Misplaced Pages

Vitalism: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 19:38, 7 December 2014 editValjean (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, IP block exemptions, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers95,336 edits Criticism: improve format; fix disambiguation issue← Previous edit Latest revision as of 23:24, 15 December 2024 edit undoSchazjmd (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users68,344 edits Mesmerism: italic not needed for "and" 
(293 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Belief about living organisms}}
{{About|the non-] philosophy|other uses|Vital (disambiguation)}}
{{About|the non-mechanist philosophy|the Jain philosophical concept|Vitalism (Jainism)|other uses|Vital (disambiguation)}}
] (and other organic substances) from inorganic compounds was counterevidence for the vitalist hypothesis that only organisms could make such compounds.]]
{{Alternative medicine sidebar |fringe}}
'''Vitalism''' is the doctrine that "living organisms are fundamentally different from non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or are governed by different principles than are inanimate things".<ref></ref> Where vitalism explicitly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy" or "]", which some equate with the ].


'''Vitalism''' is a belief that starts from the premise that "living organisms are fundamentally different from non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or are governed by different principles than are inanimate things."<ref name=Bechtel>{{cite encyclopedia |url= http://mechanism.ucsd.edu/teaching/philbio/vitalism.htm |author=Bechtel, William; Williamson, Robert C. |year=1998 |title=Vitalism |editor=E. Craig |encyclopedia=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge}}</ref>{{efn|] and ] ('']'') published a series of works that in Evelyn Fox Keller's view took on the task of uprooting the remaining vestiges of vitalism, essentially by showing that the principles of physics and chemistry were enough, by themselves, to account for the growth and development of biological form.<ref>Evelyn Fox Keller, ''Making Sense of Life Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines''. Harvard University Press, 2002.</ref> On the other hand, ] notes that D'Arcy Thompson's avoidance of ] had an "odor of spirit forces" about it.<ref name=Ruse>{{cite book |author1=Ruse, Michael |editor1-last=Henning |editor1-first=Brian G. |editor2-last=Scarfe |editor2-first=Adam |title=Beyond Mechanism: Putting Life Back Into Biology |date=2013 |publisher=Lexington Books |page=419 |chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=3VtosxAtq-EC|chapter=17. From Organicism to Mechanism-and Halfway Back?|isbn=9780739174371 }}</ref>}} Where vitalism explicitly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy", "'']''" (coined by vitalist ]), "vital force", or "'''''vis vitalis'''''", which some equate with the ]. In the 18th and 19th centuries, vitalism was ], between those who felt that the known mechanics of physics would eventually explain the difference between life and non-life and vitalists who argued that the processes of life could not be reduced to a mechanistic process. Vitalist biologists such as ] proposed ] ] meant to show inadequacies with mechanistic explanations, but their experiments failed to provide support for vitalism. Biologists now consider vitalism in this sense to have been refuted by ], and hence regard it either as a ],<ref name="Williams2003">{{cite book |last=Williams |first=Elizabeth Ann |title=A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier |url= https://books.google.com/books?id=AvqYl4sdwaYC&pg=PA4 |year=2003 |publisher=Ashgate |isbn=978-0-7546-0881-3 |page=4}}</ref> or as a ] since the mid-20th century.<ref name="DevBio"/><ref name="ps"/>
Although now rejected by mainstream science,<ref></ref> vitalism has a long history in ] philosophies: most ] practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces. In the Western tradition founded by ], these vital forces were associated with the ] and ]s; Eastern traditions posited an imbalance or blocking of ] (or ]).


Vitalism has a long history in ] philosophies: many ] practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces.
== Philosophy ==
] in 1885.)]]
The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back at least to ancient Egypt.<ref>Jidenu, Paulin (1996) ''African Philosophy, 2nd Ed.'' Indiana University Press, ISBN 0-253-21096-8, p.16.</ref> In ], the ] proposed natural explanations ] from ] and ]. However, by the time of ], this account was supplemented, (for example, by the ] of ]), and in stoic physics, the ] assumed the role of ]. ] believed the lungs draw pneuma from the air, which the blood communicates throughout the body.<ref>Charles Birch, John B. Cobb, ''The Liberation of Life: From the Cell to the Community'', 1985, p. 75</ref>


== History ==
{{quote|Plato's world of eternal and unchanging ], imperfectly represented in matter by a divine Artisan, contrasts sharply with the various mechanistic ], of which ] was, by the fourth century at least, the most prominent... This debate was to persist throughout the ancient world. Atomistic mechanism got a shot in the arm from ]... while the ] adopted a divine teleology... The choice seems simple: either show how a structured, regular world could arise out of undirected processes, or inject intelligence into the system.<ref>{{cite book |title=Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought |last=Hankinson |first=R. J. |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-19-924656-4 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=iwfy-n5IWL8C |page=125}}</ref>|R. J. Hankinson|''Cause and Explanation in Ancient Greek Thought'' (1997)}}


== Science == ===Ancient times===
The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back at least to ].<ref>Jidenu, Paulin (1996) ''African Philosophy, 2nd Ed.'' Indiana University Press, {{ISBN|0-253-21096-8}}, p.16.</ref> In ], the ] proposed natural explanations ] from ] and ]. However, by the time of ], this account was supplemented, (for example, by the unpredictable '']'' of ]), and in ], the '']'' assumed the role of '']''. ] believed the lungs draw ''pneuma'' from the air, which the blood communicates throughout the body.<ref>{{harvnb|Birch|Cobb|1985|p=75}}</ref>
In Europe, medieval physics was influenced by the idea of pneuma, helping to shape later ]. In the 17th century, modern science responded to ]'s ] and the mechanism of ] with vitalist theories: that whereas the chemical transformations undergone by non-living substances are reversible, so-called "organic" matter is permanently altered by chemical transformations (such as cooking). ], one of the early 19th century fathers of modern chemistry, argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions.<ref>''Andrew Ede (2007), The Rise and Decline of Colloid Science in North America, 1900–1935: The Neglected Dimension'', p. 23</ref>


===Medieval===
Vitalist chemists predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components, but ] synthesised ] from inorganic components in 1828.<ref></ref> However, contemporary accounts do not support the common belief that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. This ''Wöhler Myth'', as historian Peter Ramberg called it, originated from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931, which, "ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until 'one afternoon the miracle happened'".<ref>''</ref><ref></ref><ref>n 1845, ] succeeded in making acetic acid from inorganic compounds, and in the 1850s, ] repeated this feat for numerous organic compounds. In retrospect, Wöhler's work was the beginning of the end of Berzelius's vitalist hypothesis, but only in retrospect, as Ramberg had shown.</ref> Further discoveries continued to obviate the need for a special "vital force".
In Europe, medieval physics was influenced by the idea of ''pneuma'', helping to shape later ].


===Early modern===
Vitalism is no longer philosophically and scientifically viable, and is sometimes used as a ] ].<ref>"Other writers (eg, Peterfreund, 1971) simply use the term vitalism as a pejorative label." in Galatzer-Levy, RM (1976) Psychic Energy, A Historical Perspective ''Ann Psychoanal'' 4:41–61 </ref> ], co-founder of the ] and a critic of vitalism, wrote:
Vitalists included English anatomist ] (1597–1677) and the Italian doctor ] (1628–1694).<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76">{{harvnb|Birch|Cobb|1985|pp=76–78}}</ref> ] (1733–1794) is considered to be the father of ] in ], that is, he marks the point when embryonic development began to be described in terms of the proliferation of cells rather than the incarnation of a preformed soul. However, this degree of empirical observation was not matched by a mechanistic philosophy: in his '']'' (1759), he tried to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a ''vis essentialis'' (an organizing, formative force). ] (1788–1869) later developed the theory of ], a form of life-energy that permeates living things.
{{quote|It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine... The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable.<ref>Mayr E (2002) ''The Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology'', adapted for the internet, on </ref>}}
{{quote|Vitalism has become so disreputable a belief in the last fifty years that no biologist alive today would want to be classified as a vitalist. Still, the remnants of vitalist thinking can be found in the work of ], ], and ], who seem to believe in some sort of nonmaterial principle in organisms.<ref>Ernst Mayr ''Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist'' 1988, p. 13</ref>}}


In the 17th century, modern science responded to ]'s ] and the mechanism of ] with vitalist theories: that whereas the chemical transformations undergone by non-living substances are reversible, so-called "organic" matter is permanently altered by chemical transformations (such as cooking).<ref name=Ede/>
], shortly after his famous rebuttal of ], performed several experiments that he felt supported vitalism. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." In 1858, Pasteur showed that fermentation only occurs when living cells are present and, that fermentation only occurs in the absence of oxygen; he was thus led to describe fermentation as "life without air". Rejecting the claims of Berzelius, ], ] and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, he concluded that fermentation was a "vital action".<ref name="Becthel_Richardson"> Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1998). ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. E. Craig (Ed.), London: Routledge.</ref>


As worded by ] and ], "the claims of the vitalists came to the fore again" in the 18th century:<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/> "]'s followers were active as were others, such as the physician genius ] of the Hotel Dieu."<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/> However, "Bichat moved from the tendency typical of the French vitalistic tradition to progressively free himself from ] in order to combine with hypotheses and theories which accorded to the scientific criteria of physics and chemistry."<ref>{{harvnb|''History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences''|p=238}}</ref> ] recognised "a 'living principle' in addition to mechanics."<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/>
Other vitalists included English anatomist ] (1597–1677) and the Italian doctor ] (1628–1694).<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76">Charles Birch, John B. Cobb, ''The Liberation of Life: From the Cell to the Community'', 1985, pp. 76–78</ref> ] (1733–1794) is considered to be the father of ] descriptive ], that is, he marks the point when embryonic development began to be described in terms of the proliferation of cells rather than the incarnation of a preformed soul. In his '']'' (1759), he endeavored to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a "vis essentialis", an organizing, formative force, and declared "All believers in epigenesis are Vitalists." ] later developed the theory of ], a form of life-energy that permeates living things.


] established ] as the model of thought in the life sciences in 1781 with his publication of ''Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte''. Blumenbach cut up freshwater polyps and established that the removed parts would regenerate. He inferred the presence of a "formative drive" (''Bildungstrieb'') in living matter. But he pointed out that this name, "like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification". In the early 18th century, the physicians ] and ] recognized a "living principle" in addition to mechanics.<ref name="Charles Birch 1985, pp. 76"/> ] was influential in establishing epigenesis in the life sciences in 1781 with his publication of ''Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte''. Blumenbach cut up freshwater '']'' and established that the removed parts would regenerate. He inferred the presence of a "formative drive" (''Bildungstrieb'') in living matter. But he pointed out that this name,
{{blockquote|like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification.}}


===19th century===
Between 1833 and 1844, ] wrote a book on ] called ''Handbuch der Physiologie'', which became the leading textbook in the field for much of the nineteenth century. The book showed Müller's commitments to vitalism; he questioned why organic matter differs from inorganic, then proceeded to chemical analyses of the blood and lymph. He describes in detail the circulatory, lymphatic, respiratory, digestive, endocrine, nervous, and sensory systems in a wide variety of animals but explains that the presence of a soul makes each organism an indivisible whole. He also claimed the behavior of light and sound waves showed that living organisms possessed a life-energy for which physical laws could never fully account.<ref>http://vlp.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/pdfgen/essays/enc22.pdf</ref>
{{further|Alternatives to Darwinism}}
] in the early 19th century from ] was ] for the vitalist hypothesis that only organisms could make the components of living things.]]


], one of the early 19th century founders of modern ], argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions.<ref name=Ede>Ede, Andrew. (2007) ''The Rise and Decline of Colloid Science in North America, 1900–1935: The Neglected Dimension'', p. 23</ref> Berzelius contended that compounds could be distinguished by whether they required any organisms in their ] (]) or whether they did not (]).<ref>{{Cite journal|last=Wilkinson|first=Ian|date=10 June 2002|title=History of Clinical Chemistry|journal=EJIFCC|volume=13|issue=4|pages=114–118|issn=1650-3414|pmc=6208063}}</ref> Vitalist chemists predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components, but ] synthesised ] from inorganic components in 1828.<ref>{{Cite journal|url=https://www.karger.com/Article/FullText/13463|title=Vitalism and Synthesis of Urea|first1=E.|last1=Kinne-Saffran|first2=R. K. H.|last2=Kinne|date=August 7, 1999|journal=American Journal of Nephrology|volume=19|issue=2|pages=290–294|via=www.karger.com|doi=10.1159/000013463|pmid=10213830|s2cid=71727190}}</ref> However, contemporary accounts do not support the common belief that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. This ''Wöhler Myth'', as historian Peter Ramberg called it, originated from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931, which, "ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until 'one afternoon the miracle happened'".<ref>{{cite journal|doi=10.1179/amb.2000.47.3.170|pmid=11640223|title=The Death of Vitalism and the Birth of Organic Chemistry: Wohler's Urea Synthesis and the Disciplinary Identity of Organic Chemistry.|journal=Ambix|volume=47|issue=3|pages=170–195|year=2000|last1=Ramberg|first1=Peter J.|s2cid=44613876}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Schummer |first1=Joachim |title=The notion of nature in chemistry |journal=Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A |date=December 2003 |volume=34 |issue=4 |pages=705–736 |doi=10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00050-5|bibcode=2003SHPSA..34..705S |url=http://www.joachimschummer.net/papers/2003_NatureChemistry_SHPS.pdf}}</ref>{{efn|In 1845, ] succeeded in making acetic acid from inorganic compounds, and in the 1850s, ] repeated this feat for numerous organic compounds. In retrospect, Wöhler's work was the beginning of the end of Berzelius's vitalist hypothesis, but only in retrospect, as Ramberg had shown.}}
] (1867–1941) interpreted his experiments as showing that life is not run by physicochemical laws.<ref name="DevBio"></ref> His main argument was that when one cuts up an embryo after its first division or two, each part grows into a complete adult. Driesch's reputation as an experimental biologist deteriorated as a result of his vitalistic theories.<ref name="DevBio"/>


Between 1833 and 1844, ] wrote a book on ] called ''Handbuch der Physiologie'', which became the leading textbook in the field for much of the nineteenth century. The book showed Müller's commitments to vitalism; he questioned why organic matter differs from inorganic, then proceeded to chemical analyses of the blood and lymph. He describes in detail the circulatory, lymphatic, respiratory, digestive, endocrine, nervous, and sensory systems in a wide variety of animals but explains that the presence of a ] makes each organism an indivisible whole. He claimed that the behaviour of light and sound waves showed that living organisms possessed a life-energy for which physical laws could never fully account.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Otis |first1=Laura |title=Johannes Peter Müller (1801-1858) |url=https://vlp.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/pdfgen/essays/enc22.pdf |website=Virtual Laboratory: Essays and Resources on the Experimentalization of Life (Max Planck Institute) |date=October 2004}}</ref>
Other vitalists included ] and ]. Reinke used the word ''neovitalism'' to describe his work, he claimed that it would be eventually verified through experimentation and wanted an improvement over the other vitalistic theories. The work of Reinke was an influence for ].<ref>Jung's Concept of Die Dominanten (The Dominants) </ref>


] (1822–1895) after his famous rebuttal of ], performed several experiments that he felt supported vitalism. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." Rejecting the claims of Berzelius, ], ] and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, Pasteur concluded that fermentation was a "vital action".<ref name=Bechtel/>
] adopted an anti-mechanist approach to biology and an ] philosophy early on in his career. Haldane saw his work as a vindication of his belief that ] was an essential concept in biology. His views became widely known with his first book ''Mechanism, life and personality'' in 1913.<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168">Peter J. Bowler, Reconciling science and religion: the debate in early-twentieth-century Britain, 2001, pp. 168–169</ref> Haldane borrowed arguments from the vitalists to use against mechanism; however, he was not a vitalist. Haldane treated the organism as fundamental to biology: "we perceive the organism as a self-regulating entity", "every effort to analyze it into components that can be reduced to a mechanical explanation violates this central experience".<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168"/> The work of Haldane was an influence on ].


===20th century===
Haldane also stated that a purely mechanist interpretation can not account for the characteristics of life. Haldane wrote a number of books in which he attempted to show the invalidity of both vitalism and mechanist approaches to science. Haldane explained:


] (1867–1941) interpreted his experiments as showing that life is not run by physicochemical laws.<ref name="DevBio">{{Cite web|url=http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?ch=10&id=110|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20061031180529/http://7e.devbio.com/article.php?ch=10&id=110|url-status=dead|title=Developmental Biology 8e Online: A Selective History of Induction|archivedate=October 31, 2006}}</ref> His main argument was that when one cuts up an embryo after its first division or two, each part grows into a complete adult. Driesch's reputation as an experimental biologist deteriorated as a result of his vitalistic theories, which scientists have seen since his time as pseudoscience.<ref name="DevBio" /><ref name=ps>{{cite book |last=Dyde |first=Sean |editor1-last=Normandin |editor1-first=Sebastian |editor2-last=Wolfe |editor2-first= T. Charles |title=Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightenment Life Science, 1800–2010 |chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=EQVAAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 |year=2013 |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-007-2445-7 |page=104 |chapter=Chapter 5: Life and the Mind in Nineteenth-Century Britain |quote=In medicine and biology, vitalism has been seen as a philosophically-charged term, a pseudoscientific gloss that corrupted scientific practice …}}</ref> Vitalism is a superseded scientific hypothesis, and the term is sometimes used as a ] ].<ref>{{Cite journal|url=http://www.pep-web.org/document.php?id=aop.004.0041a|title=Psychic Energy: A Historical Perspective|first=R. M.|last=Galatzer-Levy|date=August 7, 1976|journal=Ann. Psychoanal.|volume=4|pages=41–61|via=PEP Web}}</ref> ] (1904–2005) wrote:
{{quote|We must find a different theoretical basis of biology, based on the observation that all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so coordinated that they express what is normal for an adult organism.|<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95"/>}}
{{quote|It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine... The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable.<ref>{{cite web |last1=Mayr|first1=Ernst|date=2002|url= http://www.biologie.uni-hamburg.de/b-online/e01_2/autonomy.htm |title=BOTANY ONLINE: Ernst MAYR: Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology |access-date=2006-09-24 |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20060926210457/http://www.biologie.uni-hamburg.de/b-online/e01_2/autonomy.htm |archive-date=2006-09-26 }}</ref>}}
{{quote|Vitalism has become so disreputable a belief in the last fifty years that no biologist alive today would want to be classified as a vitalist. Still, the remnants of vitalist thinking can be found in the work of ], ], and ], who seem to believe in some sort of nonmaterial principle in organisms.<ref>Ernst Mayr ''Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist'' 1988, p. 13. {{ISBN|978-0674896666}}.</ref>}}


Other vitalists included ] and ]. Reinke used the word ''neovitalism'' to describe his work, claiming that it would eventually be verified through experimentation, and that it was an improvement over the other vitalistic theories. The work of Reinke influenced ].<ref>{{Cite journal|url=https://www.academia.edu/6789277|title=Jung's concept of die Dominanten (the Dominants) (1997)|first=Richard|last=Noll|via=www.academia.edu}}</ref>
By 1931, "Biologists have almost unanimously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged belief."<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95">Mark A. Bedau, Carol E. Cleland, ''The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science'', 2010, p. 95</ref>


] adopted an anti-mechanist approach to biology and an ] philosophy early on in his career. Haldane saw his work as a vindication of his belief that ] was an essential concept in biology. His views became widely known with his first book ''Mechanism, life and personality'' in 1913.<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168">Bowler, Peter J. Reconciling science and religion: the debate in early-twentieth-century Britain, 2001, pp. 168–169. {{ISBN|978-0226068589}}.</ref> Haldane borrowed arguments from the vitalists to use against mechanism; however, he was not a vitalist. Haldane treated the organism as fundamental to biology: "we perceive the organism as a self-regulating entity", "every effort to analyze it into components that can be reduced to a mechanical explanation violates this central experience".<ref name="Peter J. Bowler 2001, pp. 168" /> The work of Haldane was an influence on ]. Haldane stated that a purely mechanist interpretation could not account for the characteristics of life. Haldane wrote a number of books in which he attempted to show the invalidity of both vitalism and mechanist approaches to science. Haldane explained:
=== Relationship to emergentism ===


{{quote|We must find a different theoretical basis of biology, based on the observation that all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so coordinated that they express what is normal for an adult organism.|<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95" />}}
Some aspects of contemporary science make reference to ]es; those in which the properties of a system cannot be fully described in terms of the properties of the constituents.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Schultz | first1 = SG | title = A century of (epithelial) transport physiology: from vitalism to molecular cloning | journal = The American journal of physiology | volume = 274 | issue = 1 Pt 1 | pages = C13–23 | year = 1998 | pmid = 9458708 }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Gilbert | first1 = SF | last2 = Sarkar | first2 = S | title = Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century | journal = Developmental Dynamics | volume = 219 | issue = 1 | pages = 1–9 | year = 2000 | pmid = 10974666 | doi = 10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A }}</ref> This may be because the properties of the constituents are not fully understood, or because the interactions between the individual constituents are also important for the behavior of the system.


By 1931, biologists had "almost unanimously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged belief."<ref name="Mark A. Bedau 2010, p. 95">{{cite book |title=The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science|editor1-first=Mark A. |editor1-last=Bedau|editor1-link=Mark Bedau |editor2-first=Carol E.|editor2-last=Cleland |editor2-link= Carol Cleland |chapter=The Decline of Vitalism |first=Ernst |last=Mayr |author-link=Ernst Mayr |pages=93–95|quote=Yet considering how dominant vitalism was in biology and for how long a period it prevailed, it is surprising how rapidly and completely it collapsed. The last support of vitalism as a viable concept in biology disappeared about 1930." (p.&nbsp;94) From p.&nbsp;95: "Vitalism survived even longer in the writings of philosophers than it did in the writings of physicists. But so far as I know, there are no vitalists among the philosophers of biology who started publishing after 1965. Nor do I know of a single reputable living biologist who still supports straightforward vitalism. The few late twentieth-century biologists with vitalist leanings (A. Hardy, S. Wright, A. Portmann) are no longer alive. |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L3ycvNfa320C&pg=PA93 |publisher=] |year=2010 |isbn=9781139488655}}</ref>
Whether ] should be grouped with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy.<ref>see "Emergent Properties" in the ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. online at for explicit discussion; briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also Emmeche C (2001) Does a robot have an Umwelt? ''Semiotica'' 134: 653–693 </ref> According to Emmeche ''et al.'' (1997):


==Emergentism ==
{{quote|On the one hand, many scientists and philosophers regard emergence as having only a pseudo-scientific status. On the other hand, new developments in physics, biology, psychology, and cross-disciplinary fields such as cognitive science, artificial life, and the study of non-linear dynamical systems have focused strongly on the high level 'collective behaviour' of complex systems, which is often said to be truly emergent, and the term is increasingly used to characterize such systems.|<ref name="Emmeche 1997">Emmeche C (1997) Explaining Emergence: towards an ontology of levels. ''Journal for General Philosophy of Science'' </ref>}}
{{main|Emergentism}}


Contemporary science and engineering sometimes describe ], in which the properties of a system cannot be fully described in terms of the properties of the constituents.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Schultz |first=S.G. |title=A century of (epithelial) transport physiology: from vitalism to molecular cloning |journal=The American Journal of Physiology |volume=274 |issue=1 Pt 1 |pages=C13–23 |year=1998 |pmid=9458708 |doi=10.1152/ajpcell.1998.274.1.C13 |doi-access=free }}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gilbert |first1=S.F. |last2=Sarkar |first2=S. |title=Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century |journal=Developmental Dynamics |volume=219 |issue=1 |pages=1–9 |year=2000 |pmid=10974666 |doi=10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A |doi-access=free }}</ref> This may be because the properties of the constituents are not fully understood, or because the interactions between the individual constituents are important for the behavior of the system.
Emmeche ''et al.'' (1998) state that "there is a very important difference between the vitalists and the emergentists: the vitalist's creative forces were relevant only in organic substances, not in inorganic matter. Emergence hence is creation of new properties regardless of the substance involved." "The assumption of an extra-physical vitalis (vital force, ], ], etc.), as formulated in most forms (old or new) of vitalism, is usually without any genuine explanatory power. It has served altogether too often as an intellectual tranquilizer or verbal sedative—stifling scientific inquiry rather than encouraging it to proceed in new directions."<ref></ref>

Whether emergence should be grouped with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy.{{efn|See;<ref>{{cite web |last1=O’Connor |first1=Timothy |title=Emergent Properties |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties-emergent/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |date=2021}}</ref> briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Emmeche|first=C|title=Does a robot have an Umwelt? Reflections on the qualitative biosemiotics of Jakob von Uexküll |journal=Semiotica |date=16 July 2001 |volume=2001 |issue=134 |pages=653–693 |doi=10.1515/semi.2001.048|url=http://www.nbi.dk/~emmeche/cePubl/2001d.robumwelt.pdf}}</ref>}} According to Emmeche ''et al.'' (1997):

{{quote|On the one hand, many scientists and philosophers regard emergence as having only a pseudo-scientific status. On the other hand, new developments in physics, biology, psychology, and cross-disciplinary fields such as cognitive science, artificial life, and the study of non-linear dynamical systems have focused strongly on the high level 'collective behaviour' of complex systems, which is often said to be truly emergent, and the term is increasingly used to characterize such systems.|<ref name="Emmeche 1997">Emmeche, C. (1997) Explaining Emergence: towards an ontology of levels. ''Journal for General Philosophy of Science'' {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20061006171903/http://alf.nbi.dk/~emmeche/coPubl/97e.EKS/emerg.html |date=2006-10-06 }}</ref>}}


== Mesmerism == == Mesmerism ==
{{main|Animal magnetism}}
] proposed the vitalist force of '']'' in animals with breath.]]


A popular vitalist theory of the 18th century was "]," in the theories of ] (1734–1815). However, the use of the (conventional) English term ''animal magnetism'' to translate Mesmer's '''magnétisme animal''' can be misleading for three reasons: A popular vitalist theory of the 18th century was "]", in the theories of ] (1734–1815). However, the use of the (conventional) English term ''animal magnetism'' to translate Mesmer's '''magnétisme animal''' can be misleading for three reasons:
* Mesmer chose his term to clearly distinguish his variant of ''magnetic'' force from those referred to, at that time, as ''mineral magnetism'', ''cosmic magnetism'' and ''planetary magnetism''. * Mesmer chose his term to clearly distinguish his variant of ''magnetic'' force from those referred to, at that time, as ''mineral magnetism'', ''cosmic magnetism'' and ''planetary magnetism''.
* Mesmer felt that this particular force/power only resided in the bodies of humans and animals. * Mesmer felt that this particular force/power only resided in the bodies of humans and animals.
* Mesmer chose the word "''animal''," for its root meaning (from Latin ''animus'' = "breath") specifically to identify his force/power as a quality that belonged to all creatures with breath; viz., the animate beings: humans '''and''' animals. * Mesmer chose the word "''animal''," for its root meaning (from Latin ''animus''="breath") specifically to identify his force as a quality that belonged to all creatures with breath; viz., the animate beings: humans and animals.


Mesmer's ideas became so influential that King ] of France appointed two commissions to investigate ]; one was led by ], the other, led by ], included ] and ]. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and ]s. In Franklin's garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid," but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier's house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid."<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Best | first1 = M | last2 = Neuhauser | first2 = D | last3 = Slavin | first3 = L | title = Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped | url = http://qhc.bmjjournals.com/cgi/content/full/12/3/232 | journal = Quality & safety in health care | volume = 12 | issue = 3 | pages = 232–3 | year = 2003 | pmid = 12792017 | pmc = 1743715 | doi=10.1136/qhc.12.3.232}}</ref> Mesmer's ideas became so influential that King ] of France appointed two commissions to investigate ]; one was led by ], the other, led by ], included ] and ]. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and ]s. In Franklin's garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid," but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier's house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid."<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Best |first1=M. |last2=Neuhauser |first2=D. |last3=Slavin |first3=L. |title=Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped |url= http://qhc.bmjjournals.com/cgi/content/full/12/3/232 |journal=Quality & Safety in Health Care |volume=12 |issue=3 |pages=232–3 |year=2003 |pmid=12792017 |pmc=1743715 |doi=10.1136/qhc.12.3.232}}</ref>


== Medical philosophies ==
== Complementary and alternative medicine ==


Vitalism has a long history in ] philosophies: many ] practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces. One example of a similar notion in Africa is the ] concept of ]. In the European tradition founded by ], these vital forces were associated with the ] and ]. Multiple Asian traditions posited an imbalance or blocking of ] or ]. Amongst unterritorialized traditions such as religions and arts, forms of vitalism continue to exist as philosophical positions or as memorial tenets.{{citation needed|date=April 2017}}
The National Center for Complementary and Alternative Medicine (]) classifies ] therapies into five categories or domains:<ref name="titleComplementary and Alternative Medicine - U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual">{{cite web |url=http://www.nlm.nih.gov/tsd/acquisitions/cdm/subjects24.html |title=Complementary and Alternative Medicine – U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual |accessdate=2008-03-31 |work=}}</ref>
* alternative medical ]s, or complete systems of therapy and practice;
* ] interventions, or techniques designed to facilitate the mind's effect on bodily functions and symptoms;
* biologically based systems, including ];
* manipulative and body-based methods, such as chiropractic and massage therapy; and
* ].


The therapies that continue to be most intimately associated with vitalism are bioenergetic medicines, in the category of energy therapies. This field may be further divided into ] medicines (BEM) and ] therapies (BT). Compared with bioenergetic medicines, biofield therapies have a stronger identity with vitalism. Examples of biofield therapies include ], ], external ], ] healing and SHEN therapy.<ref name="Rubik">Rubik, ''Bioenergetic Medicines'', American Medical Student Association Foundation, viewed 28 November 2006, </ref> Biofield therapies are medical treatments in which the "]" field of a patient is manipulated by a biofield practitioner. The subtle energy is held to exist beyond the electromagnetic (EM) energy that is produced by the heart and brain. Beverly Rubik describes the biofield as a "complex, dynamic, extremely weak EM field within and around the human body...."<ref name="Rubik"/> ] therapies include ],<ref name="titleComplementary and Alternative Medicine U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual">{{cite web |url= https://www.nlm.nih.gov/tsd/acquisitions/cdm/subjects24.html |title=Complementary and Alternative Medicine U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual |access-date=2008-03-31}}</ref> associated with vitalism, especially biofield therapies such as ], ], external ], ] healing and SHEN therapy.<ref name="Rubik">{{cite web|last=Rubik|first=Beverly|title=Bioenergetic Medicines|work=American Medical Student Association Foundation|access-date=8 November 2006|url= http://www.amsa.org/ICAM/C6.doc |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20060214125248/https://www.amsa.org/ICAM/C6.doc |archive-date=2006-02-14 }}</ref> In these therapies, the "]" field of a patient is manipulated by a practitioner. The subtle energy is held to exist beyond the electromagnetic energy produced by the heart and brain. Beverly Rubik describes the biofield as a "complex, dynamic, extremely weak EM field within and around the human body...."<ref name="Rubik" />


The founder of ], ], promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." As practised by some homeopaths today, homeopathy simply rests on the premise of treating sick persons with extremely diluted agents that – in undiluted doses – are deemed to produce similar symptoms in a healthy individual. Nevertheless, it remains equally true that the view of disease as a dynamic disturbance of the immaterial and dynamic vital force is taught in many homeopathic colleges and constitutes a fundamental principle for many contemporary practising homeopaths. The founder of ], ], promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." The view of disease as a dynamic disturbance of the immaterial and dynamic vital force is taught in many homeopathic colleges and constitutes a fundamental principle for many contemporary practising homeopaths.{{citation needed|date=April 2017}}


== Criticism == == Criticism ==
] mocked vitalism in his 1673 play '']''.]]


Vitalism has sometimes been criticized as begging the question by inventing a name. ] had famously parodied this fallacy in '']'', where a quack "answers" the question of "Why does ] cause sleep?" with "Because of its ] power."<ref name="fr.wikisource.org">'' Mihi a docto doctore / Demandatur causam et rationem quare / Opium facit dormire. / A quoi respondeo, / Quia est in eo / Vertus dormitiva, / Cujus est natura / Sensus assoupire.'' </ref> ] compared vitalism to stating that water is the way it is because of its "aquosity".<ref name="The Physical Basis of Life">, ''Pall Mall Gazette'', 1869</ref> His grandson ] in 1926 compared "vital force" or ''élan vital'' to explaining a railroad locomotive's operation by its ''élan locomotif'' ("locomotive force"). Vitalism has sometimes been criticized as ] by inventing a name. ] had famously parodied this fallacy in '']'', where a quack "answers" the question of "Why does ] cause sleep?" with "Because of its '''dormitive virtue''' (i.e., ] power)."<ref name="fr.wikisource.org">'' Mihi a docto doctore / Demandatur causam et rationem quare / Opium facit dormire. / A quoi respondeo, / Quia est in eo / Vertus dormitiva, / Cujus est natura / Sensus assoupire.'' </ref> ] compared vitalism to stating that water is the way it is because of its "aquosity".<ref name="The Physical Basis of Life">, ''Pall Mall Gazette'', 1869</ref> His grandson ] in 1926 compared "vital force" or ''élan vital'' to explaining a railroad locomotive's operation by its ''élan locomotif'' ("locomotive force").


Another criticism is that vitalists have failed to rule out mechanistic explanations. This is rather obvious in retrospect for organic chemistry and developmental biology, but this criticism goes back at least a century. In 1912, ] published a landmark work, ''The Mechanistic Conception of Life''. He described experiments on how a sea urchin could have a pin for its father, as Bertrand Russell put it (''Religion and Science''). He also offered this challenge: Another criticism is that vitalists have failed to rule out mechanistic explanations. This is rather obvious in retrospect for ] and ], but the criticism goes back at least a century. In 1912, ] published ''The Mechanistic Conception of Life'', in which he described experiments on how a sea urchin could have a pin for its father, as ] put it (''Religion and Science''). He offered this challenge:


: "... we must either succeed in producing living matter artificially, or we must find the reasons why this is impossible." (pp.&nbsp;5–6) : "... we must either succeed in producing living matter artificially, or we must find the reasons why this is impossible." (pp.&nbsp;5–6)


He also addressed vitalism more explicitly: Loeb addressed vitalism more explicitly:


: "It is, therefore, unwarranted to continue the statement that in addition to the acceleration of oxidations the beginning of individual life is determined by the entrance of a metaphysical "life principle" into the egg; and that death is determined, aside from the cessation of oxidations, by the departure of this "principle" from the body. In the case of the evaporation of water we are satisfied with the explanation given by the kinetic theory of gases and do not demand that to repeat a well-known jest of Huxley the disappearance of the "aquosity" be also taken into consideration." (pp.&nbsp;14–15) : "It is, therefore, unwarranted to continue the statement that in addition to the acceleration of oxidations the beginning of individual life is determined by the entrance of a metaphysical "life principle" into the egg; and that death is determined, aside from the cessation of oxidations, by the departure of this "principle" from the body. In the case of the evaporation of water we are satisfied with the explanation given by the kinetic theory of gases and do not demand that to repeat a well-known jest of Huxley the disappearance of the "aquosity" be also taken into consideration." (pp.&nbsp;14–15)


Bechtel and Richardson<ref name="Becthel_Richardson"/> state that today vitalism "is often viewed as ], and therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine." For many scientists, "vitalist" theories were unsatisfactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, ], the co-discoverer of the structure of ], stated "And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only ]s will believe tomorrow."<ref name="Crick">Crick F (1967) ''Of Molecules and Men''; Great Minds Series Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed . Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) ''Synthese'' 20:238–253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings".</ref> Bechtel states that vitalism "is often viewed as ], and therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine."<ref name=Bechtel/> For many scientists, "vitalist" theories were unsatisfactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, ], the co-discoverer of the structure of ], stated "And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only ] will believe tomorrow."<ref name="Crick">Crick, Francis (1967) ''Of Molecules and Men''; Great Minds Series Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed . Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) ''Synthese'' 20:238–253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings".</ref>


While many vitalistic theories have in fact been ], notably Mesmerism, the ] retention of untested and untestable theories continues to this day. ] published an analysis of the wide acceptance among professional nurses of "scientific theories" of spiritual healing. (Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers?).<ref name="Sokal"></ref> Use of a technique called ] was especially reviewed by Sokal, who concluded, "nearly all the pseudoscientific systems to be examined in this essay are based philosophically on vitalism" and added that "Mainstream science has rejected vitalism since at least the 1930s, for a plethora of good reasons that have only become stronger with time."<ref name="Sokal"/> While many vitalistic theories have in fact been falsified, notably Mesmerism, the ] retention of untested and ] theories continues to this day. ] published an analysis of the wide acceptance among professional nurses of "scientific theories" of spiritual healing. (Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers?).<ref name="Sokal"></ref> Use of a technique called ] was especially reviewed by Sokal, who concluded, "nearly all the pseudoscientific systems to be examined in this essay are based philosophically on vitalism" and added that "Mainstream science has rejected vitalism since at least the 1930s, for a plethora of good reasons that have only become stronger with time."<ref name="Sokal" />


Joseph C. Keating, Jr.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.ncmic.com/pages/ce/seminars/speakers/keating.htm|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20060525203939/http://www.ncmic.com/pages/ce/seminars/speakers/keating.htm|url-status=dead|title=Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD: Biographical sketch|archivedate=May 25, 2006}}</ref> discusses vitalism's past and present roles in ] and calls vitalism "a form of ]." He further explains that:
In his book "Kinds of Minds", philosopher ] wrote, "Dualism...and Vitalism (the view that living things contain some special physical but equally mysterious stuff—élan vital) have been relegated to the trash heap of history...." (Chapter 2).<ref name="Dennett">Dennett, Daniel C., 1996, ''Kinds of Minds: Toward an Understanding of Consciousness'', BasicBooks.</ref>


: "Vitalism is that rejected tradition in biology which proposes that life is sustained and explained by an unmeasurable, intelligent force or energy. The supposed effects of vitalism are the manifestations of life itself, which in turn are the basis for inferring the concept in the first place. This ] offers pseudo-explanation, and may deceive us into believing we have explained some aspect of biology when in fact we have only labeled our ignorance. 'Explaining an unknown (life) with an unknowable (Innate),' suggests chiropractor Joseph Donahue, 'is absurd'."<ref name="keating_innate">{{citation |title=The Meanings of Innate |author=Keating, Joseph C. |volume=46 |issue=1 |pmc=2505097 |journal=The Journal of the Canadian Chiropractic Association |year=2002 |pages=4–10}}</ref>
Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD,<ref></ref> discusses vitalism's past and present roles in ] and calls vitalism "a form of ]." He further explains that:

: "Vitalism is that rejected tradition in biology which proposes that life is sustained and explained by an unmeasurable, intelligent force or energy. The supposed effects of vitalism are the manifestations of life itself, which in turn are the basis for inferring the concept in the first place. This circular reasoning offers pseudo-explanation, and may deceive us into believing we have explained some aspect of biology when in fact we have only labeled our ignorance. 'Explaining an unknown (life) with an unknowable (]),' suggests philosopher Joseph Donahue, D.C., 'is absurd'."<ref name="keating_innate"> Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD, J Can Chiropr Assoc 2002; 46(1)</ref>


Keating views vitalism as incompatible with scientific thinking: Keating views vitalism as incompatible with scientific thinking:


: "Chiropractors are not unique in recognizing a tendency and capacity for self-repair and auto-regulation of human physiology. But we surely stick out like a sore thumb among professions which claim to be scientifically based by our unrelenting commitment to vitalism. So long as we propound the 'One cause, one cure' rhetoric of Innate, we should expect to be met by ridicule from the wider health science community. Chiropractors can't have it both ways. Our theories cannot be both dogmatically held vitalistic constructs and be scientific at the same time. The purposiveness, consciousness and rigidity of the Palmers' Innate should be rejected."<ref name="keating_innate"/> : "Chiropractors are not unique in recognizing a tendency and capacity for self-repair and auto-regulation of human physiology. But we surely stick out like a sore thumb among professions which claim to be scientifically based by our unrelenting commitment to vitalism. So long as we propound the 'One cause, one cure' rhetoric of Innate, we should expect to be met by ridicule from the wider health science community. Chiropractors can't have it both ways. Our theories cannot be both dogmatically held vitalistic constructs and be scientific at the same time. The purposiveness, consciousness and rigidity of the Palmers' Innate should be rejected."<ref name="keating_innate" />


Keating also mentions Skinner's viewpoint: Keating also mentions Skinner's viewpoint:


: "Vitalism has many faces and has sprung up in many areas of scientific inquiry. Psychologist ], for example, pointed out the irrationality of attributing behavior to mental states and traits. Such 'mental way stations,' he argued, amount to excess theoretical baggage which fails to advance cause-and-effect explanations by substituting an unfathomable psychology of 'mind'."<ref name="keating_innate"/> : "Vitalism has many faces and has sprung up in many areas of scientific inquiry. Psychologist ], for example, pointed out the irrationality of attributing behavior to mental states and traits. Such 'mental way stations,' he argued, amount to excess theoretical baggage which fails to advance cause-and-effect explanations by substituting an unfathomable psychology of 'mind'."<ref name="keating_innate" />


According to Williams, "oday, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force."<ref name="Williams" /> "Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality."<ref name="Williams">{{cite encyclopedia|encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of Pseudoscience: From Alien Abductions to Zone Therapy|editor-first=William F.|editor-last=Williams|year=2013|edition=revised|title=Vitalism|page=367|isbn=9781135955229|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=vH1EAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA395 |quote='''VITALISM''' &ndash; The concept that bodily functions are due to a 'vital principle' or 'life force' that is distinct from the physical forces explainable by the laws of chemistry and physics. Many alternative approaches to modern medicine are rooted in vitalism. ... The exact nature of the vital force was debated by early philosophers, but vitalism in one form or another remained the preferred thinking behind most science and medicine until 1828. That year, German scientist ] (1800&ndash;82) synthesized an organic compound from an inorganic substance, a process that vitalists considered to be impossible. ... Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality. Today, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force.}}</ref>
According to Williams,<ref name="Williams">Williams.W. (2000) ''The ]. From Alien Abductions to Zone Therapy''. Facts on File inc. Contributors: Drs D.Conway, L.Dalton, R.Dolby, R.Duval, H.Farrell, J.Frazier, J.McMillan, J.Melton, T.O'Niell, R.Shepherd, S.Utley, W.Williams. ISBN 0-8160-3351-X
</ref> "today, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force." "Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality."


]<ref></ref> states that the term "bioenergetics" "is applied in biochemistry to refer to the readily measurable ] within organisms, and between organisms and the environment, which occur by normal physical and chemical processes. This is not, however, what the new vitalists have in mind. They imagine the ] field as a holistic living force that goes beyond reductionist physics and chemistry."<ref name=Stenger>{{cite journal|last=Stenger|first=Victor J.|title=The Physics of 'Alternative Medicine': Bioenergetic Fields.|journal=The Scientific Review of Alternative Medicine|date=Spring–Summer 1999|volume= 3|issue= 1|url=http://www.sram.org/0301/bioenergetic-fields.html|authorlink=Victor_J_Stenger}}</ref> ]<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/vstenger/Medicine/Biofield.html|archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20160303202347/http://www.colorado.edu/philosophy/vstenger/Medicine/Biofield.html|url-status=dead|title=Victor J. Stenger's site|archivedate=March 3, 2016}}</ref> states that the term "bioenergetics" "is applied in biochemistry to refer to the readily measurable ] within organisms, and between organisms and the environment, which occur by normal physical and chemical processes. This is not, however, what the new vitalists have in mind. They imagine the ] field as a holistic living force that goes beyond reductionist physics and chemistry."<ref name=Stenger>{{cite journal |last=Stenger |first=Victor J. |title=The Physics of 'Alternative Medicine': Bioenergetic Fields |journal=The Scientific Review of Alternative Medicine |date=Spring–Summer 1999 |volume=3 |issue=1 |url= http://www.sram.org/0301/bioenergetic-fields.html |author-link=Victor J Stenger |access-date=2006-12-03 |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20061218144228/http://www.sram.org/0301/bioenergetic-fields.html |archive-date=2006-12-18 |url-status=dead }}</ref>


Such a field is sometimes explained as electromagnetic(EM), though some advocates also make confused appeals to quantum physics.<ref name="Rubik"/> Joanne Stefanatos states that "The principles of energy medicine originate in quantum physics."<ref name="Stefanatos">Stefanatos, J. 1997, 'Introduction to Bioenergetic Medicine', Shoen, A.M and S.G. Wynn, ''Complementary and Alternative Veterinary Medicine: Principles and Practices'', Mosby-Yearbook, Chicago.</ref> Stenger<ref name="Stenger"/> offers several explanations as to why this line of reasoning may be misplaced. He explains that energy exists in discrete packets called quanta. Energy fields are composed of their component parts and so only exist when quanta are present. Therefore energy fields are not holistic, but are rather a system of discrete parts that must obey the laws of physics. This also means that energy fields are not instantaneous. These facts of quantum physics place limitations on the infinite, continuous field that is used by some theorists to describe so-called "human energy fields".<ref name="Biley">Biley, Francis, C. 2005, ''Unitary Health Care: Martha Rogers' Science of Unitary Human Beings'', University of Wales College of Medicine, viewed 30 November 2006, </ref> Stenger continues, explaining that the effects of EM forces have been measured by physicists as accurately as one part in a billion and there is yet to be any evidence that living organisms emit a unique field.<ref name="Stenger"/> Such a field is sometimes explained as electromagnetic, though some advocates also make confused appeals to quantum physics.<ref name="Rubik" /> Joanne Stefanatos states that "The principles of energy medicine originate in quantum physics."<ref name="Stefanatos">Stefanatos, J. 1997, ''Introduction to Bioenergetic Medicine'', Shoen, A.M. and S.G. Wynn, ''Complementary and Alternative Veterinary Medicine: Principles and Practices'', Mosby-Yearbook, Chicago.</ref> Stenger<ref name="Stenger" /> offers several explanations as to why this line of reasoning may be misplaced. He explains that energy exists in discrete packets called quanta. Energy fields are composed of their component parts and so only exist when quanta are present. Therefore, energy fields are not holistic, but are rather a system of discrete parts that must obey the laws of physics. This also means that energy fields are not instantaneous. These facts of quantum physics place limitations on the infinite, continuous field that is used by some theorists to describe so-called "human energy fields".<ref name="Biley">Biley, Francis C. 2005, ''Unitary Health Care: Martha Rogers' Science of Unitary Human Beings'', University of Wales College of Medicine, viewed 30 November 2006, {{cite web |url= http://medweb.uwcm.ac.uk/martha/ |title=RogersHomepage |access-date=2006-12-02 |url-status=dead |archive-url= https://web.archive.org/web/20061205024515/http://medweb.uwcm.ac.uk/martha/ |archive-date=2006-12-05 }}</ref> Stenger continues, explaining that the effects of EM forces have been measured by physicists as accurately as one part in a billion and there is yet to be any evidence that living organisms emit a unique field.<ref name="Stenger" />


Vitalistic thinking has also been identified in the naive biological theories of children: "Recent experimental results show that a majority of preschoolers tend to choose vitalistic explanations as most plausible. Vitalism, together with other forms of intermediate causality, constitute unique causal devices for naive biology as a core domain of thought."<ref>{{cite journal | doi = 10.1016/j.tics.2004.06.004 | last1 = Inagaki | first1 = K | last2 = Hatano | first2 = G | year = 2004 | title = 'Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology.' | url = | journal = Trends Cogn Sci | volume = 8 | issue = 8| pages = 356–62 | pmid = 15335462 }}</ref> Vitalistic thinking has been identified in the naive biological theories of children: "Recent experimental results show that a majority of preschoolers tend to choose vitalistic explanations as most plausible. Vitalism, together with other forms of intermediate causality, constitute unique causal devices for naive biology as a core domain of thought."<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/j.tics.2004.06.004 |last1=Inagaki |first1=K. |last2=Hatano |first2=G. |year=2004 |title='Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology.' |journal=Trends Cogn Sci |volume=8 |issue=8|pages=356–62 |pmid=15335462 |s2cid=29256474 }}</ref>


== See also == == See also ==
{{div col|cols=3}} {{div col|colwidth=22em}}
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* '']''
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
* ]
* ]
* ] * ]
* ] * ]
* ]
{{div col end}} {{div col end}}


== References == ==Notes==
{{reflist|2}} {{notelist}}


==References==
== External links ==
{{reflist}}

==Sources==
* {{cite book|last1=Birch|first1=Charles|last2=Cobb|first2=John B|title=The Liberation of Life: From the Cell to the Community|year=1985|publisher=CUP Archive |isbn=9780521315142|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=h3c6AAAAIAAJ}}
* {{cite book|ref={{harvid|''History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences''}}|title=History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences|volume=29|year=2007|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tUkoAQAAIAAJ}}

==External links==
{{Wikiversity}} {{Wikiversity}}
* {{In Our Time|Vitalism|b00dwhwt|Vitalism}}
* Coexistentialism by A. Nagraj
*{{In Our Time|Vitalism|b00dwhwt|Vitalism}}
* – Joseph B. Strauss, DC. Straight chiropractic philosophy
* at the ] * at the ]
* – diametrically opposed worldview themes from Project Worldview


* For vital force and vitalism in the Spanish context, see Nicolás Fernández-Medina's '''' (McGill-Queen's UP, 2018).

{{Evolution}}
{{Philosophy of biology}}
{{philosophy of science}} {{philosophy of science}}


] ]
]
] ]
]
] ]
] ]

Latest revision as of 23:24, 15 December 2024

Belief about living organisms This article is about the non-mechanist philosophy. For the Jain philosophical concept, see Vitalism (Jainism). For other uses, see Vital (disambiguation).
Part of a series on
Alternative medicine
General information
Fringe medicine and science
Controversies
Classifications
Traditional medicine
Alternative diagnoses

Vitalism is a belief that starts from the premise that "living organisms are fundamentally different from non-living entities because they contain some non-physical element or are governed by different principles than are inanimate things." Where vitalism explicitly invokes a vital principle, that element is often referred to as the "vital spark", "energy", "élan vital" (coined by vitalist Henri Bergson), "vital force", or "vis vitalis", which some equate with the soul. In the 18th and 19th centuries, vitalism was discussed among biologists, between those who felt that the known mechanics of physics would eventually explain the difference between life and non-life and vitalists who argued that the processes of life could not be reduced to a mechanistic process. Vitalist biologists such as Johannes Reinke proposed testable hypotheses meant to show inadequacies with mechanistic explanations, but their experiments failed to provide support for vitalism. Biologists now consider vitalism in this sense to have been refuted by empirical evidence, and hence regard it either as a superseded scientific theory, or as a pseudoscience since the mid-20th century.

Vitalism has a long history in medical philosophies: many traditional healing practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces.

History

Ancient times

The notion that bodily functions are due to a vitalistic principle existing in all living creatures has roots going back at least to ancient Egypt. In Greek philosophy, the Milesian school proposed natural explanations deduced from materialism and mechanism. However, by the time of Lucretius, this account was supplemented, (for example, by the unpredictable clinamen of Epicurus), and in Stoic physics, the pneuma assumed the role of logos. Galen believed the lungs draw pneuma from the air, which the blood communicates throughout the body.

Medieval

In Europe, medieval physics was influenced by the idea of pneuma, helping to shape later aether theories.

Early modern

Vitalists included English anatomist Francis Glisson (1597–1677) and the Italian doctor Marcello Malpighi (1628–1694). Caspar Friedrich Wolff (1733–1794) is considered to be the father of epigenesis in embryology, that is, he marks the point when embryonic development began to be described in terms of the proliferation of cells rather than the incarnation of a preformed soul. However, this degree of empirical observation was not matched by a mechanistic philosophy: in his Theoria Generationis (1759), he tried to explain the emergence of the organism by the actions of a vis essentialis (an organizing, formative force). Carl Reichenbach (1788–1869) later developed the theory of Odic force, a form of life-energy that permeates living things.

In the 17th century, modern science responded to Newton's action at a distance and the mechanism of Cartesian dualism with vitalist theories: that whereas the chemical transformations undergone by non-living substances are reversible, so-called "organic" matter is permanently altered by chemical transformations (such as cooking).

As worded by Charles Birch and John B. Cobb, "the claims of the vitalists came to the fore again" in the 18th century: "Georg Ernst Stahl's followers were active as were others, such as the physician genius Francis Xavier Bichat of the Hotel Dieu." However, "Bichat moved from the tendency typical of the French vitalistic tradition to progressively free himself from metaphysics in order to combine with hypotheses and theories which accorded to the scientific criteria of physics and chemistry." John Hunter recognised "a 'living principle' in addition to mechanics."

Johann Friedrich Blumenbach was influential in establishing epigenesis in the life sciences in 1781 with his publication of Über den Bildungstrieb und das Zeugungsgeschäfte. Blumenbach cut up freshwater Hydra and established that the removed parts would regenerate. He inferred the presence of a "formative drive" (Bildungstrieb) in living matter. But he pointed out that this name,

like names applied to every other kind of vital power, of itself, explains nothing: it serves merely to designate a peculiar power formed by the combination of the mechanical principle with that which is susceptible of modification.

19th century

Further information: Alternatives to Darwinism
The synthesis of urea in the early 19th century from inorganic compounds was counterevidence for the vitalist hypothesis that only organisms could make the components of living things.

Jöns Jakob Berzelius, one of the early 19th century founders of modern chemistry, argued that a regulative force must exist within living matter to maintain its functions. Berzelius contended that compounds could be distinguished by whether they required any organisms in their synthesis (organic compounds) or whether they did not (inorganic compounds). Vitalist chemists predicted that organic materials could not be synthesized from inorganic components, but Friedrich Wöhler synthesised urea from inorganic components in 1828. However, contemporary accounts do not support the common belief that vitalism died when Wöhler made urea. This Wöhler Myth, as historian Peter Ramberg called it, originated from a popular history of chemistry published in 1931, which, "ignoring all pretense of historical accuracy, turned Wöhler into a crusader who made attempt after attempt to synthesize a natural product that would refute vitalism and lift the veil of ignorance, until 'one afternoon the miracle happened'".

Between 1833 and 1844, Johannes Peter Müller wrote a book on physiology called Handbuch der Physiologie, which became the leading textbook in the field for much of the nineteenth century. The book showed Müller's commitments to vitalism; he questioned why organic matter differs from inorganic, then proceeded to chemical analyses of the blood and lymph. He describes in detail the circulatory, lymphatic, respiratory, digestive, endocrine, nervous, and sensory systems in a wide variety of animals but explains that the presence of a soul makes each organism an indivisible whole. He claimed that the behaviour of light and sound waves showed that living organisms possessed a life-energy for which physical laws could never fully account.

Louis Pasteur (1822–1895) after his famous rebuttal of spontaneous generation, performed several experiments that he felt supported vitalism. According to Bechtel, Pasteur "fitted fermentation into a more general programme describing special reactions that only occur in living organisms. These are irreducibly vital phenomena." Rejecting the claims of Berzelius, Liebig, Traube and others that fermentation resulted from chemical agents or catalysts within cells, Pasteur concluded that fermentation was a "vital action".

20th century

Hans Driesch (1867–1941) interpreted his experiments as showing that life is not run by physicochemical laws. His main argument was that when one cuts up an embryo after its first division or two, each part grows into a complete adult. Driesch's reputation as an experimental biologist deteriorated as a result of his vitalistic theories, which scientists have seen since his time as pseudoscience. Vitalism is a superseded scientific hypothesis, and the term is sometimes used as a pejorative epithet. Ernst Mayr (1904–2005) wrote:

It would be ahistorical to ridicule vitalists. When one reads the writings of one of the leading vitalists like Driesch one is forced to agree with him that many of the basic problems of biology simply cannot be solved by a philosophy as that of Descartes, in which the organism is simply considered a machine... The logic of the critique of the vitalists was impeccable.

Vitalism has become so disreputable a belief in the last fifty years that no biologist alive today would want to be classified as a vitalist. Still, the remnants of vitalist thinking can be found in the work of Alistair Hardy, Sewall Wright, and Charles Birch, who seem to believe in some sort of nonmaterial principle in organisms.

Other vitalists included Johannes Reinke and Oscar Hertwig. Reinke used the word neovitalism to describe his work, claiming that it would eventually be verified through experimentation, and that it was an improvement over the other vitalistic theories. The work of Reinke influenced Carl Jung.

John Scott Haldane adopted an anti-mechanist approach to biology and an idealist philosophy early on in his career. Haldane saw his work as a vindication of his belief that teleology was an essential concept in biology. His views became widely known with his first book Mechanism, life and personality in 1913. Haldane borrowed arguments from the vitalists to use against mechanism; however, he was not a vitalist. Haldane treated the organism as fundamental to biology: "we perceive the organism as a self-regulating entity", "every effort to analyze it into components that can be reduced to a mechanical explanation violates this central experience". The work of Haldane was an influence on organicism. Haldane stated that a purely mechanist interpretation could not account for the characteristics of life. Haldane wrote a number of books in which he attempted to show the invalidity of both vitalism and mechanist approaches to science. Haldane explained:

We must find a different theoretical basis of biology, based on the observation that all the phenomena concerned tend towards being so coordinated that they express what is normal for an adult organism.

— 

By 1931, biologists had "almost unanimously abandoned vitalism as an acknowledged belief."

Emergentism

Main article: Emergentism

Contemporary science and engineering sometimes describe emergent processes, in which the properties of a system cannot be fully described in terms of the properties of the constituents. This may be because the properties of the constituents are not fully understood, or because the interactions between the individual constituents are important for the behavior of the system.

Whether emergence should be grouped with traditional vitalist concepts is a matter of semantic controversy. According to Emmeche et al. (1997):

On the one hand, many scientists and philosophers regard emergence as having only a pseudo-scientific status. On the other hand, new developments in physics, biology, psychology, and cross-disciplinary fields such as cognitive science, artificial life, and the study of non-linear dynamical systems have focused strongly on the high level 'collective behaviour' of complex systems, which is often said to be truly emergent, and the term is increasingly used to characterize such systems.

— 

Mesmerism

Main article: Animal magnetism
Franz Mesmer proposed the vitalist force of magnétisme animal in animals with breath.

A popular vitalist theory of the 18th century was "animal magnetism", in the theories of Franz Mesmer (1734–1815). However, the use of the (conventional) English term animal magnetism to translate Mesmer's magnétisme animal can be misleading for three reasons:

  • Mesmer chose his term to clearly distinguish his variant of magnetic force from those referred to, at that time, as mineral magnetism, cosmic magnetism and planetary magnetism.
  • Mesmer felt that this particular force/power only resided in the bodies of humans and animals.
  • Mesmer chose the word "animal," for its root meaning (from Latin animus="breath") specifically to identify his force as a quality that belonged to all creatures with breath; viz., the animate beings: humans and animals.

Mesmer's ideas became so influential that King Louis XVI of France appointed two commissions to investigate mesmerism; one was led by Joseph-Ignace Guillotin, the other, led by Benjamin Franklin, included Bailly and Lavoisier. The commissioners learned about Mesmeric theory, and saw its patients fall into fits and trances. In Franklin's garden, a patient was led to each of five trees, one of which had been "mesmerized"; he hugged each in turn to receive the "vital fluid," but fainted at the foot of a 'wrong' one. At Lavoisier's house, four normal cups of water were held before a "sensitive" woman; the fourth produced convulsions, but she calmly swallowed the mesmerized contents of a fifth, believing it to be plain water. The commissioners concluded that "the fluid without imagination is powerless, whereas imagination without the fluid can produce the effects of the fluid."

Medical philosophies

Vitalism has a long history in medical philosophies: many traditional healing practices posited that disease results from some imbalance in vital forces. One example of a similar notion in Africa is the Yoruba concept of ase. In the European tradition founded by Hippocrates, these vital forces were associated with the four temperaments and humours. Multiple Asian traditions posited an imbalance or blocking of qi or prana. Amongst unterritorialized traditions such as religions and arts, forms of vitalism continue to exist as philosophical positions or as memorial tenets.

Complementary and alternative medicine therapies include energy therapies, associated with vitalism, especially biofield therapies such as therapeutic touch, Reiki, external qi, chakra healing and SHEN therapy. In these therapies, the "subtle energy" field of a patient is manipulated by a practitioner. The subtle energy is held to exist beyond the electromagnetic energy produced by the heart and brain. Beverly Rubik describes the biofield as a "complex, dynamic, extremely weak EM field within and around the human body...."

The founder of homeopathy, Samuel Hahnemann, promoted an immaterial, vitalistic view of disease: "...they are solely spirit-like (dynamic) derangements of the spirit-like power (the vital principle) that animates the human body." The view of disease as a dynamic disturbance of the immaterial and dynamic vital force is taught in many homeopathic colleges and constitutes a fundamental principle for many contemporary practising homeopaths.

Criticism

The 17th century French playwright Molière mocked vitalism in his 1673 play Le Malade imaginaire.

Vitalism has sometimes been criticized as begging the question by inventing a name. Molière had famously parodied this fallacy in Le Malade imaginaire, where a quack "answers" the question of "Why does opium cause sleep?" with "Because of its dormitive virtue (i.e., soporific power)." Thomas Henry Huxley compared vitalism to stating that water is the way it is because of its "aquosity". His grandson Julian Huxley in 1926 compared "vital force" or élan vital to explaining a railroad locomotive's operation by its élan locomotif ("locomotive force").

Another criticism is that vitalists have failed to rule out mechanistic explanations. This is rather obvious in retrospect for organic chemistry and developmental biology, but the criticism goes back at least a century. In 1912, Jacques Loeb published The Mechanistic Conception of Life, in which he described experiments on how a sea urchin could have a pin for its father, as Bertrand Russell put it (Religion and Science). He offered this challenge:

"... we must either succeed in producing living matter artificially, or we must find the reasons why this is impossible." (pp. 5–6)

Loeb addressed vitalism more explicitly:

"It is, therefore, unwarranted to continue the statement that in addition to the acceleration of oxidations the beginning of individual life is determined by the entrance of a metaphysical "life principle" into the egg; and that death is determined, aside from the cessation of oxidations, by the departure of this "principle" from the body. In the case of the evaporation of water we are satisfied with the explanation given by the kinetic theory of gases and do not demand that to repeat a well-known jest of Huxley the disappearance of the "aquosity" be also taken into consideration." (pp. 14–15)

Bechtel states that vitalism "is often viewed as unfalsifiable, and therefore a pernicious metaphysical doctrine." For many scientists, "vitalist" theories were unsatisfactory "holding positions" on the pathway to mechanistic understanding. In 1967, Francis Crick, the co-discoverer of the structure of DNA, stated "And so to those of you who may be vitalists I would make this prophecy: what everyone believed yesterday, and you believe today, only cranks will believe tomorrow."

While many vitalistic theories have in fact been falsified, notably Mesmerism, the pseudoscientific retention of untested and untestable theories continues to this day. Alan Sokal published an analysis of the wide acceptance among professional nurses of "scientific theories" of spiritual healing. (Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers?). Use of a technique called therapeutic touch was especially reviewed by Sokal, who concluded, "nearly all the pseudoscientific systems to be examined in this essay are based philosophically on vitalism" and added that "Mainstream science has rejected vitalism since at least the 1930s, for a plethora of good reasons that have only become stronger with time."

Joseph C. Keating, Jr. discusses vitalism's past and present roles in chiropractic and calls vitalism "a form of bio-theology." He further explains that:

"Vitalism is that rejected tradition in biology which proposes that life is sustained and explained by an unmeasurable, intelligent force or energy. The supposed effects of vitalism are the manifestations of life itself, which in turn are the basis for inferring the concept in the first place. This circular reasoning offers pseudo-explanation, and may deceive us into believing we have explained some aspect of biology when in fact we have only labeled our ignorance. 'Explaining an unknown (life) with an unknowable (Innate),' suggests chiropractor Joseph Donahue, 'is absurd'."

Keating views vitalism as incompatible with scientific thinking:

"Chiropractors are not unique in recognizing a tendency and capacity for self-repair and auto-regulation of human physiology. But we surely stick out like a sore thumb among professions which claim to be scientifically based by our unrelenting commitment to vitalism. So long as we propound the 'One cause, one cure' rhetoric of Innate, we should expect to be met by ridicule from the wider health science community. Chiropractors can't have it both ways. Our theories cannot be both dogmatically held vitalistic constructs and be scientific at the same time. The purposiveness, consciousness and rigidity of the Palmers' Innate should be rejected."

Keating also mentions Skinner's viewpoint:

"Vitalism has many faces and has sprung up in many areas of scientific inquiry. Psychologist B.F. Skinner, for example, pointed out the irrationality of attributing behavior to mental states and traits. Such 'mental way stations,' he argued, amount to excess theoretical baggage which fails to advance cause-and-effect explanations by substituting an unfathomable psychology of 'mind'."

According to Williams, "oday, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force." "Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality."

Victor Stenger states that the term "bioenergetics" "is applied in biochemistry to refer to the readily measurable exchanges of energy within organisms, and between organisms and the environment, which occur by normal physical and chemical processes. This is not, however, what the new vitalists have in mind. They imagine the bioenergetic field as a holistic living force that goes beyond reductionist physics and chemistry."

Such a field is sometimes explained as electromagnetic, though some advocates also make confused appeals to quantum physics. Joanne Stefanatos states that "The principles of energy medicine originate in quantum physics." Stenger offers several explanations as to why this line of reasoning may be misplaced. He explains that energy exists in discrete packets called quanta. Energy fields are composed of their component parts and so only exist when quanta are present. Therefore, energy fields are not holistic, but are rather a system of discrete parts that must obey the laws of physics. This also means that energy fields are not instantaneous. These facts of quantum physics place limitations on the infinite, continuous field that is used by some theorists to describe so-called "human energy fields". Stenger continues, explaining that the effects of EM forces have been measured by physicists as accurately as one part in a billion and there is yet to be any evidence that living organisms emit a unique field.

Vitalistic thinking has been identified in the naive biological theories of children: "Recent experimental results show that a majority of preschoolers tend to choose vitalistic explanations as most plausible. Vitalism, together with other forms of intermediate causality, constitute unique causal devices for naive biology as a core domain of thought."

See also

Notes

  1. Stéphane Leduc and D'Arcy Thompson (On Growth and Form) published a series of works that in Evelyn Fox Keller's view took on the task of uprooting the remaining vestiges of vitalism, essentially by showing that the principles of physics and chemistry were enough, by themselves, to account for the growth and development of biological form. On the other hand, Michael Ruse notes that D'Arcy Thompson's avoidance of natural selection had an "odor of spirit forces" about it.
  2. In 1845, Adolph Kolbe succeeded in making acetic acid from inorganic compounds, and in the 1850s, Marcellin Berthelot repeated this feat for numerous organic compounds. In retrospect, Wöhler's work was the beginning of the end of Berzelius's vitalist hypothesis, but only in retrospect, as Ramberg had shown.
  3. See; briefly, some philosophers see emergentism as midway between traditional spiritual vitalism and mechanistic reductionism; others argue that, structurally, emergentism is equivalent to vitalism. See also.

References

  1. ^ Bechtel, William; Williamson, Robert C. (1998). "Vitalism". In E. Craig (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge.{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  2. Evelyn Fox Keller, Making Sense of Life Explaining Biological Development with Models, Metaphors, and Machines. Harvard University Press, 2002.
  3. Ruse, Michael (2013). "17. From Organicism to Mechanism-and Halfway Back?". In Henning, Brian G.; Scarfe, Adam (eds.). Beyond Mechanism: Putting Life Back Into Biology. Lexington Books. p. 419. ISBN 9780739174371.
  4. Williams, Elizabeth Ann (2003). A Cultural History of Medical Vitalism in Enlightenment Montpellier. Ashgate. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-7546-0881-3.
  5. ^ "Developmental Biology 8e Online: A Selective History of Induction". Archived from the original on October 31, 2006.
  6. ^ Dyde, Sean (2013). "Chapter 5: Life and the Mind in Nineteenth-Century Britain". In Normandin, Sebastian; Wolfe, T. Charles (eds.). Vitalism and the Scientific Image in Post-Enlightenment Life Science, 1800–2010. Springer. p. 104. ISBN 978-94-007-2445-7. In medicine and biology, vitalism has been seen as a philosophically-charged term, a pseudoscientific gloss that corrupted scientific practice …
  7. Jidenu, Paulin (1996) African Philosophy, 2nd Ed. Indiana University Press, ISBN 0-253-21096-8, p.16.
  8. Birch & Cobb 1985, p. 75
  9. ^ Birch & Cobb 1985, pp. 76–78
  10. ^ Ede, Andrew. (2007) The Rise and Decline of Colloid Science in North America, 1900–1935: The Neglected Dimension, p. 23
  11. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, p. 238
  12. Wilkinson, Ian (10 June 2002). "History of Clinical Chemistry". EJIFCC. 13 (4): 114–118. ISSN 1650-3414. PMC 6208063.
  13. Kinne-Saffran, E.; Kinne, R. K. H. (August 7, 1999). "Vitalism and Synthesis of Urea". American Journal of Nephrology. 19 (2): 290–294. doi:10.1159/000013463. PMID 10213830. S2CID 71727190 – via www.karger.com.
  14. Ramberg, Peter J. (2000). "The Death of Vitalism and the Birth of Organic Chemistry: Wohler's Urea Synthesis and the Disciplinary Identity of Organic Chemistry". Ambix. 47 (3): 170–195. doi:10.1179/amb.2000.47.3.170. PMID 11640223. S2CID 44613876.
  15. Schummer, Joachim (December 2003). "The notion of nature in chemistry" (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A. 34 (4): 705–736. Bibcode:2003SHPSA..34..705S. doi:10.1016/S0039-3681(03)00050-5.
  16. Otis, Laura (October 2004). "Johannes Peter Müller (1801-1858)" (PDF). Virtual Laboratory: Essays and Resources on the Experimentalization of Life (Max Planck Institute).
  17. Galatzer-Levy, R. M. (August 7, 1976). "Psychic Energy: A Historical Perspective". Ann. Psychoanal. 4: 41–61 – via PEP Web.
  18. Mayr, Ernst (2002). "BOTANY ONLINE: Ernst MAYR: Walter Arndt Lecture: The Autonomy of Biology". Archived from the original on 2006-09-26. Retrieved 2006-09-24.
  19. Ernst Mayr Toward a new philosophy of biology: observations of an evolutionist 1988, p. 13. ISBN 978-0674896666.
  20. Noll, Richard. "Jung's concept of die Dominanten (the Dominants) (1997)" – via www.academia.edu. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  21. ^ Bowler, Peter J. Reconciling science and religion: the debate in early-twentieth-century Britain, 2001, pp. 168–169. ISBN 978-0226068589.
  22. ^ Mayr, Ernst (2010). "The Decline of Vitalism". In Bedau, Mark A.; Cleland, Carol E. (eds.). The Nature of Life: Classical and Contemporary Perspectives from Philosophy and Science. Cambridge University Press. pp. 93–95. ISBN 9781139488655. Yet considering how dominant vitalism was in biology and for how long a period it prevailed, it is surprising how rapidly and completely it collapsed. The last support of vitalism as a viable concept in biology disappeared about 1930." (p. 94) From p. 95: "Vitalism survived even longer in the writings of philosophers than it did in the writings of physicists. But so far as I know, there are no vitalists among the philosophers of biology who started publishing after 1965. Nor do I know of a single reputable living biologist who still supports straightforward vitalism. The few late twentieth-century biologists with vitalist leanings (A. Hardy, S. Wright, A. Portmann) are no longer alive.
  23. Schultz, S.G. (1998). "A century of (epithelial) transport physiology: from vitalism to molecular cloning". The American Journal of Physiology. 274 (1 Pt 1): C13–23. doi:10.1152/ajpcell.1998.274.1.C13. PMID 9458708.
  24. Gilbert, S.F.; Sarkar, S. (2000). "Embracing complexity: organicism for the 21st century". Developmental Dynamics. 219 (1): 1–9. doi:10.1002/1097-0177(2000)9999:9999<::AID-DVDY1036>3.0.CO;2-A. PMID 10974666.
  25. O’Connor, Timothy (2021). "Emergent Properties". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  26. Emmeche, C (16 July 2001). "Does a robot have an Umwelt? Reflections on the qualitative biosemiotics of Jakob von Uexküll" (PDF). Semiotica. 2001 (134): 653–693. doi:10.1515/semi.2001.048.
  27. Emmeche, C. (1997) Explaining Emergence: towards an ontology of levels. Journal for General Philosophy of Science available online Archived 2006-10-06 at the Wayback Machine
  28. Best, M.; Neuhauser, D.; Slavin, L. (2003). "Evaluating Mesmerism, Paris, 1784: the controversy over the blinded placebo controlled trials has not stopped". Quality & Safety in Health Care. 12 (3): 232–3. doi:10.1136/qhc.12.3.232. PMC 1743715. PMID 12792017.
  29. "Complementary and Alternative Medicine – U.S. National Library of Medicine Collection Development Manual". Retrieved 2008-03-31.
  30. ^ Rubik, Beverly. "Bioenergetic Medicines". American Medical Student Association Foundation. Archived from the original on 2006-02-14. Retrieved 8 November 2006.
  31. Mihi a docto doctore / Demandatur causam et rationem quare / Opium facit dormire. / A quoi respondeo, / Quia est in eo / Vertus dormitiva, / Cujus est natura / Sensus assoupire. Le Malade imaginaire, (French Wikisource)
  32. The Physical Basis of Life, Pall Mall Gazette, 1869
  33. Crick, Francis (1967) Of Molecules and Men; Great Minds Series Prometheus Books 2004, reviewed here. Crick's remark is cited and discussed in: Hein H (2004) Molecular biology vs. organicism: The enduring dispute between mechanism and vitalism. Synthese 20:238–253, who describes Crick's remark as "raising spectral red herrings".
  34. ^ Pseudoscience and Postmodernism: Antagonists or Fellow-Travelers? (pdf)
  35. "Joseph C. Keating, Jr., PhD: Biographical sketch". Archived from the original on May 25, 2006.
  36. ^ Keating, Joseph C. (2002), "The Meanings of Innate", The Journal of the Canadian Chiropractic Association, 46 (1): 4–10, PMC 2505097
  37. ^ Williams, William F., ed. (2013). "Vitalism". Encyclopedia of Pseudoscience: From Alien Abductions to Zone Therapy (revised ed.). p. 367. ISBN 9781135955229. VITALISM – The concept that bodily functions are due to a 'vital principle' or 'life force' that is distinct from the physical forces explainable by the laws of chemistry and physics. Many alternative approaches to modern medicine are rooted in vitalism. ... The exact nature of the vital force was debated by early philosophers, but vitalism in one form or another remained the preferred thinking behind most science and medicine until 1828. That year, German scientist Friedrich Wöhler (1800–82) synthesized an organic compound from an inorganic substance, a process that vitalists considered to be impossible. ... Vitalists claim to be scientific, but in fact they reject the scientific method with its basic postulates of cause and effect and of provability. They often regard subjective experience to be more valid than objective material reality. Today, vitalism is one of the ideas that form the basis for many pseudoscientific health systems that claim that illnesses are caused by a disturbance or imbalance of the body's vital force.
  38. "Victor J. Stenger's site". Archived from the original on March 3, 2016.
  39. ^ Stenger, Victor J. (Spring–Summer 1999). "The Physics of 'Alternative Medicine': Bioenergetic Fields". The Scientific Review of Alternative Medicine. 3 (1). Archived from the original on 2006-12-18. Retrieved 2006-12-03.
  40. Stefanatos, J. 1997, Introduction to Bioenergetic Medicine, Shoen, A.M. and S.G. Wynn, Complementary and Alternative Veterinary Medicine: Principles and Practices, Mosby-Yearbook, Chicago.
  41. Biley, Francis C. 2005, Unitary Health Care: Martha Rogers' Science of Unitary Human Beings, University of Wales College of Medicine, viewed 30 November 2006, "RogersHomepage". Archived from the original on 2006-12-05. Retrieved 2006-12-02.
  42. Inagaki, K.; Hatano, G. (2004). "'Vitalistic causality in young children's naive biology.'". Trends Cogn Sci. 8 (8): 356–62. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.06.004. PMID 15335462. S2CID 29256474.

Sources

External links

Evolutionary biology
Evolution
Population
genetics
Development
Of taxa
Of organs
Of processes
Tempo and modes
Speciation
History
Philosophy
Related
Philosophy of biology
Themes
Evolution
Philosophers of biology
Biologists
Related
Philosophy of science
Concepts
Theories
Philosophy of...
Related topics
Philosophers of science
Precursors
  • Category
  • Philosophy portal
  • icon Science portal
  • Categories: