Caeiro, Tiago (24 November 2023). "Eutanásia não avança para já. Ministério da Saúde deixa regulamentação para o próximo governo" [Euthanasia is not moving forward for now. Ministry of Health leaves regulation to the next government]. Observador (in Portuguese). Archived from the original on 2 December 2023. Retrieved 14 January 2024.
  61. Colombo, Asher D.; Dalla-Zuanna, Gianpiero (25 January 2024). "Data and Trends in Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia, and Some Related Demographic Issues". Population and Development Review. 50 (1): 233–257. doi:10.1111/padr.12605. hdl:11585/955009. Fig. 1.
  62. Davis, Nicola (15 July 2019). "Euthanasia and assisted dying rates are soaring. But where are they legal?". the Guardian. Archived from the original on 26 March 2021. Retrieved 6 May 2024.
  63. Scopetti, Matteo; Morena, Donato; Padovano, Martina; Manetti, Federico; Di Fazio, Nicola; Delogu, Giuseppe; Ferracuti, Stefano; Frati, Paola; Fineschi, Vittorio (18 May 2023). "Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in Mental Disorders: Ethical Positions in the Debate between Proportionality, Dignity, and the Right to Die". Healthcare. 11 (10). MDPI AG: 1470. doi:10.3390/healthcare11101470. ISSN 2227-9032. PMC 10218690. PMID 37239756.
  64. West's Encyclopedia of American Law, Vol. 4. West Publishing Company. 1998. p. 24. ISBN 9780314201577.
  65. ^ Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997
  66. Harris, N. (1 October 2001). "The Euthanasia Debate". Journal of the Royal Army Medical Corps. 147 (3): 367–370. doi:10.1136/jramc-147-03-22. PMID 11766225. S2CID 298551.
  67. Manoj Kumar Mohanty (August 2004). "Variants of homicide: a review". Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine. 11 (4): 214–18. doi:10.1016/j.jcfm.2004.04.006. PMID 15363757.
  68. ^ "the definition of homicide". Dictionary.com. Archived from the original on 3 March 2016. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  69. ^ "Physician-Assisted Suicide: Ethical Topic in Medicine". depts.washington.edu. Archived from the original on 13 April 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  70. Taylor, Bill (7 July 2017). "Physician Assisted Suicide" (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 December 2004. Retrieved 7 July 2017.
  71. ""Legal Aspects of Withholding and Withdrawing Life Support from Critically Ill Patients in the United States and Providing Palliative Care to Them", Am. J. Respir. Crit. Care Med., Volume 162, Number 6, December 2000". Archived from the original on 13 August 2003.
  72. Oluyemisi Bamgbose (2004). "Euthanasia: Another Face of Murder". International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology. 48 (1): 111–21. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.631.618. doi:10.1177/0306624X03256662. PMID 14969121. S2CID 32664881.
  73. Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee : Netherlands. 27 August 2001
  74. Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997
  75. R Cohen-Almagor (2009). "Belgian euthanasia law: a critical analysis". J. Med. Ethics. 35 (7): 436–39. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.508.6943. doi:10.1136/jme.2008.026799. PMID 19567694. S2CID 44968015.
  76. "Euthanasia and beyond: on the Supreme Court's verdict SC Constitution Bench holds passive euthanasia, living wills permissible". The Hindu. Karnataka. 9 March 2018. Archived from the original on 5 June 2018. Retrieved 9 March 2018.
  77. ^ Leslie Kane, MA. "Exclusive Ethics Survey Results: Doctors Struggle With Tougher-Than-Ever Dilemmas". Medscape.com. Archived from the original on 14 August 2017. Retrieved 6 July 2017.
  78. "Public opinion – Dignity in Dying". Archived from the original on 14 May 2019. Retrieved 3 August 2018.
  79. "Assisted dying case 'stronger than ever' with majority of doctors now in support". 7 February 2018. Archived from the original on 15 May 2019. Retrieved 3 August 2018.
  80. "WMA Declaration on Euthanasia and Physician-assisted Suicide". October 2019.
  81. Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (5 May 1980). "Declaration on Euthanasia". www.vatican.va. Archived from the original on 16 June 2023. Retrieved 27 May 2023.
  82. ^ "The Orthodox Christian view on Euthanasia". www.orthodoxchristian.info. Archived from the original on 12 August 2017.
  83. ^ "Assemblies of God (USA) Official Web Site – Medical: Euthanasia, and Extraordinary Support to Sustain Life". ag.org. Archived from the original on 14 August 2017.
  84. "21. Selected Church Policies and Guidelines". ChurchofJesusChrist.org. Archived from the original on 21 October 2014. Retrieved 16 July 2019.
  85. "The Church of the Nazarene, Doctrinal and Ethical Positions". www.crivoice.org. Archived from the original on 8 November 2017.
  86. "Error" (PDF). Archived (PDF) from the original on 18 April 2016. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  87. "What Are Christian Perspectives on Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide? - Euthanasia - ProCon.org". euthanasia.procon.org. Archived from the original on 15 August 2017.
  88. "LCMS Views – Frequently Asked Questions – The Lutheran Church—Missouri Synod". www.lcms.org. Archived from the original on 14 August 2017.
  89. "General Synod Statements: Physician-Assisted Suicide – Reformed Church in America". www.rca.org. Archived from the original on 19 March 2017.
  90. "The Salvation Army International – Positional Statement: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide". www.salvationarmy.org. Archived from the original on 14 August 2017.
  91. "Southern Baptist Convention > Resolution on Euthanasia And Assisted Suicide". www.sbc.net. Archived from the original on 9 October 2017.
  92. Why the Church of England Supports the Current Law on Assisted Suicide. Dr Brendan McCarthy Archbishops' Council Church House, London 2015
  93. Submission to The Special Joint Committee on Physician-Assisted Dying. Rev. Jordan Cantwell Moderator of The United Church of Canada. 2016
  94. Ozzano, L.; Giorgi, A. (2015). European Culture Wars and the Italian Case: Which side are you on?. Routledge Studies in Religion and Politics. Taylor & Francis. p. 178. ISBN 978-1-317-36548-8. Archived from the original on 13 May 2023. Retrieved 5 May 2023.
  95. Garnier, T. (2022). From God to Climate Change: The journey of Albert Garnier's 30-year mission in China to scientist son Ben's fight with the riddle of the world. Paragon Publishing. p. 135. ISBN 978-1-78222-969-8. Archived from the original on 13 May 2023. Retrieved 5 May 2023.
  96. Islamic Perspectives, Euthanasia (Qatl al-raḥma). Abulfadl Mohsin Ebrahim. Journal of the Islamic Medical Association of North America 2007 Volume 4.
  97. Death and Euthanasia in Jewish Law: Essays and Responses. W Jacob and M. Zemer. Pitsburg and Tel Aviv. Rodef Shalom Press. 1995
  98. "BBC - Religions - Hinduism: Euthanasia, assisted dying and Suicide". www.bbc.co.uk. Retrieved 22 December 2024.

Further reading

External links

Death
In medicine
Cell death
Lists
Mortality
After death
Body
Stages
Preservation
Disposal
Other aspects
Paranormal
Legal
Fields
Other
Social conservatism in the United States
Issues and ideas
Advocates
Groups
Political parties
Related
Suicide
Suicide crisis
Social aspects
Suicide types
Epidemiology
History
Related
By subculture
By country
Categories: