Revision as of 15:14, 29 July 2022 editDarylprasad (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users6,982 edits removing old text that was in breach of copyrightTags: Reverted copyright violation template removed nowiki added Visual edit: Switched← Previous edit | Revision as of 15:15, 29 July 2022 edit undoPraxidicae (talk | contribs)Edit filter helpers, Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, Page movers, IP block exemptions, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers169,003 edits Reverted 1 edit by Darylprasad (talk): Once again..Tags: Twinkle Undo RevertedNext edit → | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{copyvio-revdel|url=https://www.talentshare.org/~mm9n/articles/cosmos/5.htm|url2=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/|start1=1094150342|end1=1101132711}} | |||
{{Short description|Greek philosopher and founder of neoplatonism (204 or 205–270)}} | |||
{{Short description|Greek philosopher and founder of neoplatonism (c. 204/5–270)}} | |||
{{Distinguish|Photinus}} | {{Distinguish|Photinus}} | ||
{{Infobox philosopher | {{Infobox philosopher | ||
| region = ] | | region = ] | ||
| era = ] | | era = ] | ||
| image = Plotinos.jpg | | image = Plotinos.jpg | ||
| caption = Head in white marble. The identification as Plotinus is plausible but not proven. | |||
| caption = Portrait in white marble from the second half of the 3rd century CE, perhaps of Plotinus, located in the ]<ref>{{Cite web |date=8 May 2022 |title=Regio V - Insula II - Terme del Filosofo (V,II,6-7) (Baths of the Philosopher) |url=http://www.ostia-antica.org/regio5/2/2-6.htm |url-status=live |access-date=13 July 2022 |website=Ostia - Virtual museum}}</ref>{{Sfn|Hermansen|1982|p=78|loc=The Guilds of Ostia}} | |||
| name = Plotinus | | name = Plotinus | ||
| birth_date = 204 |
| birth_date = {{circa|204/5}} | ||
| birth_place = ] |
| birth_place = ] or ], ], ] | ||
| death_date = {{Death year and age|270| |
| death_date = {{Death year and age|270|205}} | ||
| death_place = ], Roman Empire | | death_place = ], Roman Empire | ||
| notable_works = '']''<ref name="Gerson 2017">{{cite book |author-last=Gerson |author-first=Lloyd P. |author-link=Lloyd P. Gerson |year=2017 |chapter=Plotinus and Platonism |editor1-last=Tarrant |editor1-first=Harold |editor2-last=Renaud |editor2-first=François |editor3-last=Baltzly |editor3-first=Dirk |editor3-link=Dirk Baltzly |editor4-last=Layne |editor4-first=Danielle A. |title=Brill's Companion to the Reception of Plato in Antiquity |location=] and ] |publisher=] |series=Brill's Companions to Classical Reception |volume=13 |pages=316–335 |doi=10.1163/9789004355385_018 |isbn=978-90-04-27069-5 |issn=2213-1426}}</ref> | |||
| notable_works = '']''{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}} | |||
| school_tradition = ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica">{{cite encyclopedia |last1=Armstrong |first1=A. Hilary |last2=Duignan |first2=Brian |last3=Lotha |first3=Gloria |last4=Rodriguez |first4=Emily |date=1 January 2021 |origyear=20 July 1998 |title=Plotinus |url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Plotinus |encyclopedia=] |location=] |publisher=] |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210417025334/https://www.britannica.com/biography/Plotinus |archive-date=17 April 2021 |url-status=live |access-date=5 August 2021 |quote=Plotinus (born 205 CE, Lyco, or Lycopolis, Egypt?—died 270, Campania), ancient philosopher, the centre of an influential circle of intellectuals and men of letters in 3rd-century Rome, who is regarded by modern scholars as the founder of the neoplatonic school of philosophy. In his 28th year—he seems to have been rather a late developer—Plotinus felt an impulse to study philosophy and thus went to ]. He attended the lectures of the most eminent professors in Alexandria at the time, which reduced him to a state of complete depression. In the end, a friend who understood what he wanted took him to hear the self-taught philosopher ]. When he had heard Ammonius speak, Plotinus said, “This is the man I was looking for,” and stayed with him for 11 years. At the end of his time with Ammonius, Plotinus joined the expedition of the ] ] against ] (242–243), with the intention of trying to learn something at first hand about the philosophies of the Persians and Indians. The expedition came to a disastrous end in ], however, when Gordian was murdered by the soldiers and ] was proclaimed emperor. Plotinus escaped with difficulty and made his way back to ]. From there he went to ], where he settled at the age of 40. Plotinus's own thought shows some striking similarities to ], but he never actually made contact with Eastern sages because of the failure of the expedition. Though direct or indirect contact with Indians educated in their own religious-philosophical traditions may not have been impossible in 3rd-century Alexandria, the resemblances of the philosophy of Plotinus to Indian thought were more likely a natural development of the Greek tradition that he inherited.}}</ref><ref name="Stanford1">{{cite encyclopedia |author-last=Gerson |author-first=Lloyd P. |date=Fall 2018 |title=Plotinus |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/ |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |editor-link=Edward N. Zalta |encyclopedia=] |publisher=The Metaphysics Research Lab, ], ] |issn=1095-5054 |oclc=643092515 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20181126171129/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/ |archive-date=26 November 2018 |access-date=5 August 2021 |quote=Plotinus (204/5 – 270 C.E.), is generally regarded as the founder of neoplatonism. He is one of the most influential philosophers in antiquity after ] and ]. The term ‘neoplatonism’ is an invention of early 19th century European scholarship and indicates the penchant of historians for dividing ‘periods’ in history. In this case, the term was intended to indicate that Plotinus initiated a new phase in the development of the Platonic tradition. What this ‘newness’ amounted to, if anything, is controversial, largely because one's assessment of it depends upon one's assessment of what Platonism is. In fact, Plotinus (like all his successors) regarded himself simply as a Platonist, that is, as an expositor and defender of the philosophical position whose greatest exponent was Plato himself. The three basic principles of Plotinus' metaphysics are called by him ‘the One’ (or, equivalently, ‘the Good’), Intellect, and Soul. These principles are both ultimate ontological realities and explanatory principles. Plotinus believed that they were recognized by Plato as such, as well as by the entire subsequent Platonic tradition. ] informs us that during the first ten years of his time in Rome, Plotinus lectured exclusively on the philosophy of Ammonius. During this time he also wrote nothing. Porphyry tells us that when he himself arrived in Rome in 263, the first 21 of Plotinus' treatises had already been written. The remainder of the 54 treatises constituting his ''Enneads'' were written in the last seven or eight years of his life.}}</ref><ref name="Siorvanes 2018">{{cite book |author-last=Siorvanes |author-first=Lucas |year=2018 |chapter=Plotinus and Neoplatonism: The Creation of a New Synthesis |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=NfxdDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA847 |editor1-last=Keyser |editor1-first=Paul T. |editor2-last=Scarborough |editor2-first=John |title=Oxford Handbook of Science and Medicine in the Classical World |location=] |publisher=] |doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199734146.013.78 |pages=847–868 |isbn=9780199734146 |lccn=2017049555}}</ref> | |||
| school_tradition = ]{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=9|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=21|loc=Platonist Curricula and their Influence by Tarrant}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2010a|p=439|loc=Hierocles of Alexandria by Schibli}}{{Sfn|Sorabji|2005|p=6|loc=Introduction}} | |||
| main_interests = ], ], ] |
| main_interests = ], ], ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/><ref name="Halfwassen 2014">{{cite book |author-last=Halfwassen |author-first=Jens |year=2014 |chapter=The Metaphysics of the One |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yhcWBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA182 |editor1-last=Remes |editor1-first=Pauliina |editor2-last=Slaveva-Griffin |editor2-first=Svetla |title=The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism |location=] and ] |publisher=] |series=Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy |pages=182–199 |isbn=9781138573963}}</ref> | ||
| notable_ideas = ] of all things from ] |
| notable_ideas = ] of all things from ]<ref name="Halfwassen 2014"/><br/>Three main ]: ], ], and ]<ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Halfwassen 2014"/><br/>]<ref name="Halfwassen 2014"/> | ||
| influences = {{flatlist| | | influences = {{flatlist| | ||
* ] |
* ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> | ||
* ] |
* ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/> | ||
* ] |
* ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> | ||
* ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007">{{cite book |last=Stamatellos |first=Giannis |year=2007 |chapter=Matter and Soul |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0r0yH93JWOIC&pg=PA161 |title=Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences on Plotinus' Enneads |location=] |publisher=] |pages=161–172 |isbn=978-0-7914-7061-9 |lccn=2006017562}}</ref> | * ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007">{{cite book |last=Stamatellos |first=Giannis |year=2007 |chapter=Matter and Soul |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0r0yH93JWOIC&pg=PA161 |title=Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences on Plotinus' Enneads |location=] |publisher=] |pages=161–172 |isbn=978-0-7914-7061-9 |lccn=2006017562}}</ref> | ||
* ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> | * ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> | ||
Line 27: | Line 28: | ||
* ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> | * ]<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> | ||
}} | }} | ||
| influenced = ], |
| influenced = ],<ref name="Gerson 2017"/> ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ] | ||
}} | }} | ||
{{Neoplatonism}} | {{Neoplatonism}} | ||
'''Plotinus''' ({{IPAc-en|p|l|ɒ|ˈ|t|aɪ|n|ə|s}}; {{lang-grc-gre|Πλωτῖνος}}, ''Plōtînos''; {{circa|204/5}} – 270 CE) was a ] in the ] tradition, born and raised in ]. Plotinus is regarded by modern scholarship as the founder of ].<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> His teacher was the self-taught philosopher ], who belonged to the ].<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> Historians of the 19th century invented the term "neoplatonism"<ref name="Stanford1"/> and applied it to refer to Plotinus and his philosophy, which was vastly influential during ], the ], and the ].<ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> Much of the biographical information about Plotinus comes from ]'s preface to his edition of Plotinus' most notable literary work, '']''.<ref name="Gerson 2017"/> In his ] writings, Plotinus described three fundamental principles: ], ], and the ].<ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Halfwassen 2014"/><ref>{{cite web|title=Who was Plotinus?|website=] |url=http://www.abc.net.au/rn/philosopherszone/stories/2011/3237626.htm|date=2011-06-07}}</ref> His works have inspired centuries of ], ], ], ], and ] metaphysicians and ], including developing precepts that influence mainstream theological concepts within religions, such as his work on duality of the One in two metaphysical states. | |||
'''Plotinus''' ({{IPAc-en|p|l|ɒ|ˈ|t|aɪ|n|ə|s}}; {{lang-grc-gre|Πλωτῖνος}}, ''Plōtînos'') (204{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}}{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Corrigan|2005|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Edwards|2000|p=xxiv|loc=Introduction}} or 205{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ii|loc=front matter}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=7 (footnote 1)|loc=The Life of Plotinus}}–270 CE{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ii|loc=front matter}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=129|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}) was a neoplatonic{{Sfn|Pavlos|Janby|Emilsson|Tollefsen|2019|p=203|loc=The doctrine of immanent realism in Maximus the Confessor by Mateiescu}} philosopher likely to have been born in Lycopolis (modern day ]{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=4|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|Page|1952|p=v|loc=Biographical Note}}), Roman{{Sfn|Copenhaver|2002|p=xx|loc=Introduction}} Egypt,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=|loc=Life, works and philosophical background|pp=11-12}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Corrigan|2005|p=1|loc=Introduction}} and is regarded by contemporary scholarship as the founder of ].{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ii|loc=front matter}}<ref name=":1">{{Cite web |last=Armstrong |first=A. Hilary |date=1 January 2022 |others=Lotha, Duignan, Rodriguez |title=Plotinus |url=https://www.britannica.com/biography/Plotinus |url-status=live |access-date=12 July 2022 |website=Encyclopedia Britannica}}</ref><ref name=":2">{{Cite web |last=Gerson |first=Lloyd |date=28 June 2018b |title=Plotinus |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/ |url-status=live |access-date=12 July 2022 |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2018b}}}}</ref> His name is of Roman{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=12|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=114|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} origin and he was from a Greek,{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=2|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=5|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} Roman{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}} or a ] Egyptian family.{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=2|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=5|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} | |||
Before Plotinus established the first neoplatonic school in Rome in 245 CE,{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Corrigan|2005|p=1|loc=Introduction}} he was taught in ] for about 10 or 11 years by the self-taught<ref name=":1" /> philosopher ],{{Sfn|Gerson|2018a|p=317|loc=Plotinus and Platonism by Gerson}} who belonged to the ] tradition.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018b|loc=Life and Writings: "Plotinus’ teacher, Ammonius Saccas"|p=webpage}}{{Sfn|Keyser|Scarborough|2018|p=847|loc=Plotinus and Neoplatonism: The Creation of a New Synthesis by Siorvanes}} All of the ''reliable'' information about Plotinus' life comes from a biography written by his student ] as an introduction to Plotinus' work the ''].''{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=11|loc=Introduction}} In the ''Enneads'' Plotinus describes three fundamental ] principles: ] (τὸ ἕν) the first ];{{Sfn|Gerson|2020|p=289|loc=English Glossary of Important Terms}} ] (νοῦς) the second hypostasis;{{Sfn|Gerson|2020|p=287|loc=English Glossary of Important Terms}} and ] (ψυχή) the third{{Sfn|Gerson|2020|p=293|loc=English Glossary of Important Terms}} hypostasis.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=9|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=20|loc=Platonist curricula and their influence by Tarrant}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018b|loc=The Three Fundamental Principles of Plotinus’ Metaphysics: "The three basic principles of Plotinus’ metaphysics are called by him ‘the One’ (or, equivalently, ‘the Good’), Intellect, and Soul (see V 1; V 9.)."|p=webpage}} | |||
Plotinus' ''Enneads'' contain a unified synthesis of nearly eight centuries of Greek philosophy, and explicitly mentions the philosophers: ], ] and the ], ], ], ], ], ], ], and ].{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=10|loc=Plotinus: The Platonic tradition and the foundation of Neoplatonism by Gatti translated by Gerson}} The ''Enneads'' passed on the Platonic tradition to centuries of ], ], and early-modern philosophers, and ] philosophy and religion,{{Sfn|Keyser|Scarborough|2018|p=864 (19 of 24 in Online Publication)|loc=Plotinus and Neoplatonism: The Creation of a New Synthesis, 6. Influence by Siorvanes.}} as well as having an enormous influence on art, poetry, and the nonacademic esoteric tradition.{{Sfn|Clark|2016|p=9|loc=Why Read Plotinus?}} | |||
== Biography == | == Biography == | ||
] reported that Plotinus was 66 years old when he died in 270, the second year of the reign of the ] ], thus giving us the year of his teacher's birth as around 205. ] reported that Plotinus was born in Lyco, which could either refer to the modern ] in ] or ], in ].<ref name="Gerson 2017"/><ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> This has led to speculations that he may have been either native ], ] Egyptian,<ref>Bilolo, M.: ''La notion de « l’Un » dans les Ennéades de Plotin et dans les Hymnes thébains. Contribution à l’étude des sources égyptiennes du néo-platonisme.'' In: D. Kessler, R. Schulz (Eds.), "Gedenkschrift für Winfried Barta ''ḥtp dj n ḥzj''" (Münchner Ägyptologische Untersuchungen, Bd. 4), Frankfurt; Berlin; Bern; New York; Paris; Wien: Peter Lang, 1995, pp. 67–91.</ref> ],<ref name=":1">{{Cite book |last=Gerson |first=Lloyd P. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=359nRoAU4iEC |title=Plotinus |date=1999 |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-0-415-20352-4 |pages=XII (12) |language=en}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book |last1=Rist |first1=John M. |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=n49OAAAAIAAJ |title=Plotinus: Road to Reality |last2=Rist |date=1967 |publisher=CUP Archive |isbn=978-0-521-06085-1 |pages=4 |language=en}}</ref> or ].<ref>"Plotinus." The Columbia Electronic Encyclopedia, Sixth Edition. ], 2003.</ref> Historian ] states that Plotinus was "almost certainly" a Greek.<ref name=":1" /> | |||
The neoplatonic philosopher ], a student and associate of Plotinus in the last six{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=114|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} or eight{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}} years of his life, and his eventual biographer, says in his biographical work ''Life of Plotinus'' (''Vita Plotini'',{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}} which is the most reliable authority for the life of Plotinus{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Corrigan|2005|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=11|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=114|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}}) that Plotinus never talked about his family or his country to him; and so what we know of Plotinus' birthplace and nationality of his family is uncertain.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=114|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} In ''Life of Plotinus'', Porphyry also reports that Plotinus did not reveal his birth date or birth month, but he knew Plotinus died in the 66th{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=vii|loc=Preface}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.34-2.35|ps=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} ''year of his life''{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=26|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} (i.e. after he was 65 and before he was 66 years old) at the end of the second year of the reign of the ] ] in 270 CE, hence giving us the year of Plotinus' birth as 204 or 205 CE.{{Sfn|Smith|1974|p=xi|loc=Introduction}} | |||
Plotinus had an inherent distrust of materiality (an attitude common to ]), holding to the view that phenomena were a poor image or mimicry (]) of something "higher and intelligible" (VI.I) which was the "truer part of genuine Being". This distrust extended to the ], including his own; it is reported by Porphyry that at one point he refused to have his portrait painted, presumably for much the same reasons of dislike. Likewise, Plotinus never discussed his ancestry, childhood, or his place or date of birth.<ref name=":0" /> From all accounts his personal and social life exhibited the highest moral and spiritual standards. | |||
=== Birthplace === | |||
According to the 5th century historian ], in his work ''Lives of Philosophers and Sophists,'' Plotinus was born in 'a place called Lyco'; however, that work was written in 455 CE,{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=4|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} nearly two centuries after Plotinus died, and we do not know where Eunapius got his information from, as many possible sources have been lost,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=12|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} or if his information is reliable.{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=11 (and footnote 1)|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=115|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} The ], a 10th-century ] encyclopedia, calls Plotinus 'a Lycopolitan', and the 11th century Byzantine empress ] says, in what may be her work ''Bed of Violets'',{{Sfn|Bigg|1895|pp=181-182|loc=Plotinus}} that 'some say he was born at Lyco, a ] of Lycopolis in Egypt'.{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=115|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} The ancient city of Lycopolis referred to by those reports is usually taken by scholars to be the modern day city ]{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=4|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}}{{Sfn|Clark|2016|p=3|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|Page|1952|p=v|loc=Biographical Note}} (Assiout,{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} ancient Egyptian: ''Zawty{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=4|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}}'') which was the capital of the 13th nome of Upper Egypt situated between ] and ],{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=4|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} and infrequently taken by scholars to be its colony ] in the Delta.{{Sfn|Clark|2016|p=3|loc=Introduction}} | |||
Plotinus took up the study of ] at the age of twenty-eight, around the year 232, and travelled to ] to study.<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> There he was dissatisfied with every teacher he encountered, until an acquaintance suggested he listen to the ideas of the ] Platonist philosopher ].<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> Upon hearing Ammonius' lecture, Plotinus declared to his friend: "this is the man I was looking for",<ref name="Britannica"/> began to study intently under his new instructor, and remained with him as his student for eleven years.<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Stanford1"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> Besides Ammonius, Plotinus was also influenced by the philosophical works of ],<ref name="Gerson 2017"/> the ] philosophers ] and ],<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> the ] philosophers ] and ], along with various ]<ref name="Gerson 2017"/> and ].<ref name="Stamatellos 2007"/> | |||
All those reports have led to speculations that Plotinus could have been a native Egyptian,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|loc=Life, works and philosophical background|pp=11-12}} a ]{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=2|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=5|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} Egyptian, a Greek or a Roman.{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Rist|1967|p=4|loc=Introduction}} The speculation that Plotinus was Roman comes from the meagre{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} conjecture{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=114|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} that the name 'Plotinus' is the male version of the name inherited from the 2nd century Roman empress ], whose husband was the Roman emperor ].{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=12|loc=Introduction}} Some late 19th century scholarship added to that speculation by saying that Plotinus may have been a ], descended from a ] of the empress.{{Sfn|Bigg|1895|pp=181-182|loc=Plotinus}} The eminent 21st century American-Canadian Plotinian scholar Professor ] relates, in his introduction to a 2010 publication, that Plotinus was 'likely a Greek', but he also says, in the following sentence, that it is possible that Plotinus 'came from a ] Egyptian or Roman family'.{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}} | |||
=== Expedition to Persia and return to Rome === | |||
=== Alexandria === | |||
After having spent eleven years in Alexandria, he then decided, at the age of around 38, to investigate the philosophical teachings of the ] and ].<ref name="Britannica"/><ref>Porphyry, ''On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books'', Ch. 3 (in Armstrong's Loeb translation, "he became eager to make acquaintance with the Persian philosophical discipline and that prevailing among the Indians").</ref> In the pursuit of this endeavor he left Alexandria and joined the army of the Roman emperor ] as it marched on ] (242-243 C.E.).<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> However, ] was a failure, and on Gordian's eventual death Plotinus found himself abandoned in a hostile land, and only with difficulty found his way back to safety in ].<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/> | |||
Despite his reluctance to talk about his own life, Plotinus did relate some details of his early life to ].{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.1-3.6}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=8-9}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} In 211 CE,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=11|loc=Chronology}} when he was about six or seven years old, he was already under the instruction of a grammarian.{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=7|loc=Life of Plotinus and Order of his Writings by Porphyry}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: line 3.5}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}} There is then a period of about 20 years, of which we know nothing,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=27|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} and our information about him continues from 231 CE,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=11|loc=Chronology}} when he was about 27 years old, at which time he felt the impulse to study philosophy and was recommended to teachers of philosophy in ], who at that time were held in high esteem.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.6-3.8}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} | |||
At the age of forty, during the reign of Emperor ], he came to ], where he stayed for most of the remainder of his life.<ref name="Britannica"/><ref name="Siorvanes 2018"/><ref name=":0">{{Cite book|title=Beauty and the mystic : Plotinus and Hawkins|last=Leete, Helen, 1938-|date=23 December 2016|isbn=9780987524836|location=Epping, N.S.W|oclc=967937243}}</ref> There he attracted a number of students. His innermost circle included ], ] of ], the Senator ], and ], a doctor who devoted himself to learning from Plotinus and attending to him until his death. Other students included: ], an ] by ancestry who died before Plotinus, leaving him a legacy and some land; ], a critic and poet; ], a doctor of ]; and ] from Alexandria. He had students amongst the ] beside Castricius, such as ], ], and ]. Women were also numbered amongst his students, including Gemina, in whose house he lived during his residence in Rome, and her daughter, also Gemina; and Amphiclea, the wife of Ariston the son of ].<ref>Porphyry, ''Vita Plotini'', 9. See also Emma C. Clarke, ], and Jackson P. Hershbell (1999), ''Iamblichus on The Mysteries'', page xix. SBL. who say that "to gain some credible chronology, one assumes that Ariston married Amphicleia some time after Plotinus's death"</ref> Finally, Plotinus was a correspondent of the philosopher ]. | |||
In Alexandria, Plotinus attended philosophical lectures, but came away from those lectures sad and discouraged, and told a close friend, who understood his troubles and suggested that he attend a lecture by the Platonist{{Sfn|Gerson|2010a|p=284|loc=Origen by Prinzivalli}} philosopher ].{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.6-3.8}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} Ammonius is only partly{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} known to us through the information in Porphyry's biography of Plotinus,{{Sfn|Dillon|1996|pp=281-282|loc=The Neopythagoreans}}{{Sfn|Smith|2004|p=4|loc=Part I: Setting the Agenda, The Philosophy of Plotinus, Introduction}} and at the time was teaching or had already taught Antoninus;{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} Erennius (Herennius);{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=217|loc=III.B.1. The king}}{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} ];{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=260|loc=III.B.8. Homeland and empire}}{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} Olympius;{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} ],{{Sfn|McGuckin|2004|p=5|loc=Life of Origen}}{{Sfn|Trigg|2002|p=12|loc=Introduction}} (who may have been another Origen known as ]);{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books|pp=9, 28, 32, 34, 61, 74}} and Theodosius.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=28|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books: 3.6-3.13}} In 231{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=31|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} or 232 CE,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}} after hearing a lecture by Ammonius, Plotinus declared to his friend: 'this is the man I was looking for', and after that day began studying under Ammonius, and remained his close associate for 11{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=31|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} years, by which time he was 38 years old.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.12-3.21}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} | |||
=== |
=== Later life === | ||
While in Rome Plotinus also gained the respect of the Emperor ] and his wife ]. At one point Plotinus attempted to interest Gallienus in rebuilding an abandoned settlement in ], known as the 'City of Philosophers', where the inhabitants would live under the constitution set out in ]'s ''Laws''. An Imperial subsidy was never granted, for reasons unknown to Porphyry, who reports the incident. | |||
After living about 11{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=31|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} years in Alexandria, and having made much progress in his study of philosophy, Plotinus decided to investigate the philosophical teachings of the ] and ],{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.15-3.22}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} (apparently the ]{{Sfn|Smith|2004|p=2|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Perl|2015|p=2|loc=Introduction to the Series}}).{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}} In the pursuit of this endeavor, he left Alexandria and joined the army of the 18{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=127|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} or 19{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=198|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} year-old Roman emperor ] in 242{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}} or 243 CE,{{Sfn|Garson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}} as a philosopher and not a soldier.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=30|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}}{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}} The army was headed to march against the great ]{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=10|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} (king of kings) King Sapor{{Sfn|Harris|1982|p=287|loc=The Influence of Indian Philosophy on Neoplatonism by Tripathi}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=116|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} (]){{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=10|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} of ]{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=194|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} Persia.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.15-3.22}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} The ], founded in 224 CE, was particularly unreceptive to Graeco-Roman influences and held onto a rigid ] orthodoxy.{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=10|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} It is conjectured that the religious teacher ] was in the Persian army headed by King Shapur I.{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=10|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} | |||
Plotinus subsequently went to live in ]. He spent his final days in seclusion on an estate in ] which his friend Zethos had bequeathed him. According to the account of Eustochius, who attended him at the end, Plotinus' final words were: "Try to raise the divine in yourselves to the divine in the all."<ref>Mark Edwards, ''Neoplatonic Saints: The Lives of Plotinus and Proclus by Their Students'', Liverpool University Press, 2000, p. 4 n. 20.</ref> Eustochius records that a snake crept under the bed where Plotinus lay, and slipped away through a hole in the wall; at the same moment the philosopher died. | |||
Some scholars argue that Plotinus had connections with the Roman emperor Gordian III in order for him to be part of the expedition, however, other scholars think that Plotinus merely had to show up at the reception camp in Syria, and from there might have followed the Imperial army on its expedition to the East.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} Gordian's expedition didn't reach very far east,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=11|loc=Life, works and philosophical background.}} as ] failed when Gordian III was killed in battle{{Sfn|Edwards|2000|p=xxxix|loc=Introduction}} in early 244 CE{{Sfn|Peachin|1990|pp=29-30|loc=Chronology}} (maybe assassinated by his own troops){{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=3|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=116|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} at a camp about 30km{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=202|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} south of ] in a region named Zaitha{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=31|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}}{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=127|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} (now the village al-Mar-wâniyya){{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=202|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} in ].{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=11|loc=Life, works and philosophical background.}} Following those events, Plotinus with great difficulty found his way back to safety in ] (today the Turkish coast close to the Syrian border),{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=11|loc=Life, works and philosophical background.}} and soon afterwards moved to Rome.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.15-3.23}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=11|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} | |||
Plotinus wrote the essays that became the '']'' (from Greek ἐννέα (''ennéa''), or group of nine) over a period of several years from c. 253 C.E. until a few months before his death seventeen years later. Porphyry makes note that the ''Enneads'', before being compiled and arranged by himself, were merely the enormous collection of notes and essays which Plotinus used in his lectures and debates, rather than a formal book. Plotinus was unable to revise his own work due to his poor eyesight, yet his writings required extensive editing, according to Porphyry: his master's handwriting was atrocious, he did not properly separate his words, and he cared little for niceties of spelling. Plotinus intensely disliked the editorial process, and turned the task to Porphyry, who not only polished them but put them into the arrangement we now have. | |||
There had been a passionate attraction to the East among Greeks, with the idea of it being a source of great wisdom, since the age of ], ], ], and ].{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=29|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} The Eastern philosophies were also a great source of interest to ], ], ] and his son, , ], ], and many others.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=29|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Hence it was not surprising that Plotinus was enthusiastic in his endeavours to travel to the East and learn about their philosophies.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=29|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
== Major ideas == | |||
At the age of 40, between 244{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}}–245 CE,{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Corrigan|2005|p=1|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=3|loc=Introduction}} Plotinus settled in Rome during the reign of emperor ], and stayed there until 269 CE,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}} when due to an illness,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.15-2.20}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=5|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|pp=|p=2}} and in what was to be the last months of his life, he moved to ], and there succumbed to his illness in 270 CE.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.15-3.35}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=5, 7}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=2|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} | |||
=== The One === | |||
The move to Rome by Plotinus is surprising because, compared to Alexandria and Athens of the times, there was no important philosophical trend in that city.{{Sfn|Kalligus|2014|pp=32-33|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Theories for Plotinus' move to Rome, related by the 21st century Professor Emeritus ], are that: (a) perhaps Plotinus' former teacher Ammonius had died in Alexandria in the meantime and Plotinus did not want to be the student of a different teacher; (b) Plotinus did not have a good relationship with the type of academicism in Athens, where at the time ]{{Sfn|Fleet|2012|p=2|loc=Introduction to the Series}} was the head of the ]; and (c) Plotinus had important acquaintances in Rome who could provide him with financial and political support, and introduce him to the Roman elite.{{Sfn|Kalligus|2014|pp=32-33|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
{{See also|Substance theory}} | |||
Plotinus taught that there is a supreme, totally transcendent "]", containing no division, multiplicity, or distinction; beyond all categories of ] and non-being. His "One" "cannot be any existing thing", nor is it merely the sum of all things (compare the ] doctrine of disbelief in non-material existence), but "is prior to all existents". Plotinus identified his "One" with the concept of 'Good' and the principle of 'Beauty'. (I.6.9) | |||
His "One" concept encompassed thinker and object. Even the self-contemplating intelligence (the ] of the ]) must contain ]. "Once you have uttered 'The Good,' add no further thought: by any addition, and in proportion to that addition, you introduce a deficiency." (III.8.11) Plotinus denies ], self-awareness or any other action (''ergon'') to the One (τὸ Ἕν, ''to hen''; V.6.6). Rather, if we insist on describing it further, we must call the One a sheer potentiality ('']'') without which nothing could exist. (III.8.10) As Plotinus explains in both places and elsewhere (e.g. V.6.3), it is impossible for the One to be Being or a self-aware Creator God. At (V.6.4), Plotinus compared the One to "light", the Divine Intellect/] (Νοῦς, ''Nous''; first will towards Good) to the "Sun", and lastly the Soul (Ψυχή, '']'') to the "Moon" whose light is merely a "derivative conglomeration of light from the 'Sun'". The first light could exist without any celestial body. | |||
==== Plotinus' school ==== | |||
In c. 245 CE, shortly after he had settled in Rome, Plotinus established the first neoplatonic school.{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=1|loc=Introduction}} His school was open to everybody, and attracted people who just wanted to hear his lectures or attend meetings or seminars or participate in open philosophical discussions, whilst others came to seek a philosophical way of life, and others attended because they wanted to become philosophers.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|pp=14-16|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} Plotinus did not impose a rigid curriculum at his school,{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=21|loc=Platonist Curricula and their Influence by Tarrant}} he himself did not write anything in his first 10 years in Rome, but rather based his seminars on Ammonius Saccas' teachings and encouraged students to ask questions and discuss subjects.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.33-3.38}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=11|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=3|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} Subjects of study at Plotinus' school included works by ] and ] and commentaries on Plato and Aristotle by the ], ] and ].{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|loc=Life, works and philosophical background|p=27}} In his biography of Plotinus, Porphyry does not say his listing of subjects studied at the school is exhaustive, and so there may have been other philosophical works that were read in Plotinus' school.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|loc=Life, works and philosophical background|p=27}} | |||
The One, being beyond all attributes including being and non-being, is the source of the world—but not through any act of creation, willful or otherwise, since activity cannot be ascribed to the unchangeable, immutable One. Plotinus argues instead that the multiple cannot exist without the simple. The "less perfect" must, of necessity, "emanate", or issue forth, from the "perfect" or "more perfect". Thus, all of "creation" emanates from the One in succeeding stages of lesser and lesser perfection. These stages are not temporally isolated, but occur throughout time as a constant process. | |||
==== Students ==== | |||
Plotinus' students included philosophers, students of philosophy, doctors, Roman senators, poets and orators. His innermost circle of students were:{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=9|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} | |||
The One is not just an intellectual concept but something that can be experienced, an experience where one goes beyond all multiplicity.<ref>Stace, W. T. (1960) ''The Teachings of the Mystics'', New York, Signet, pp. 110–123</ref> Plotinus writes, "We ought not even to say that he will ''see'', but he will ''be'' that which he sees, if indeed it is possible any longer to distinguish between seer and seen, and not boldly to affirm that the two are one."<ref>Stace, W. T. (1960) ''The Teachings of the Mystics'', New York, Signet, p. 122</ref> | |||
* ] of ] who joined Plotinus' school in 246–247 CE{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=12|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} and stayed for over 20{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=8|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} years until 268–269 CE.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.38-3.41, 7.1-7.5}} The industrious organization of Amelius contributed greatly to the success and longevity of Plotinus' school.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=36|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Amelius was Plotinus' most important student, as he organized the school, wrote works and commentaries that analyzed Plotinus' philosophy, and defended Plotinus against critics and opponents.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=41|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Amelius also thought highly of the philosopher ], whose works were read in Plotinus' circle,{{Sfn|Gerson|2010a|p=66|loc=Platonism before Plotinus by Tarrant}} and eventually went to live in a city substantively associated with Numenius,{{Sfn|Dillon|1996|p=361|loc=Numenius of Apamea}} the Syrian city of ], shortly before Plotinus died.{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=6|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} When Plotinus was accused of appropriating Numenius' ideas, it was Amelius who wrote a book in Plotinus' defense called ''On the Difference between the Doctrines of Plotinus and Numenius''.{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=6|loc=The Philosophy of Plotinus the Egyptian}} | |||
* ], a doctor who lived in Puteoli (modern day ], 40 miles outside Naples),{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=24|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} was a close friend of Plotinus, who came to the school near the end of Plotinus' life, devoted himself to learning from Plotinus, and attended him on his deathbed.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 1.13-1.14, 7.9}} After Plotinus' death, his uncorrected manuscripts belonged to Eustochius.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=130|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} Porphyry thought highly of Eustochius, who seems to have edited and published an edition of some{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=397|loc=Plotinus and Christian philosophy by Rist}}{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=88|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} of Plotinus' treatises, that were quoted by ] in ''Praeparatio Evangelica'',{{Sfn|Slaveva-Griffin|2009|p=134 (note 18)|loc=Unity of Thought and Writing}} but are now lost.{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}} Eustochius' edition of Plotinus' treatise was published before Porphyry edited and published the ''Enneads'' about 30 years after Plotinus died.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=365 (note 9)|loc=Neoplatonism and medicine by Wilberding}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=36 (note 8)|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} | |||
* ], a student and associate of Plotinus from 262–263 CE{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=13|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} until he left the school in 268 CE.{{Sfn|Gerson|2010a|p=303|loc=Plotinus by O'Meara}} He was Plotinus' most brilliant student,{{Sfn|Evangeliou|1996|p=xi|loc=Prologue}} a close friend, his biographer, and who Plotinus asked to edit his writings,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.50-7.52}} and eventually was the first{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}} editor of the ''],'' which was first published between 301–305 CE.{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989|p=ix|loc=Preface}} The neoplatonic philosopher Porphyry was amongst the first serious students of the ], and wrote on astrology,{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=445|loc=Freedom, providence and fate by Adamson}} religion, and philosophy, where he was a critic of ], ], ],{{Sfn|Berchman|2005|p=2|loc=Chapter 1: Author, Title, Date, Sources, Provenance}} and the school of his student, the neoplatonic philosopher ].{{Sfn|Magny|2014|p=8|loc=Introduction}} Porphyry also wrote on a important passage in ]'s '']'' in his work ''],'' and he wrote on Pythagorean musical theory.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=21|loc=Platonist Curricula and their Influence by Tarrant}} | |||
=== Emanation by the One === | |||
Superficially considered, Plotinus seems to offer an alternative to the orthodox ] notion of creation '']'' (out of nothing), although Plotinus never mentions Christianity in any of his works. The metaphysics of emanation (ἀπορροή ''aporrhoe'' (ΙΙ.3.2) or ἀπόρροια ''aporrhoia'' (II.3.11)), however, just like the metaphysics of Creation, confirms the absolute transcendence of the One or of the Divine, as the source of the Being of all things that yet remains transcendent of them in its own nature; the One is in no way affected or diminished by these emanations, just as the Christian God in no way is affected by some sort of exterior "nothingness". Plotinus, using a venerable analogy that would become crucial for the (largely neoplatonic) metaphysics of developed Christian thought, likens the One to the ] which emanates light indiscriminately without thereby diminishing itself, or reflection in a mirror which in no way diminishes or otherwise alters the object being reflected.<ref></ref> | |||
The belief of the equality of men and women prevailed in ancient neoplatonic and Pythagorean schools.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Among Plotinus' women students of philosophy{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=16|loc=Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Writings by Porphyry}} commented on by Porphyry in his biography of Plotinus, were: | |||
The first emanation is '']'' (Divine Mind, '']'', Order, Thought, Reason), identified metaphorically with the ] in Plato's '']''. It is the first ] toward Good. From ''Nous'' proceeds the ], which Plotinus subdivides into upper and lower, identifying the lower aspect of Soul with ]. From the world soul proceeds individual ] souls, and finally, matter, at the lowest level of ] and thus the least ] level of the cosmos. Plotinus asserted the ultimately divine nature of material creation since it ultimately derives from the One, through the mediums of ''Nous'' and the world soul. It is by the Good or through beauty that we recognize the One, in material things and then in the ]. (I.6.6 and I.6.9) | |||
* '''Amphiclea''', who was well versed in philosophy,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} and whose husband was Ariston, who may{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}}{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=272|loc=III.B.9.a. Gender, sex and love}} have been the son of the neoplatonic philosopher ].{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 9.5-9.6}} | |||
* '''Chione''', who lived in Gemina's house and may have employed the servants.{{Sfn|Edwards|2000|p=21 (footnote 117)|loc=On the Life of Plotinus}}{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=18|loc=Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Writings by Porphyry}} Porphyry mentions that Plotinus once helped in identifying the servant who had stolen a valuable necklace from her.{{Sfn|Edwards|2000|loc=On the Life of Plotinus|pp=21-22}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 11.1-11.7}} | |||
* '''Gemina''', who also was well versed in philosophy,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=15|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} and in whose spacious{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} house Plotinus lived while he was in Rome.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|p=374|loc=Nature: Physics, Medicine and Biology by Corrigan|2014}} Her house was also home to the children of dying{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} or deceased{{Sfn|Gerson|2010|p=xii|loc=Introduction}}{{Sfn|O'Meara|1995|p=5|loc=Introduction}} nobility{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=197|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} to whom Plotinus was an honorary guardian, one that supervised the actions of each guardian.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} One of his duties he undertook as an honorary guardian was to take meticulous care of the children's financial matters.{{Sfn|Katz|1950|p=ix|loc=Introduction}} He believed that until the children chose to become philosophers and renounce their wealth, their property and revenue should be kept intact and secure.{{Sfn|Bigg|1895|p=184|loc=Plotinus}} Gemina's house was also home to Chione and her children,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 9.1-9.2}} and is likely to have been the venue for Plotinus' school.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} There has been a suggestion by the 20th–21st century French Professor ], in a 1992 publication, that Gemina was the widow of the Roman emperor ], whose full name was Afinia M. F. Gemina Baebiana.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} If that suggestion is true, it would further indicate Plotinus' connection to the elite of Roman society.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
* '''Gemina''', Gemina's daughter, also called Gemina,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 9.2-9.4}} who was greatly devoted to philosophy.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=15|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} | |||
20th and 21st century scholars have debated, and are still debating whether the 'Sarcophagus of Plotinus',<ref>{{Cite web |date=12 October 2014 |title="Figures". The Enneads of Plotinus, Volume 1: A Commentary, Volume 1, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2014, pp. 679-680. |url=https://www.degruyter.com/document/doi/10.1515/9781400852512-011/pdf |url-status=live |access-date=21 July 2022 |website=De Gruyter |doi=10.1515/9781400852512-011}}</ref> dated c. 270 CE, depicts the younger Gemina and the elder Gemina at either side of a philosopher, where that philosopher maybe a depiction of Plotinus.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books, Appendix B: The Figural Representations of Plotinus|pp=94-95}} The sarcophagus also depicts another philosopher, that may be a depiction of Porphyry, looking over Plotinus' right shoulder.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books, Appendix B: The Figural Representations of Plotinus|pp=94-95}} The 'Sarcophagus of Plotinus' is located in the Gregorian Museum, one of the ].{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books, Appendix B: The Figural Representations of Plotinus|pp=94-95}} | |||
The essentially devotional nature of Plotinus' philosophy may be further illustrated by his concept of attaining ecstatic union with the One ('']''). Porphyry relates that Plotinus attained such a union four times during the years he knew him. This may be related to ], realisation, liberation, and other concepts of ] common to many Eastern and Western traditions.<ref>{{cite book|last=Lander|first=Janis|title=Spiritual Art and Art Education|year=2013|publisher=Routledge|page= 76|isbn=9781134667895}}</ref> | |||
===== Doctors ===== | |||
]). Plotinus sometimes stayed with Zethus, his doctor and close friend, at his estate near Minturnae.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.21-7.23}}]] | |||
Apart from Eustochius, Porphyry reports the following doctors were also students of Plotinus: | |||
* ], a doctor from ] (a city also known as Bethshan,{{Sfn|Bigg|1895|p=188|loc=Plotinus}} or ]{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=261|loc=III.B.8. Homeland and empire}} on the West bank of the ]), who died shortly before Plotinus.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: line 7.6}} 19th century scholarship conjectures that he was Rabbi Mar Samuel (c. 180–257 CE), whom the ] relates had meetings and conversations with a famous non-Jewish teacher called Paltia (Plotinus?).{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=43|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} Porphyry relates that Paulinus was not the brightest of students.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=365 (note 10)|loc=Neoplatonism and medicine by Wilberding}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.6-7.8}} | |||
* ], a doctor and close friend of Plotinus, Porphyry and Amelius; was an ] by ancestry and who married the daughter of Theodosius, a student of Ammonius Saccas.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.15-7.28}} Plotinus sometimes stayed with him at his estate six{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=23|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} miles north of ] (modern day Minturno), which Castricius Firmus eventually bought.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.21-7.23}} Zethus died before Plotinus.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: line 1.19}} | |||
===== Roman senators ===== | |||
Plotinus also had quite a few Roman senators who listened to his seminars, and some became his students, including: | |||
* ], an influential person with a significant fortune, who may{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=128|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} or may not{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=44|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} have been a Roman senator, and who supplied some of Plotinus' needs while he was gravely ill.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 1.21-1.23}} | |||
* ], who diligently applied himself to the study of philosophy.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.29-7.30}} He was probably from near the ], and may have been the Marcellus whom ] addressed in a preface to a book that replied to the philosophies of Plotinus and Amelius.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=196|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} | |||
* ''']''', who gave up all his possessions and the management of his house, dismissed his slaves, resigned his position, only ate every other day, which Porphyry says cured him from his debilitating gout, slept at various houses of his friends, and eventually became a member of Plotinus' inner circle of philosophers, and was praised publicly by Plotinus as a model to all others who wanted to become philosophers.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.30-7.45}} Before studying with Plotinus, Rogantianus may have been appointed praefect of the army on the Rhine in 241 CE and proconsul for Asia in 254 CE.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=196|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} | |||
* ''']''', who also diligently applied himself to the study of philosophy.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.30-7.31}} Sabinillus may have been made an ordinary ] together with emperor ] in 266 CE.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=196|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} The 21st century Professor Emeritus ] thinks it is possible that Sabinillus was buried in a sarcophagus now located in the ] that came from ], which is in the region of ].{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books|pp=45-46}} | |||
===== Others ===== | |||
Other listeners to Plotinus' seminars mentioned by Porphyry include: | |||
* '''Carterius''', who was persuaded by Amelius to attend a seminar and secretly draw or paint a portrait of Plotinus without his knowledge.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 1.12-1.20}} He was a famous painter according to Porphyry, of whom nothing else is known apart from Porphyry's brief anecdote.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=21|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
* ''']''', who at one time came to a seminar by Plotinus, however, after Plotinus saw Origen in the audience, Porphyry says Plotinus soon left <nowiki/>the seminar saying something along the lines 'that it was only natural for lecturers to cease talking when they were aware of the <nowiki/>presence, in the '''''<nowiki/>'''''a'''''<nowiki/>'''''udien'''''<nowiki/>'''''ce, of people who already knew what was to be said'.{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=21|loc=Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Writings by Porphyry}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 14.21-14.25}} | |||
* ] of Alexander, who started as an orator, then turned to the study of philosophy, but did not stay long at the school as he was too interested in financial matters and money-lending.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.46-7.47}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=9|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=}} Other than the information in Porphyry's ''Life of Plotinus'', nothing else is known about Serapion.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books|pp=|p=46}} | |||
* ], a critic and poet, who Porphyry says wrote a beautiful poem about Atlantis and also edited a work by ]. His eyesight failed and he died shortly before Plotinus.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 7.12-7.15}} | |||
Porphyry also reports that he had correspondences with the philosopher ], who was the head of the ] in Athens,{{Sfn|Fleet|2012|p=2|loc=Introduction to the Series}} discussing Plotinus' philosophy, and Longinus wrote back saying he was very impressed by Plotinus' writings and wanted Porphyry to send him more works of Plotinus exactly transcribed.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 19.1-19.40}} Plotinus however, was not very impressed by Longinus, as after he had heard a reading of Longinus' work ''On First Principles'',{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 14.15-14.21}} he remarked:<blockquote>"''Longinus is a literary man, but not a philosopher.''"—Plotinus{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=21|loc=Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Writings by Porphyry}}</blockquote> | |||
==== Elite Allies ==== | |||
], located in the ], Berlin. Plotinus was a close friend of Gallienus and his wife, the Roman empress ].{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=13|loc=Introduction}}]] | |||
While in Rome, Plotinus became a close friend of the mid 3rd century CE Roman emperor ] and his wife, the Roman empress ].{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=13|loc=Introduction}} Although Plotinus' writings show no indication of activity or interest in political affairs, Porphyry reports that he nearly swayed emperor Gallienus, perhaps between 267–268 CE,{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=207|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} to construct a city of philosophers in ], to be called Platonopolis, which was to be governed according to the doctrines in Plato's work '']''.{{Sfn|Armstrong|1962|p=14|loc=Introduction}} Most likely the planned city was to be in the Campanian provinces where Plotinus' friends already had estates, and realistically, Platonopolis was not only to be a city of philosophers, but a city that included all ranks of society.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=207-208}} Nothing came of the project, most likely due to the emperor's poor relationship with the Senate, despite some members of that body being supporters of Plotinus.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=55|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
Late 20th and 21st century scholarship suggest there may be a possibility that Gemina, at whose house Plotinus stayed the entire time he was in Rome and whose house is likely to have been the venue for Plotinus' school,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} was the widow of the Roman emperor ], whose full name was Afinia M. F. Gemina Baebiana, and who was the Roman emperor between 251–253 CE.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=48|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}}{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=|p=196}} Emperor Gallus was an almost immediate predecessor to emperor ], Roman emperor from 253–260 CE, and Valerian's son, ], the Roman co-emperor with Valerian from 253–260 CE, and sole Roman emperor from 260 CE until 268 CE.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=|p=197}} Hence, it is suggested by some 21st century scholarship that Gemina, having close connections with the emperors Valerian and Gallienus, introduced Plotinus to emperor Gallienus and his wife, the empress Iulia Cornelia Salonina, who may have belonged to a Greek{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=54|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} family from ].{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=|p=197}} The emperor Gallus and the empress Salonina who both, according to Porphyry,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 12.1-12.2}} honoured and revered Plotinus visited Plotinus' school and probably participated in his classes at least once.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=III.C.1. The chair of Plotinus?|pp=|p=297}} | |||
==== Status ==== | |||
Some 21st century scholarship argues that Plotinus was from a wealthy and cultivated family, likely high civil servants, who had strong connections with the Roman imperial court.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson|pp=126-127}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=12|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}}{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to Imperial Rome (references Professor Harder 1896-1957)|pp=|p=199}} These arguments are to some degree based on the observations by the mid-20th century German Professor ]{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to Imperial Rome|pp=|p=195}} on Plotinus' later wealthy life in Rome, which were elaborated in detail during the 1980s by the French Professor ].{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to Imperial Rome|pp=|p=195}} One such Indication of that wealth was that children of wealthy families were often handed over to a nursemaid from their birth,{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}} and this was the case with Plotinus, as reported by Porphyry in his biography.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=126|loc=Plotinus’ style and argument by Brisson}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 3.2-3.6}} Another indication of his family's wealth was that by the time he was eight years old, he was under the instruction of a grammarian,{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=7|loc=Life of Plotinus and Order of his Writings by Porphyry}} as rhetoric was part of the normal curriculum for the educated elite.{{Sfn|Clark|2016|p=17|loc=How to Read Plotinus}} It is also clear that Plotinus' early teaching was in Greek, and he also wrote in Greek, a language, which since the time of ], was taught from a young age to the highest and best-educated Roman class.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=33|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} | |||
Other indications of Plotinus' family's wealth and strong connections with the Roman elite, substantially related by the Danish Dr. Asger Ousager in a 2005 publication,{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=195-199}} are that in Rome: he belonged to the upper-class{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=12|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} of society that was close to senators;{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} he could afford masseurs;{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.5-2.10}} he spent summer vacations on wealthy estates in ],{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 5.1-5.5}} where the Roman upper class spent holidays;{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} his doctor Eustochius was summoned from Puteoli (modern day ]), a seaside resort for the ultimate élite,{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}} to his deathbed in the villa of the wealthy estate of the deceased Zethus;{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=195|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.17-2.25, 7.17-7.23}} his circle of students included wealthy and influential people including Roman senators;{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=195-196}} and upon arriving in Rome he was soon lodging in Gemina's estate, who must have been relatively wealthy whether or not she was a former empress.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=195-199}} Further, dying Roman nobles let their children be raised at Gemina's house,{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=197|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 9.5-9.9}} where Plotinus was their tutor and guardian,{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=197|loc=Coming to imperial Rome}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 9.9-9.16}} implying that he was a very creditable person within the highest circles of Rome.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=197|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=}} Dr. Ousager relates that such a wealthy and honoured status afforded to Plotinus in Rome would be unlikely if his family was not in possession of wealth and honour beforehand.{{Sfn|Ousager|2005|p=197|loc=Coming to imperial Rome|pp=}} | |||
==== Writing style ==== | |||
When Plotinus eventually wrote down his thoughts, beginning from 254 CE,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=13|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} he would make sure the problems concerned were thoroughly debated beforehand in the school, and would not only take into consideration the opinions of Plato, Aristotle and the Stoics, but also consider the opinions of recent commentators and his students, before formulating his own opinion.{{Sfn|O'Meara|1995|p=10|loc=Introduction: Plotinus' Life and Works}} On the manner in which Plotinus wrote, Porphyry says that Plotinus would work out a train of thought from beginning to end, and then would write continuously and without hesitation, as if 'copying from a book', without worrying about his spelling or the beauty of his individual letters, as he was only concerned with ideas, which gives another reason as to why Plotinus' language is not easy to read.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2008|loc=Introduction|pp=1-2}}{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 8.3-8.11}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=29|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=7|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} | |||
Despite the difficulty of his writing style, Plotinus is regarded by scholarship as having written some charming{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} and beautiful{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}}{{Sfn|Uždavinys|2009|p=viii|loc=Foreword by Bregman}}{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=349|loc=Plotinus and language by Schroeder}}{{Sfn|Whittaker|1918|p=39|loc=Plotinus and his Nearest Predecessors}} passages, and writes in a way that is agreeably personal and unaffected.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} From his writings it is evident that he deeply cared and thought deeply about the issues on which he was writing, and it is easy to believe that his thoughts are being recorded as they occurred in his mind, unembellished and unedited, which leads too the conclusion that Plotinus' mind must have been quite orderly.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} | |||
===== Enneads ===== | |||
Plotinus began writing philosophical treatises from 254 CE{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=13|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} for a period of about 17 years until shortly before his death in 270 CE.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=18|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} Porphyry, about 30 years after Plotinus died, edited and arranged Plotinus' treatises into 54 treatises, or six '']'' and gave them titles, which are still in use today, and wrote an introduction to the ''Enneads'' that was a biography of Plotinus' life called ''Life of Plotinus'' (''<span lang="la" dir="ltr">Vita Plotini</span>''{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=19|loc=Introduction}}).{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|loc=Life, works and philosophical background|pp=18-19}} To Porphyry, the number 54 was significant for Pythagorean{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=119|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} numerological reasons (3<sup>3</sup> × 2, or 6 × 3<sup>2</sup>) and he had to split certain treatises to arrive at that number.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=19|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} Plotinus had already written 21 treatises, beginning in 254 CE,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=13|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} before Porphyry arrived at his school in 263 CE,{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=13|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} and he wrote 24 treatises while Porphyry was at his school, and wrote nine more after Porphyry left his school in 268{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=14|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books}} CE.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=19|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} | |||
Porphyry had a very difficult task in editing and arranging Plotinus' treatises into the ''Enneads'', as Plotinus, due to his failing eyesight, disliked writing and did not correct his works, which at times were composed in a hurry and amid constant interruptions.{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=119|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} However, Porphyry reports that Plotinus was capable of recording the orderly conceptions in his mind through his writings even when interrupted, as after the interruption he would resume his train of thought.{{Sfn|Remes|2008|p=21|loc=Introduction}} To add to the difficulty of Porphyry's editorial work, Plotinus' writing style, although being usually very structured,{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} is also very concise and requires constant effort from a reader,{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|p=119|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus}} with introductory and bridging remarks used sparingly.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} | |||
Plotinus' writings in the ''Enneads'' approach questions, and arguments for specific claims, from different angles and sometimes venture into related topics.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} His powerful arguments are very concisely stated and are not spelled out with explicit premises, inferences and conclusions.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=17|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} One of the major reasons why the ''Enneads'' is difficult to read is because it was not intended for publication, but was intended for circulation in Plotinus' school, and hence presupposed familiarity with subjects discussed in the school, and another reason is that Plotinus never attempts to explain his philosophy in a systematic manner.{{Sfn|Emilsson|2008|loc=Introduction|pp=1-2}} | |||
===== Influences ===== | |||
Besides ], Plotinus, in his work ''Enneads'' (which contains everything he wrote),{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=18|loc=Life, works and philosophical background}} was influenced by the philosophical works of: ], ] and the ], ], ], ], ], ], ], ]; the ] of the 2nd century CE: Severus, ], ] and ] (a ] middle Platonist of the 2nd to 3rd century CE); and he was also influenced by the works of ].{{Sfn|Gerson|1999|p=|loc=Plotinus: The Platonic tradition and the foundation of Neoplatonism by Gatti translated by Gerson|pp=10, 13}} | |||
=== Later life === | |||
Due to his illness, Plotinus moved from Rome and spent his final days, between 269{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ix|loc=Chronology}} to 270 CE,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=1|loc=General Introduction to the Translations}}{{Sfn|Emilsson|2017|p=ii|loc=front matter}} in ] in the estate of Zethus, an Arabian doctor and an old friend and former student who had died.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.10-2.20, 7.1-7.3, 7.15-7.20, 7.25-7.29}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=5, 7, 27}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|pp=1-2, 6}} There his needs were supplied partly from Zethus' estate and partly from an estate at ], owned by Castricius Firmus, a friend of Plotinus' student ], and also Plotinus' student.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.10-2.20, 7.1-7.3, 7.15-7.20, 7.25-7.29}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=5, 7, 27}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|pp=1-2, 6}} According to the account of Eustochius, a doctor and Plotinus' student, (who was delayed in his journey from ] to the estate of Zethus), and was the only person to attend Plotinus on his deathbed, Plotinus' last words were:{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.25-2.32, 7.8-7.10}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=7, 25}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|p=2}} <blockquote>''"I have been waiting for you; I am trying to unite what is divine in us to that which is divine in the universe.''"—Plotinus (last words){{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=7|loc=Life of Plotinus and Order of his Writings by Porphyry}}</blockquote>Eustochius records that at the moment Plotinus died, a snake slid under the bed where Plotinus lay, and disappeared into a hole in the wall.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.27-2.29}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=7|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|pp=2, 6|p=}} It seems that this event was related to the Alexandrian doctor's belief, wide-spread at the time, of the snake-shaped Egyptian god Agathodaimon<ref>{{Cite web |title=Agathos Daimon |url=http://www.globalegyptianmuseum.org/glossary.aspx?id=42 |url-status=live |access-date=27 July 2022 |website=The Global Egyptian Museum}}</ref> or the newer Ptolemaic symbolism of the setting of a star; where both were signs to Eustochius of Plotinus' heroic destiny.{{Sfn|Kalligas|2014|p=|loc=Porphyry: On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books|pp=24-25}} On the day Plotinus died, ] was in ], Sicily; Amelius was in ], Syria; and Castricius was in ].{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.30-2.32}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=7|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|p=2}} Eustochius told Porphyry the details of Plotinus' last moments when they later met in Rome.{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|p=1}} | |||
=== Personal traits === | |||
Plotinus, like many future neoplatonists, had a distrust of the evidence of senses, a suspicion of the mortal body, believed the immortal soul had a direct knowledge of intelligible truths and that the sensible world was patterned on unchanging immaterial forms.{{Sfn|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014|p=522|loc=Neoplatonism and Christianity in the West by Moran}} Hence it was not surprising that he would not allow artists to perpetuate his physical body in a painting or a statue,{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines: 1.4-1.5}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=3|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=1|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} saying:<blockquote>"''Is it not enough for me to have to carry around this image, in which nature has enclosed us? Must I besides transmit to posterity the image of this image as worthy of attention?''"—Plotinus{{Sfn|Guthrie|1918a|p=5|loc=Life of Plotinus and Order of his Writings by Porphyry}}</blockquote>At one time however, his student ] succeeded in persuading his friend Carterius, a famous painter of the times, to attend one of Plotinus' lectures, commit Plotinus' features to memory, and subsequently draw or paint, with Amelius' suggestions towards bringing out resemblances, a lifelike portrait of Plotinus without his knowledge.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 1.10-1.18}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=3, 5|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=1|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} Due to his beliefs, Plotinus never spoke of his ancestry, his parentage or his birthplace, never took medicaments derived from animals, stayed away from the baths, but late in his life did for a time consent to being massaged daily, until such time as some of his masseurs died from a terrible epidemic, which soon afterwards afflicted him and probably contributed to a sickness that led to his death.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 1.3-2.10}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|p=|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=5, 7}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=1|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry}} Plotinus was a vegetarian, and although he did not celebrate his birthday, he did sacrifice and entertain his friends with a banquet on the birthdays of Socrates and Plato.{{Sfn|Gerson|2018|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books by Porphyry of Tyre: lines 2.3-2.6, 2.39-2.42}}{{Sfn|Armstrong|1989a|loc=Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books|pp=5, 7}}{{Sfn|MacKenna|1956|p=|loc=On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Work by Porphyry|pp=1-2}} | |||
Plotinus was a shy man, who showed signs of nervousness when he lectured, had austerely simple habits, was patient of interruption, and did not cut short objectors who came up with difficulties.{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus|pp=|p=120}} His modesty sometimes masked his own originality, and on the very rare occasions where he believed he experienced a beatific vision, he believed it to be a privilege, and that they were to be waited for, not sought.{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus|pp=|p=121}} Plotinus did not try to throw himself into an ecstatic state, and never claimed any mysteries were revealed to him while in a state of trance, and there is not the slightest trace of hysterical emotion in Plotinus' writings.{{Sfn|Inge|1948a|loc=Forerunners of Plotinus|pp=120-121}} | |||
== Doctrines == | |||
=== The true human and happiness === | === The true human and happiness === | ||
{{unreferenced section|date=April 2020}} | {{unreferenced section|date=April 2020}} | ||
Line 206: | Line 136: | ||
{{quote|There are no hard feelings if they tell us in which respects they intend to disagree with Plato Rather, whatever strikes them as their own distinct views in comparison with the Greeks’, these views – as well as the views that contradict them – should be forthrightly set out on their own in a considerate and philosophical manner.}} | {{quote|There are no hard feelings if they tell us in which respects they intend to disagree with Plato Rather, whatever strikes them as their own distinct views in comparison with the Greeks’, these views – as well as the views that contradict them – should be forthrightly set out on their own in a considerate and philosophical manner.}} | ||
The neoplatonic movement (though Plotinus would have simply referred to himself as a philosopher of Plato) seems to be motivated by the desire of Plotinus to revive the pagan philosophical tradition.{{refn|group=note|"... as Plotinus had endeavored to revive the religious spirit of paganism".<ref>''A Biographical History of Philosophy'', by George Henry Lewes Published 1892, G. Routledge & Sons, LTD, p. 294</ref>}} Plotinus was not claiming to innovate with the ''Enneads'', but to clarify aspects of the works of Plato that he considered misrepresented or misunderstood.<ref name=" |
The neoplatonic movement (though Plotinus would have simply referred to himself as a philosopher of Plato) seems to be motivated by the desire of Plotinus to revive the pagan philosophical tradition.{{refn|group=note|"... as Plotinus had endeavored to revive the religious spirit of paganism".<ref>''A Biographical History of Philosophy'', by George Henry Lewes Published 1892, G. Routledge & Sons, LTD, p. 294</ref>}} Plotinus was not claiming to innovate with the ''Enneads'', but to clarify aspects of the works of Plato that he considered misrepresented or misunderstood.<ref name="Stanford1" /> Plotinus does not claim to be an innovator, but rather a communicator of a tradition.<ref> in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy</ref> Plotinus referred to tradition as a way to interpret Plato's intentions. Because the teachings of Plato were for members of the academy rather than the general public, it was easy for outsiders to misunderstand Plato's meaning. However, Plotinus attempted to clarify how the philosophers of the academy had not arrived at the same conclusions (such as ] or ] of the creator God as an answer to the ]) as the targets of his criticism. | ||
=== Against causal astrology === | === Against causal astrology === | ||
Line 270: | Line 200: | ||
|viaf= |lccn= |lcheading= |wikititle= }} | |viaf= |lccn= |lcheading= |wikititle= }} | ||
== |
== Bibliography == | ||
=== References === | |||
'''<small>Antiquities</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Hermansen |first=Gustav |title=Ostia Aspects of Roman City Life |publisher=The University of Alberta Press |year=1982 |isbn=0888640668 |location=Edmonton, Alberta, Canada |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Hermansen|1982}}}}</small> | |||
'''<small>History</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Peachin |first=Michael |title=Roman Imperial Titulature and Chronology, A.D. 235 - 284 |publisher=J.C. Gieben |year=1990 |isbn=9050630340 |location=Amsterdam |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Peachin|1990}}|series=Studia Amstelodamensia Ad Epigraphicam Tus Antiquum Et Papyrologicam Pertinentia. Vol. XXIX|id=ark:/13960/t9d62br8p}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Cambridge History of Philosophy in Late Antiquity |publisher=Cambridge University Press |others=L.Ayres; H. Baltussen; A. Bernard; G. Betegh; D. Blank; D. Bradshaw; J. Bregman; S. Cooper; C. D’Ancona; E. D. Digeser; J. Dillon; M. Edwards; J. Feke; J. F. Finamore; R. Fowler; S. Gersh; L. P. Gerson; R. J. Hankinson; K. Ierodiakonou; B. Inwood; S. I. Johnston; A. Jones; I. Kupreeva; C. L´evy; A. Longo; J. Magee; J. A. McGuckin; D. Minns; E. Moore; B. Motta; D. O’Meara; J. Opsomer; E. Perl; E. Prinzivalli; A. Radde-Gallwitz; G. Reydams-Schils; G. Van Riel; H. Schibli; R. W. Sharples; A. Smith; C. Steel; H. Tarrant; J. D. Turner; K. Verrycken; D. Winston; G. Zografidis |year=2010a |isbn=9780521764407 |editor-last=Gerson |editor-first=Lloyd P. |location=Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo, Mexico City |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2010a}} |volume=1}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Sorabji |first=Richard |title=The Philosophy of the Commentators, 200-600 AD |publisher=Cornell University Press |year=2005 |isbn=0801489873 |volume=1: Psychology (with Ethics and Religion) |location=Ithaca, New York |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Sorabji|2005}}}}</small> | |||
'''<small>Middle Platonism</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Dillon |first=John |title=The Middle Platonists |publisher=Cornell Universitv Press |year=1996 |isbn=0801483166 |location=London and New York |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Dillon|1996}}|edition=Revised|orig-date=1977}}</small> | |||
<small>'''Neoplatonism'''</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Nikulin |first=Dmitri |title=Neoplatonism in Late Antiquity |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2019 |isbn=9780190662363 |location=United States of America |language=en,de,grc |ref={{sfnref|Nikulin|2019}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism |publisher=Routledge |others=H. Tarrant, R. Sorabji, G. Reydams-Schils, F. Ferrari, J. D. Turner, V. Adluri, H. Baltussen, A. Smith, L. Brisson, M. Martijn, S. Ahbel-Rappe, J. Halfwassen, C. O’Brien, T. Arnold, T. Ratzsch, S. Slaveva-Griffin, R. Chiaradonna, J-M. Narbonne, R. M. Berg, L. P. Gerson, J. F. Finamore, F. M. Schroeder, G. Aubry, P. Lautner, A. Linguiti, J. Wilberding, K. Corrigan, S. Stern-Gillet, B. Collette-Dučić, P. Adamson, P. Remes, D. J. O’Meara, P. Vassilopoulou, D. Moran, D. Y. Dimitrov, S. Pessin |year=2014 |isbn=9781315744186 |editor-last=Remes |editor-first=Pauliina |location=Oxford; New York |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Remes|Slaveva-Griffin|2014}} |editor-last2=Slaveva-Griffin |editor-first2=Svetla}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Remes |first=Pauliina |title=Neoplatonism |publisher=Acumen Publishing Limited |year=2008 |isbn=9781844651252 |location=Stocksfield, United Kingdom |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Remes|2008}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Smith |first=Andrew |title=Philosophy in Late Antiquity |publisher=Routledge |year=2004 |isbn=0415225108 |location=London and New York |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Smith|2004}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last= |first= |title=Neoplatonism and Indian Thought |publisher=State University of New York Press |year=1982 |isbn=9780585068411 |location=United States of America |language=en,grc,hi |ref={{sfnref|Harris|1982}}|others=J. R. A. Mayer; J. J. O'Meara; L. J. Hatab; L. J. Rosan; A. H. Armstrong and R. R. Ravindra; I. C. Sharma; R. T. Wallis; D. F. T. Rodier; J. Borelli; P. Hacker; F. G. Bazán; R. Hatton; M. N. Nabi; R. K. Tripathi; R. Sinari.|editor-last=Harris|editor-first=R. Baine|series=Thought Studies in Neoplatonism. Vol. 2}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Whittaker |first=Thomas |title=The Neo-Platonists |publisher=The University Press |year=1918 |isbn= |location=Cambridge |language=en,grc,la |id=ark:/13960/t8bg3pj9v |ref={{sfnref|Whittaker|1918}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Biqg |first=C. |title=Neoplatonism |publisher=Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge; E. & J. B. Young & Co. |year=1895 |isbn= |location=London; New York |language=en |id=ark:/13960/t13n20g6g |ref={{sfnref|Bigg|1895}}}}</small> | |||
<small>'''Origen'''</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Westminster Handbook to Origen |publisher=Westminster John Knox Press |others=S. E. Antonova; P. M. Blowers, P. Bright, B. E. Daley S.J., E. M. Harding, R. E. Heine, H. Hunt, C. Kannengiesser, J. Konstantinovsky, L. Larsen, E. D. Lauro, F. Ledegang, J. Leemans, J. W. McCree, J. A. McGuckin, N. McLynn, C. Markschies, P. Martens, F. W. Norris, R. Norris, J. J. O'Keefe, J. S. O'Leary, A. G. Paddle, K. Parry, J. Pettis, R. Roukema, D. T. Runia, W. G. Rusch, J. M. Scarborough, T. P. Scheck, M. Sheridan D.S.B., S. C. Thomas, F. Thompson, F. W. Weidmann, V. L. Wimbush |year=2004 |isbn=0664224725 |editor-last=McGuckin |editor-first=John Anthony |series=The Westminster Handbooks to Christian Theology |location=London |language=en |ref={{sfnref|McGuckin|2004}}}}</small> | |||
*<small>{{Cite book |last=Trigg |first=Joseph W. |title=Origen |publisher=Routledge |year=2002 |isbn=0203011996 |location=London; New York, USA, Canada |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Trigg|2002}}}}</small> | |||
'''<small>Plato</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Platonism and Christian Thought in Late Antiquity |publisher=Routledge |others=S. Morlet; C. Hoenig; C. Hecht; E. Moro; E. K. Emilsson; T. T. Tollefsen; L. F. Janby; D. J. Tolan; P. G. Pavlos; D. A. Vasilakis; S. Mateiescu; J. D. Wood; E. B. Dewhurst; A. Pirtea; T. Ekenberg |year=2019 |isbn=9781138340954 |editor-last=Pavlos |editor-first=Panagiotis G. |series=Studies in Philosophy and Theology in Late Antiquity |location=London; New York |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Pavlos|Janby|Emilsson|Tollefsen|2019}} |editor-last2=Janby |editor-first2=Lars Fredrik |editor-last3=Emilsson |editor-first3=Eyjólfur Kjalar |editor-last4=Tollefsen |editor-first4=Torstein Theodor}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Brill's Companion to the Reception of Plato in Antiquity |publisher=Brill |others=C. Addey; S. Ahbel-Rappe; F. Alesse; P. Athanassiadi; D. Baltzly; M. Bonazzi; M. Chase; D. Clark; J. Finamore; R. C. Fowler; G. Gabor; L. Gerson; M. Griffin; C. Hoenig; P. Sidney Horky; D. A. Layne; C. S. O’Brien; D. J. O’Meara; J. Opsomer; F. M. Petrucci; I. Ramelli; J. Rocca; G. Roskam; F. Renaud; C. E. Snyder; H. Tarrant; J. D. Turner; G. Van Riel; S. K. Wear; S. Yli-Karjanmaa |year=2018a |isbn=9789004270695 |editor-last=Gerson |editor-first=Lloyd P. |location=Leiden and Boston |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2018a}}|series=Brill's Companions to Classical Reception. Vol. 13|issn=22131426|doi=10.1163/9789004355385_018}}</small> | |||
<small>'''Plotinus'''</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Gerson |first=Lloyd P. |title=Plotinus Reader |publisher=Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. |year=2020 |isbn=9781624668951 |location=Indianapolis; Cambridge |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2020}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Emilsson |first=Eyjólfur K. |title=Plotinus |publisher=Routledge |year=2017 |isbn=9780203413159 |location=Oxford; New York |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Emilsson|2017}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Clark |first=Stephen R. L. |title=Plotinus: Myth, Metaphor, and Philosophical Practice |publisher=The University Of Chicago Press |year=2016 |isbn=9780226339672 |location=Chicago |language=en, grc |ref={{sfnref|Clark|2016}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Gerson |first=Lloyd P. |title=Plotinus |publisher=Routledge; Taylor and Francis e-Library |year=2010 |isbn=0415056624 |editor-last=Honderich |editor-first=Ted |series=The Arguments of the Philosophers |location=London; USA; Canada |language=en,grc |doi=10.4324/9780203011478 |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2010}} |orig-date=1994}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Slaveva-Griffin |first=Svetla |title=Plotinus on Number |publisher=Oxford University Press, Inc. |year=2009 |isbn=9780195377194 |location=Oxford; New York |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Slaveva-Griffin|2009}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Heart of Plotinus: The Essential Enneads including Porphyry's On the Cave of the Nymphs |publisher=World Wisdom, INC. |others=Foreword by J. Bregman |year=2009 |isbn=9781933316697 |editor-last=Uždavinys |editor-first=Algis |location=Bloomington, Indiana |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Uždavinys|2009}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Emilsson |first=Eyjolfur Kjalar |title=Plotinus on Sense-Perception: A Philosophical Study |publisher=Cambridge University Press; Cambridge University Press, New York |year=2008 |isbn=9780521329880 |location=Cambridge; New York; New Rochelle; Melbourne; Sydney |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Emilsson|2008}}|orig-date=1998}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Corrigan |first=Kevin |title=Reading Plotinus: A Practical Introduction to Neoplatonism |publisher=Purdue University Press |year=2005 |isbn=1557532338 |location=United States of America |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Corrigan|2005}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Ousager |first=Asger |title=Plotinus on Selfhood, Freedom and Politics |publisher=Aarhus University Press |year=2005 |isbn=8779349137 |location=Denmark |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Ousager|2005}}|series=Acta Jutlandica LXXIX:1, Humanities Series 76}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus |publisher=Cambridge University Press |others=H. J . Blumenthal; J. Bussanich; S. R . L . Clark; K. Corrigan; C. D 'Ancona Costa; J. M. Dillon; E. K. Emilsson; M. L. Gatti; L. P. Gerson; G. Leroux; D. O'Brien; D. J . O'Meara; S. Rappe; J. Rist; F. M. Schroeder; A. Smith; M. F. Wagner |year=1999 |isbn=9780521470933 |editor-last=Gerson |editor-first=Lloyd P. |location=Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|1999}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=O'Meara |first=Dominic J |title=Plotinus: An Introduction to the Enneads |publisher=Clarendon Press |year=1995 |isbn=0198751478 |location=Oxford |language=en |ref={{sfnref|O'Meara|1995}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Rist |first=John M |title=Plotinus: The Road to Reality |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=1967 |isbn=0521060850 |location=Cambridge; London; New York; Melbourne |language=en,grc |ref={{sfnref|Rist|1967}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Armstrong |first=A. H. |title=Plotinus |publisher=Collier Books |year=1962 |series=Ethical and religious classics of East and West, no. 10. |location=London; New York; Toronto |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Armstrong|1962}} |orig-date=1953 |oclc=2066394 |id=OCoLC 654133692}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Inge |first=William Ralph |title=The Philosophy of Plotinus. The Gifford Lectures at St. Andrews 1917-1918 |publisher=Longmans, Green and Co. |year=1948a |volume=1 |location=London; New York; Toronto |language=en, grc |ref={{sfnref|Inge|1948a}} |id=ark:/13960/t1qg41d4n}}</small> | |||
'''<small>Porphyry</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Magny |first=Ariane |title=Porphyry in Fragments |publisher=Routledge |year=2014 |isbn=9781409441151 |location=Oxford; New York |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Magny|2014}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Berchman |first=Robert M. |title=Porphyry Against the Christians |publisher=Brill |year=2005 |isbn=9004148116 |location=Leiden; Boston |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Berchman|2005}}}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Evangeliou |first=Christos |title=Aristotle's Categories and Porphyry |publisher=E.J. Brill, Leiden, The Netherlands |year=1996 |isbn=9004085386 |location=Leiden; New York; Koln |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Evangeliou|1996}} |edition=2nd |orig-date=1988 |series=Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy, Volume XLVIII |editor-last=Verdenius |editor-first=W. J. |editor-last2=Van Winden |editor-first2=J. C. M.}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Smith |first=Andrew |title=Porphyry's Place in the Neoplatonic Tradition |publisher=Martinus Nijhoff |year=1974 |isbn=9789024716531 |location=The Hague, Netherlands |language=en,grc,la |ref={{sfnref|Smith|1974}}}}</small> | |||
<small>'''Science and Medicine'''</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Oxford Handbook of Science and Medicine in the Classical World |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2018 |isbn=9780199984657 |editor-last=Keyser |editor-first=Paul T. |location=New York, NY |language=en |ref={{sfnref|Keyser|Scarborough|2018}} |editor-last2=Scarborough|editor-first2=John|doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199734146.013.78}}</small> | |||
=== Translations === | |||
'''<small>Hermetica</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Hermetica |publisher=The Press Syndicate of the University of Cambridge; Cambridge University Press |year=2002 |isbn=0521361443 |location=United Kingdom; United States of America; Australia; Spain; South Africa |language=en,grc |translator-last=Copenhaver |translator-first=Brian P. |ref={{sfnref|Copenhaver|2002}}}}</small> | |||
<small>'''Neoplatonism'''</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last= |first= |title=Neoplatonic Saints, The Lives of Plotinus and Proclus by their Students |publisher=Liverpool University Press; Bell and Bain Limited |year=2000 |isbn=0853236151 |series=Translated Texts for Historians |volume=35 |location=Liverpool; European Union |language=en |translator-last=Edwards |translator-first=Mark |ref={{sfnref|Edwards|2000}}}}</small> | |||
'''<small>Plotinus</small>''' | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus The Enneads |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2018 |isbn=9781107001770 |editor-last=Gerson |editor-first=Lloyd P. |location=United Kingdom; USA; Australia; India; Singapore |language=en,grc |translator-last=Boys-Stones |translator-first=George |ref={{sfnref|Gerson|2018}} |translator-last2=Dillon |translator-first2=John M. |translator-last3=Gerson |translator-first3=Lloyd P. |translator-last4=King |translator-first4=R.A.H. |translator-last5=Smith |translator-first5=Andrew |translator-last6=Wilberding |translator-first6=James}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus Ennead V.1: On the Three Primary Levels of Reality |publisher=Parmenides Publishing |year=2015 |location=Las Vegas; Zurich; Athens |language=en,grc,la |translator-last=Perl |translator-first=Eric D. |ref={{sfnref|Perl|2015}}|isbn=9781930972919|series=The Enneads of Plotinus with Philosophical Commentaries|editor-first=John M.|editor-last=Dillon|editor-last2=Smith|editor-first2=Andrew}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |last=Kalligas |first=Paul |title=The Enneads of Plotinus: A Commentary |publisher=Princeton University Press |year=2014 |volume=1 |location=Princeton; Oxford; New Jersey |language=en,grc,la |translator-last=Fowden |translator-first=Elizabeth Key |ref={{sfnref|Kalligas|2014}} |isbn=9780691154213 |orig-date=1991 |translator-last2=Pilavachi |translator-first2=Nicolas}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus Ennead IV.8: On the Descent of the Soul into Bodies |publisher=Parmenides Publishing |year=2012 |location=Las Vegas; Zurich; Athens |language=en,grc,la |translator-last=Fleet |translator-first=Barrie |ref={{sfnref|Fleet|2012}}|isbn=9781930972773|series=The Enneads of Plotinus with Philosophical Commentaries|editor-first=John M.|editor-last=Dillon|editor-last2=Smith|editor-first2=Andrew}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus: Porphyry on the Life of Plotinus and the Order of his Books, Enneads I.1-9 |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=1989 |volume=1 |location=Cambridge, Massachusetts |language=en,grc |translator-last=Armstrong |translator-first=A. H. |ref={{sfnref|Armstrong|1989a}}|isbn=0674994841|edition=Revised|orig-date=1966}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus The Enneads |publisher=Faber and Faber Limited |others=Foreword by Professor E. R. Dodds, Introduction by Professor Paul Henry, S J. |year=1956 |edition=Second Edition revised by B. S. Page |location=London |language=en,grc |translator-last=MacKenna |translator-first=Stephen |id=ark:/13960/t5gb7640w |ref={{sfnref|MacKenna|1956}} |orig-date=1917-1930}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinus: The Six Enneads |publisher=William Benton; Encyclopedia Britannica; The University of Chicago |year=1952 |location=Chicago ; London; Toronto; Geneva |language=en |translator-last=MacKenna |translator-first=Stephen |id=ark:/13960/t9v17h27h |ref={{sfnref|MacKenna|Page|1952}} |series=Great Books of the Western World, Vol. 17 |translator-last2=Page |translator-first2=B. S.}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=The Philosophy of Plotinus |publisher=Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc. |year=1950 |location=United States of America |language=en |translator-last=Katz |translator-first=Joseph |id=ark:/13960/t2d796119 |ref={{sfnref|Katz|1950}}|oclc=311781}}</small> | |||
* <small>{{Cite book |title=Plotinos Complete Works |publisher=Comparative Literature Press |year=1918a |volume=1 |location=United States of America |language=en,grc |translator-last=Guthrie |translator-first=Kenneth Sylvan |id=ark:/13960/t4xg9fh13 |ref={{sfnref|Guthrie|1918a}}}}</small> | |||
== Bibliography of publications == | |||
;Critical editions of the Greek text | ;Critical editions of the Greek text | ||
* ], ''Plotin: Ennéades'' (with French translation), ], 1924–1938. | * ], ''Plotin: Ennéades'' (with French translation), ], 1924–1938. |
Revision as of 15:15, 29 July 2022
Certain historical revisions of this page may meet criterion RD1 for revision deletion, as they contain significant copyright violations of https://www.talentshare.org/~mm9n/articles/cosmos/5.htm and of https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/ that have been removed in the meantime.
Note to admins: In case of doubt, remove this template and post a message asking for review at WT:CP. With this script, go to the history with auto-selected revisions. Note to the requestor: Make sure the page has already been reverted to a non-infringing revision or that infringing text has been removed or replaced before submitting this request. This template is reserved for obvious cases only, for other cases refer to Misplaced Pages:Copyright problems. Note to others: Please do not remove this template until an administrator has reviewed it. |
Plotinus | |
---|---|
Head in white marble. The identification as Plotinus is plausible but not proven. | |
Born | c. 204/5 Asyut or Lycopolis, Egypt, Roman Empire |
Died | 270 (aged 64–65) Campania, Roman Empire |
Notable work | The Enneads |
Era | Ancient philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | Neoplatonism |
Main interests | Platonism, metaphysics, mysticism |
Notable ideas | Emanation of all things from the One Three main hypostases: the One, Intellect, and Soul Henosis |
Part of a series on |
Neoplatonism |
---|
Reconstructed bust believed to represent Plotinus |
Concepts |
Works |
People
|
Related topics |
Philosophy portal |
Plotinus (/plɒˈtaɪnəs/; Template:Lang-grc-gre, Plōtînos; c. 204/5 – 270 CE) was a philosopher in the Hellenistic tradition, born and raised in Roman Egypt. Plotinus is regarded by modern scholarship as the founder of Neoplatonism. His teacher was the self-taught philosopher Ammonius Saccas, who belonged to the Platonic tradition. Historians of the 19th century invented the term "neoplatonism" and applied it to refer to Plotinus and his philosophy, which was vastly influential during Late Antiquity, the Middle Ages, and the Renaissance. Much of the biographical information about Plotinus comes from Porphyry's preface to his edition of Plotinus' most notable literary work, The Enneads. In his metaphysical writings, Plotinus described three fundamental principles: the One, the Intellect, and the Soul. His works have inspired centuries of Pagan, Jewish, Christian, Gnostic, and Islamic metaphysicians and mystics, including developing precepts that influence mainstream theological concepts within religions, such as his work on duality of the One in two metaphysical states.
Biography
Porphyry reported that Plotinus was 66 years old when he died in 270, the second year of the reign of the Roman emperor Claudius II, thus giving us the year of his teacher's birth as around 205. Eunapius reported that Plotinus was born in Lyco, which could either refer to the modern Asyut in Upper Egypt or Deltaic Lycopolis, in Lower Egypt. This has led to speculations that he may have been either native Egyptian, Hellenized Egyptian, Greek, or Roman. Historian Lloyd P. Gerson states that Plotinus was "almost certainly" a Greek.
Plotinus had an inherent distrust of materiality (an attitude common to Platonism), holding to the view that phenomena were a poor image or mimicry (mimesis) of something "higher and intelligible" (VI.I) which was the "truer part of genuine Being". This distrust extended to the body, including his own; it is reported by Porphyry that at one point he refused to have his portrait painted, presumably for much the same reasons of dislike. Likewise, Plotinus never discussed his ancestry, childhood, or his place or date of birth. From all accounts his personal and social life exhibited the highest moral and spiritual standards.
Plotinus took up the study of philosophy at the age of twenty-eight, around the year 232, and travelled to Alexandria to study. There he was dissatisfied with every teacher he encountered, until an acquaintance suggested he listen to the ideas of the self-taught Platonist philosopher Ammonius Saccas. Upon hearing Ammonius' lecture, Plotinus declared to his friend: "this is the man I was looking for", began to study intently under his new instructor, and remained with him as his student for eleven years. Besides Ammonius, Plotinus was also influenced by the philosophical works of Aristotle, the pre-Socratic philosophers Empedocles and Heraclitus, the Middle Platonist philosophers Alexander of Aphrodisias and Numenius of Apamea, along with various Stoics and neopythagoreans.
Expedition to Persia and return to Rome
After having spent eleven years in Alexandria, he then decided, at the age of around 38, to investigate the philosophical teachings of the Persian and Indian philosophers. In the pursuit of this endeavor he left Alexandria and joined the army of the Roman emperor Gordian III as it marched on Persia (242-243 C.E.). However, the campaign was a failure, and on Gordian's eventual death Plotinus found himself abandoned in a hostile land, and only with difficulty found his way back to safety in Antioch.
At the age of forty, during the reign of Emperor Philip the Arab, he came to Rome, where he stayed for most of the remainder of his life. There he attracted a number of students. His innermost circle included Porphyry, Amelius Gentilianus of Tuscany, the Senator Castricius Firmus, and Eustochius of Alexandria, a doctor who devoted himself to learning from Plotinus and attending to him until his death. Other students included: Zethos, an Arab by ancestry who died before Plotinus, leaving him a legacy and some land; Zoticus, a critic and poet; Paulinus, a doctor of Scythopolis; and Serapion from Alexandria. He had students amongst the Roman Senate beside Castricius, such as Marcellus Orontius, Sabinillus, and Rogantianus. Women were also numbered amongst his students, including Gemina, in whose house he lived during his residence in Rome, and her daughter, also Gemina; and Amphiclea, the wife of Ariston the son of Iamblichus. Finally, Plotinus was a correspondent of the philosopher Cassius Longinus.
Later life
While in Rome Plotinus also gained the respect of the Emperor Gallienus and his wife Salonina. At one point Plotinus attempted to interest Gallienus in rebuilding an abandoned settlement in Campania, known as the 'City of Philosophers', where the inhabitants would live under the constitution set out in Plato's Laws. An Imperial subsidy was never granted, for reasons unknown to Porphyry, who reports the incident.
Plotinus subsequently went to live in Sicily. He spent his final days in seclusion on an estate in Campania which his friend Zethos had bequeathed him. According to the account of Eustochius, who attended him at the end, Plotinus' final words were: "Try to raise the divine in yourselves to the divine in the all." Eustochius records that a snake crept under the bed where Plotinus lay, and slipped away through a hole in the wall; at the same moment the philosopher died.
Plotinus wrote the essays that became the Enneads (from Greek ἐννέα (ennéa), or group of nine) over a period of several years from c. 253 C.E. until a few months before his death seventeen years later. Porphyry makes note that the Enneads, before being compiled and arranged by himself, were merely the enormous collection of notes and essays which Plotinus used in his lectures and debates, rather than a formal book. Plotinus was unable to revise his own work due to his poor eyesight, yet his writings required extensive editing, according to Porphyry: his master's handwriting was atrocious, he did not properly separate his words, and he cared little for niceties of spelling. Plotinus intensely disliked the editorial process, and turned the task to Porphyry, who not only polished them but put them into the arrangement we now have.
Major ideas
The One
See also: Substance theoryPlotinus taught that there is a supreme, totally transcendent "One", containing no division, multiplicity, or distinction; beyond all categories of being and non-being. His "One" "cannot be any existing thing", nor is it merely the sum of all things (compare the Stoic doctrine of disbelief in non-material existence), but "is prior to all existents". Plotinus identified his "One" with the concept of 'Good' and the principle of 'Beauty'. (I.6.9)
His "One" concept encompassed thinker and object. Even the self-contemplating intelligence (the noesis of the nous) must contain duality. "Once you have uttered 'The Good,' add no further thought: by any addition, and in proportion to that addition, you introduce a deficiency." (III.8.11) Plotinus denies sentience, self-awareness or any other action (ergon) to the One (τὸ Ἕν, to hen; V.6.6). Rather, if we insist on describing it further, we must call the One a sheer potentiality (dynamis) without which nothing could exist. (III.8.10) As Plotinus explains in both places and elsewhere (e.g. V.6.3), it is impossible for the One to be Being or a self-aware Creator God. At (V.6.4), Plotinus compared the One to "light", the Divine Intellect/Nous (Νοῦς, Nous; first will towards Good) to the "Sun", and lastly the Soul (Ψυχή, Psyche) to the "Moon" whose light is merely a "derivative conglomeration of light from the 'Sun'". The first light could exist without any celestial body.
The One, being beyond all attributes including being and non-being, is the source of the world—but not through any act of creation, willful or otherwise, since activity cannot be ascribed to the unchangeable, immutable One. Plotinus argues instead that the multiple cannot exist without the simple. The "less perfect" must, of necessity, "emanate", or issue forth, from the "perfect" or "more perfect". Thus, all of "creation" emanates from the One in succeeding stages of lesser and lesser perfection. These stages are not temporally isolated, but occur throughout time as a constant process.
The One is not just an intellectual concept but something that can be experienced, an experience where one goes beyond all multiplicity. Plotinus writes, "We ought not even to say that he will see, but he will be that which he sees, if indeed it is possible any longer to distinguish between seer and seen, and not boldly to affirm that the two are one."
Emanation by the One
Superficially considered, Plotinus seems to offer an alternative to the orthodox Christian notion of creation ex nihilo (out of nothing), although Plotinus never mentions Christianity in any of his works. The metaphysics of emanation (ἀπορροή aporrhoe (ΙΙ.3.2) or ἀπόρροια aporrhoia (II.3.11)), however, just like the metaphysics of Creation, confirms the absolute transcendence of the One or of the Divine, as the source of the Being of all things that yet remains transcendent of them in its own nature; the One is in no way affected or diminished by these emanations, just as the Christian God in no way is affected by some sort of exterior "nothingness". Plotinus, using a venerable analogy that would become crucial for the (largely neoplatonic) metaphysics of developed Christian thought, likens the One to the Sun which emanates light indiscriminately without thereby diminishing itself, or reflection in a mirror which in no way diminishes or otherwise alters the object being reflected.
The first emanation is Nous (Divine Mind, Logos, Order, Thought, Reason), identified metaphorically with the Demiurge in Plato's Timaeus. It is the first Will toward Good. From Nous proceeds the World Soul, which Plotinus subdivides into upper and lower, identifying the lower aspect of Soul with nature. From the world soul proceeds individual human souls, and finally, matter, at the lowest level of being and thus the least perfected level of the cosmos. Plotinus asserted the ultimately divine nature of material creation since it ultimately derives from the One, through the mediums of Nous and the world soul. It is by the Good or through beauty that we recognize the One, in material things and then in the Forms. (I.6.6 and I.6.9)
The essentially devotional nature of Plotinus' philosophy may be further illustrated by his concept of attaining ecstatic union with the One (henosis). Porphyry relates that Plotinus attained such a union four times during the years he knew him. This may be related to enlightenment, realisation, liberation, and other concepts of mystical union common to many Eastern and Western traditions.
The true human and happiness
This section does not cite any sources. Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
The philosophy of Plotinus: representative books from the Enneads, p. viiThe philosophy of Plotinus has always exerted a peculiar fascination upon those whose discontent with things as they are has led them to seek the realities behind what they took to be merely the appearances of the sense.
Authentic human happiness for Plotinus consists of the true human identifying with that which is the best in the universe. Because happiness is beyond anything physical, Plotinus stresses the point that worldly fortune does not control true human happiness, and thus “… there exists no single human being that does not either potentially or effectively possess this thing we hold to constitute happiness.” (Enneads I.4.4) The issue of happiness is one of Plotinus’ greatest imprints on Western thought, as he is one of the first to introduce the idea that eudaimonia (happiness) is attainable only within consciousness.
The true human is an incorporeal contemplative capacity of the soul, and superior to all things corporeal. It then follows that real human happiness is independent of the physical world. Real happiness is, instead, dependent on the metaphysical and authentic human being found in this highest capacity of Reason. “For man, and especially the Proficient, is not the Couplement of Soul and body: the proof is that man can be disengaged from the body and disdain its nominal goods.” (Enneads I.4.14) The human who has achieved happiness will not be bothered by sickness, discomfort, etc., as his focus is on the greatest things. Authentic human happiness is the utilization of the most authentically human capacity of contemplation. Even in daily, physical action, the flourishing human’s “… Act is determined by the higher phase of the Soul.” (Enneads III.4.6) Even in the most dramatic arguments Plotinus considers (if the Proficient is subject to extreme physical torture, for example), he concludes this only strengthens his claim of true happiness being metaphysical, as the truly happy human being would understand that which is being tortured is merely a body, not the conscious self, and happiness could persist.
Plotinus offers a comprehensive description of his conception of a person who has achieved eudaimonia. “The perfect life” involves a man who commands reason and contemplation. (Enneads I.4.4) A happy person will not sway between happy and sad, as many of Plotinus' contemporaries believed. Stoics, for example, question the ability of someone to be happy (presupposing happiness is contemplation) if they are mentally incapacitated or even asleep. Plotinus disregards this claim, as the soul and true human do not sleep or even exist in time, nor will a living human who has achieved eudaimonia suddenly stop using its greatest, most authentic capacity just because of the body’s discomfort in the physical realm. “… The Proficient’s will is set always and only inward.” (Enneads I.4.11)
Overall, happiness for Plotinus is "... a flight from this world's ways and things." (Theaet. 176) and a focus on the highest, i.e. Forms and the One.
Plotinus regarded happiness as living in an interior way (interiority or self-sufficiency), and this being the obverse of attachment to the objects of embodied desires.
Henosis
Main article: HenosisHenosis is the word for mystical "oneness", "union", or "unity" in classical Greek. In Platonism, and especially neoplatonism, the goal of henosis is union with what is fundamental in reality: the One (τὸ Ἕν), the Source, or Monad.
As is specified in the writings of Plotinus on henology, one can reach a state of tabula rasa, a blank state where the individual may grasp or merge with The One. This absolute simplicity means that the nous or the person is then dissolved, completely absorbed back into the Monad. Here within the Enneads of Plotinus the Monad can be referred to as the Good above the demiurge. The Monad or dunamis (force) is of one singular expression (the will or the one which is the good); all is contained in the Monad and the Monad is all (pantheism). All division is reconciled in the one; the final stage before reaching singularity, called duality (dyad), is completely reconciled in the Monad, Source or One (see monism). As the one source or substance of all things, the Monad is all encompassing. As infinite and indeterminate all is reconciled in the dunamis or one. It is the demiurge or second emanation that is the nous in Plotinus. It is the demiurge (creator, action, energy) or nous that "perceives" and therefore causes the force (potential or One) to manifest as energy, or the dyad called the material world. Nous as being; being and perception (intellect) manifest what is called soul (World Soul).
Henosis for Plotinus was defined in his works as a reversing of the ontological process of consciousness via meditation (in the Western mind to uncontemplate) toward no thought (Nous or demiurge) and no division (dyad) within the individual (being). Plotinus words his teachings to reconcile not only Plato with Aristotle but also various World religions that he had personal contact with during his various travels. Plotinus' works have an ascetic character in that they reject matter as an illusion (non-existent). Matter was strictly treated as immanent, with matter as essential to its being, having no true or transcendential character or essence, substance or ousia (οὐσία). This approach is called philosophical Idealism.
Relation with contemporary philosophy and religion
Plotinus's Relation to Plato
See also: Allegorical interpretations of PlatoFor several centuries after the Protestant Reformation, neoplatonism was condemned as a decadent and 'oriental' distortion of Platonism. In a 1929 essay, E. R. Dodds showed that key conceptions of neoplatonism could be traced from their origin in Plato's dialogues, through his immediate followers (e.g., Speusippus) and the neopythagoreans, to Plotinus and the neoplatonists. Thus Plotinus' philosophy was, he argued, 'not the starting-point of neoplatonism but its intellectual culmination.' Further research reinforced this view and by 1954 Merlan could say 'The present tendency is toward bridging rather than widening the gap separating Platonism from neoplatonism.'
Since the 1950s, the Tübingen School of Plato interpretation has argued that the so-called 'unwritten doctrines' of Plato debated by Aristotle and the Old Academy strongly resemble Plotinus's metaphysics. In this case, the neoplatonic reading of Plato would be, at least in this central area, historically justified. This implies that neoplatonism is less of an innovation than it appears without the recognition of Plato's unwritten doctrines. Advocates of the Tübingen School emphasize this advantage of their interpretation. They see Plotinus as advancing a tradition of thought begun by Plato himself. Plotinus's metaphysics, at least in broad outline, was therefore already familiar to the first generation of Plato's students. This confirms Plotinus' own view, for he considered himself not the inventor of a system but the faithful interpreter of Plato's doctrines.
Plotinus and the Gnostics
See also: Neoplatonism and GnosticismThis section possibly contains original research. Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations. Statements consisting only of original research should be removed. (April 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
At least two modern conferences within Hellenic philosophy fields of study have been held in order to address what Plotinus stated in his tract Against the Gnostics and to whom he was addressing it, in order to separate and clarify the events and persons involved in the origin of the term "Gnostic". From the dialogue, it appears that the word had an origin in the Platonic and Hellenistic tradition long before the group calling themselves "Gnostics"—or the group covered under the modern term "Gnosticism"—ever appeared. It would seem that this shift from Platonic to Gnostic usage has led many people to confusion. The strategy of sectarians taking Greek terms from philosophical contexts and re-applying them to religious contexts was popular in Christianity, the Cult of Isis and other ancient religious contexts including Hermetic ones (see Alexander of Abonutichus for an example).
According to A. H. Armstrong, Plotinus and the neoplatonists viewed Gnosticism as a form of heresy or sectarianism to the Pythagorean and Platonic philosophy of the Mediterranean and Middle East. Also according to Armstrong, Plotinus accused them of using senseless jargon and being overly dramatic and insolent in their distortion of Plato's ontology." Armstrong argues that Plotinus attacks his opponents as untraditional, irrational and immoral and arrogant. Armstrong believed that Plotinus also attacks them as elitist and blasphemous to Plato for the Gnostics despising the material world and its maker.
For decades, Armstrong's was the only translation available of Plotinus. For this reason, his claims were authoritative. However, a modern translation by Lloyd P. Gerson doesn't necessarily support all of Armstrong's views. Unlike Armstrong, Gerson didn't find Plotinus to be so vitriolic against the Gnostics. According to Gerson:
As Plotinus himself tells us, at the time of this treatise’s composition some of his friends were ‘attached’ to Gnostic doctrine, and he believed that this attachment was harmful. So he sets out here a number of objections and corrections. Some of these are directed at very specific tenets of Gnosticism, e.g. the introduction of a ‘new earth’ or a principle of ‘Wisdom’, but the general thrust of this treatise has a much broader scope. The Gnostics are very critical of the sensible universe and its contents, and as a Platonist, Plotinus must share this critical attitude to some extent. But here he makes his case that the proper understanding of the highest principles and emanation forces us to respect the sensible world as the best possible imitation of the intelligible world.
Plotinus seems to direct his attacks at a very specific sect of Gnostics, most notably a sect of Christian Gnostics that held anti-polytheistic and anti-daemon views, and that preached salvation was possible without struggle. At one point, Plotinus makes clear that his major grudge is the way Gnostics 'misused' Plato's teachings, and not their own teachings themselves:
There are no hard feelings if they tell us in which respects they intend to disagree with Plato Rather, whatever strikes them as their own distinct views in comparison with the Greeks’, these views – as well as the views that contradict them – should be forthrightly set out on their own in a considerate and philosophical manner.
The neoplatonic movement (though Plotinus would have simply referred to himself as a philosopher of Plato) seems to be motivated by the desire of Plotinus to revive the pagan philosophical tradition. Plotinus was not claiming to innovate with the Enneads, but to clarify aspects of the works of Plato that he considered misrepresented or misunderstood. Plotinus does not claim to be an innovator, but rather a communicator of a tradition. Plotinus referred to tradition as a way to interpret Plato's intentions. Because the teachings of Plato were for members of the academy rather than the general public, it was easy for outsiders to misunderstand Plato's meaning. However, Plotinus attempted to clarify how the philosophers of the academy had not arrived at the same conclusions (such as misotheism or dystheism of the creator God as an answer to the problem of evil) as the targets of his criticism.
Against causal astrology
This section does not cite any sources. Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
Plotinus seems to be one of the first to have argued against the then popular notion of causal astrology. In the late tractate 2.3, "Are the stars causes?", Plotinus makes the argument that specific stars influencing one's fortune (a common Hellenistic theme) attributes irrationality to a perfect universe, and invites moral depravity. He does, however, claim the stars and planets are ensouled, as witnessed by their movement.
Influence
Ancient world
The emperor Julian the Apostate was deeply influenced by neoplatonism, as was Hypatia of Alexandria. Neoplatonism influenced many Christians as well, including Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite. St. Augustine, though often referred to as a "Platonist," acquired his Platonist philosophy through the mediation of the Neoplatonist teachings of Plotinus.
Christianity
Plotinus' philosophy had an influence on the development of Christian theology. In A History of Western Philosophy, philosopher Bertrand Russell wrote that:
To the Christian, the Other World was the Kingdom of Heaven, to be enjoyed after death; to the Platonist, it was the eternal world of ideas, the real world as opposed to that of illusory appearance. Christian theologians combined these points of view, and embodied much of the philosophy of Plotinus. Plotinus, accordingly, is historically important as an influence in moulding the Christianity of the Middle Ages and of theology.
The Eastern Orthodox position on energy, for example, is often contrasted with the position of the Roman Catholic Church, and in part this is attributed to varying interpretations of Aristotle and Plotinus, either through Thomas Aquinas for the Roman Catholics or Gregory Palamas for the Orthodox Christians.
Islam
Neoplatonism and the ideas of Plotinus influenced medieval Islam as well, since the Mutazilite Abbasids fused Greek concepts into sponsored state texts, and found great influence amongst the Ismaili Shia and Persian philosophers as well, such as Muhammad al-Nasafi and Abu Yaqub Sijistani. By the 11th century, neoplatonism was adopted by the Fatimid state of Egypt, and taught by their da'i. Neoplatonism was brought to the Fatimid court by Hamid al-Din al-Kirmani, although his teachings differed from Nasafi and Sijistani, who were more aligned with the original teachings of Plotinus. The teachings of Kirmani in turn influenced philosophers such as Nasir Khusraw of Persia.
Judaism
This section does not cite any sources. Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
As with Islam and Christianity, neoplatonism in general and Plotinus in particular influenced speculative thought. Notable thinkers expressing neoplatonist themes are Solomon ibn Gabirol (Latin: Avicebron) and Moses ben Maimon (Latin: Maimonides). As with Islam and Christianity, apophatic theology and the privative nature of evil are two prominent themes that such thinkers picked up from either Plotinus or his successors.
Renaissance
This section does not cite any sources. Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed. (April 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this message) |
In the Renaissance the philosopher Marsilio Ficino set up an Academy under the patronage of Cosimo de Medici in Florence, mirroring that of Plato. His work was of great importance in reconciling the philosophy of Plato directly with Christianity. One of his most distinguished pupils was Pico della Mirandola, author of An Oration On the Dignity of Man.
Great Britain
In Great Britain, Plotinus was the cardinal influence on the 17th-century school of the Cambridge Platonists, and on numerous writers from Samuel Taylor Coleridge to W. B. Yeats and Kathleen Raine.
India
Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan and Ananda Coomaraswamy used the writing of Plotinus in their own texts as a superlative elaboration upon Indian monism, specifically Upanishadic and Advaita Vedantic thought. Coomaraswamy has compared Plotinus' teachings to the Hindu school of Advaita Vedanta (advaita meaning "not two" or "non-dual"). M. Vasudevacharya says “Though Plotinus never managed to reach India, his method shows an affinity to the “method of negation” as taught in some of the Upanishads, such as the Brhadaranyaka Upanishad, and also to the practice of yoga.
Advaita Vedanta and neoplatonism have been compared by J. F. Staal, Frederick Copleston, Aldo Magris and Mario Piantelli, Radhakrishnan, Gwen Griffith-Dickson, and John Y. Fenton.
The joint influence of Advaitin and neoplatonic ideas on Ralph Waldo Emerson was considered by Dale Riepe in 1967.
See also
- Antiochus of Ascalon
- Disciples of Plotinus
- Ecstasy in philosophy
- Emanationism
- Form of the Good
- Allegorical interpretations of Plato
- The One in Neoplatonism
- Pantaenus
- Platonic Academy
- Plato's unwritten doctrines
- Plutarch of Chaeronea
- The Theology of Aristotle
- Thomas Taylor
Notes
- Plotinus:
* "Our thought cannot grasp the One as long as any other image remains active in the soul. To this end, you must set free your soul from all outward things and turn wholly within yourself, with no more leaning to what lies outside, and lay your mind bare of ideal forms, as before of the objects of sense, and forget even yourself, and so come within sight of that One. (6.9.7)
* "If he remembers who he became when he merged with the One, he will bear its image in himself. He was himself one, with no diversity in himself or his outward relations; for no movement was in him, no passion, no desire for another, once the ascent was accomplished. Nor indeed was there any reason or though, nor, if we dare say it, any trace of himself." (6.9.11) - From Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads as translated by A. H. Armstrong, pp. 220–222:
The treatise as it stands in the Enneads is a most powerful protest on behalf of Hellenic philosophy against the un-Hellenic heresy (as it was from the Platonist as well as the orthodox Christian point of view) of Gnosticism. There were Gnostics among Plotinus's own friends, whom he had not succeeded in converting (Enneads ch.10 of this treatise) and he and his pupils devoted considerable time and energy to anti-Gnostic controversy (Life of Plotinus ch.16). He obviously considered Gnosticism an extremely dangerous influence, likely to pervert the minds even of members of his own circle. It is impossible to attempt to give an account of Gnosticism here. By far the best discussion of what the particular group of Gnostics Plotinus knew believed is M. Puech's admirable contribution to Entretiens Hardt V (Les Sourcesde Plotin). But it is important for the understanding of this treatise to be clear about the reasons why Plotinus disliked them so intensely and thought their influence so harmful. - From Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads as translated by A. H. Armstrong, pp. 220–222:
Short statement of the doctrine of the three hypostasis, the One, Intellect and Soul; there cannot be more or fewer than these three.
1. Criticism of the attempts to multiply the hypostasis, and especially of the idea of two intellects, one which thinks and that other which thinks that it thinks. (Against the Gnostics, Enneads ch. 1). The true doctrine of Soul (ch. 2).
2. The law of necessary procession and the eternity of the universe (ch. 3).
- Attack on the Gnostic doctrine of the making of the universe by a fallen soul, and on their despising of the universe and the heavenly bodies (chs. 4–5).
- The sense-less jargon of the Gnostics, their plagiarism from and perversion of Plato, and their insolent arrogance (ch. 6).
3. The true doctrine about Universal Soul and the goodness of the universe which it forms and rules (chs. 7–8).
4. Refutation of objections from the inequalities and injustices of human life (ch. 9).
5. Ridiculous arrogance of the Gnostics who refuse to acknowledge the hierarchy of created gods and spirits and say that they alone are sons of God and superior to the heavens (ch. 9).
6. The absurdities of the Gnostic doctrine of the fall of "Wisdom" (Sophia) and of the generation and activities of the Demiurge, maker of the visible universe (chs. 10–12).
7. False and melodramatic Gnostic teaching about the cosmic spheres and their influence (ch. 13).
8. The blasphemous falsity of the Gnostic claim to control the higher powers by magic and the absurdity of their claim to cure diseases by casting out demons (ch. 14).
9. The false other-worldliness of the Gnostics leads to immorality (ch. 15).
10. The true Platonic other-worldliness, which loves and venerates the material universe in all its goodness and beauty as the most perfect possible image of the intelligible, contracted at length with the false, Gnostic, other-worldliness which hates and despises the material universe and its beauties (chs. 16–18).
A. H. Lawrence, Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads, pages 220–222 - From Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads as translated by A. H. Armstrong, pp. 220–222:
The teaching of the Gnostics seems to him untraditional, irrational and immoral. They despise and revile the ancient Platonic teaching and claim to have a new and superior wisdom of their own: but in fact anything that is true in their teaching comes from Plato, and all they have done themselves is to add senseless complications and pervert the true traditional doctrine into a melodramatic, superstitious fantasy designed to feed their own delusions of grandeur. They reject the only true way of salvation through wisdom and virtue, the slow patient study of truth and pursuit of perfection by men who respect the wisdom of the ancients and that know their place in the universe. Pages 220–222 - Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads as translated by A. H. Armstrong, pp. 220–222:
9. The false other-worldliness of the Gnostics leads to immorality (Enneads ch. 15). - Introduction to Against the Gnostics in Plotinus' Enneads as translated by A. H. Armstrong, pp. 220–222:
Ridiculous arrogance of the Gnostics who refuse to acknowledge the hierarchy of created gods and spirits and say that they alone are sons of God and superior to the heavens (Enneads ch. 9) - They claim to be a privileged caste of beings, in whom alone God is interested, and who are saved not by their own efforts but by some dramatic and arbitrary divine proceeding; and this, Plotinus says, leads to immorality. Worst of all, they despise and hate the material universe and deny its goodness and the goodness of its maker. This for a Platonist is utter blasphemy, and all the worse because it obviously derives to some extent from the sharply other-worldly side of Plato's own teaching (e.g. in the Phaedo). At this point in his attack Plotinus comes very close in some ways to the orthodox Christian opponents of Gnosticism, who also insist that this world is the good work of God in his goodness. But, here as on the question of salvation, the doctrine which Plotinus is defending is as sharply opposed on other ways to orthodox Christianity as to Gnosticism: for he maintains not only the goodness of the material universe but also its eternity and its divinity. The idea that the universe could have a beginning and end is inseparably connected in his mind with the idea that the divine action in making it is arbitrary and irrational. And to deny the divinity (though a subordinate and dependent divinity) of the World-Soul, and of those noblest of embodied living beings the heavenly bodies, seems to him both blasphemous and unreasonable. Pages 220–222
- "... as Plotinus had endeavored to revive the religious spirit of paganism".
References
- ^ Gerson, Lloyd P. (2017). "Plotinus and Platonism". In Tarrant, Harold; Renaud, François; Baltzly, Dirk; Layne, Danielle A. (eds.). Brill's Companion to the Reception of Plato in Antiquity. Brill's Companions to Classical Reception. Vol. 13. Leiden and Boston: Brill Publishers. pp. 316–335. doi:10.1163/9789004355385_018. ISBN 978-90-04-27069-5. ISSN 2213-1426.
- ^ Armstrong, A. Hilary; Duignan, Brian; Lotha, Gloria; Rodriguez, Emily (1 January 2021) . "Plotinus". Encyclopædia Britannica. Edinburgh: Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc. Archived from the original on 17 April 2021. Retrieved 5 August 2021.
Plotinus (born 205 CE, Lyco, or Lycopolis, Egypt?—died 270, Campania), ancient philosopher, the centre of an influential circle of intellectuals and men of letters in 3rd-century Rome, who is regarded by modern scholars as the founder of the neoplatonic school of philosophy. In his 28th year—he seems to have been rather a late developer—Plotinus felt an impulse to study philosophy and thus went to Alexandria. He attended the lectures of the most eminent professors in Alexandria at the time, which reduced him to a state of complete depression. In the end, a friend who understood what he wanted took him to hear the self-taught philosopher Ammonius Saccas. When he had heard Ammonius speak, Plotinus said, "This is the man I was looking for," and stayed with him for 11 years. At the end of his time with Ammonius, Plotinus joined the expedition of the Roman emperor Gordian III against Persia (242–243), with the intention of trying to learn something at first hand about the philosophies of the Persians and Indians. The expedition came to a disastrous end in Mesopotamia, however, when Gordian was murdered by the soldiers and Philip the Arabian was proclaimed emperor. Plotinus escaped with difficulty and made his way back to Antioch. From there he went to Rome, where he settled at the age of 40. Plotinus's own thought shows some striking similarities to Indian philosophy, but he never actually made contact with Eastern sages because of the failure of the expedition. Though direct or indirect contact with Indians educated in their own religious-philosophical traditions may not have been impossible in 3rd-century Alexandria, the resemblances of the philosophy of Plotinus to Indian thought were more likely a natural development of the Greek tradition that he inherited.
- ^ Gerson, Lloyd P. (Fall 2018). "Plotinus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. OCLC 643092515. Archived from the original on 26 November 2018. Retrieved 5 August 2021.
Plotinus (204/5 – 270 C.E.), is generally regarded as the founder of neoplatonism. He is one of the most influential philosophers in antiquity after Plato and Aristotle. The term 'neoplatonism' is an invention of early 19th century European scholarship and indicates the penchant of historians for dividing 'periods' in history. In this case, the term was intended to indicate that Plotinus initiated a new phase in the development of the Platonic tradition. What this 'newness' amounted to, if anything, is controversial, largely because one's assessment of it depends upon one's assessment of what Platonism is. In fact, Plotinus (like all his successors) regarded himself simply as a Platonist, that is, as an expositor and defender of the philosophical position whose greatest exponent was Plato himself. The three basic principles of Plotinus' metaphysics are called by him 'the One' (or, equivalently, 'the Good'), Intellect, and Soul. These principles are both ultimate ontological realities and explanatory principles. Plotinus believed that they were recognized by Plato as such, as well as by the entire subsequent Platonic tradition. Porphyry informs us that during the first ten years of his time in Rome, Plotinus lectured exclusively on the philosophy of Ammonius. During this time he also wrote nothing. Porphyry tells us that when he himself arrived in Rome in 263, the first 21 of Plotinus' treatises had already been written. The remainder of the 54 treatises constituting his Enneads were written in the last seven or eight years of his life.
- ^ Siorvanes, Lucas (2018). "Plotinus and Neoplatonism: The Creation of a New Synthesis". In Keyser, Paul T.; Scarborough, John (eds.). Oxford Handbook of Science and Medicine in the Classical World. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 847–868. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199734146.013.78. ISBN 9780199734146. LCCN 2017049555.
- ^ Halfwassen, Jens (2014). "The Metaphysics of the One". In Remes, Pauliina; Slaveva-Griffin, Svetla (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Neoplatonism. Routledge Handbooks in Philosophy. Abingdon, Oxfordshire and New York: Routledge. pp. 182–199. ISBN 9781138573963.
- ^ Stamatellos, Giannis (2007). "Matter and Soul". Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences on Plotinus' Enneads. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press. pp. 161–172. ISBN 978-0-7914-7061-9. LCCN 2006017562.
- "Who was Plotinus?". Australian Broadcasting Corporation. 2011-06-07.
- Bilolo, M.: La notion de « l’Un » dans les Ennéades de Plotin et dans les Hymnes thébains. Contribution à l’étude des sources égyptiennes du néo-platonisme. In: D. Kessler, R. Schulz (Eds.), "Gedenkschrift für Winfried Barta ḥtp dj n ḥzj" (Münchner Ägyptologische Untersuchungen, Bd. 4), Frankfurt; Berlin; Bern; New York; Paris; Wien: Peter Lang, 1995, pp. 67–91.
- ^ Gerson, Lloyd P. (1999). Plotinus. Taylor & Francis. pp. XII (12). ISBN 978-0-415-20352-4.
- Rist, John M.; Rist (1967). Plotinus: Road to Reality. CUP Archive. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-521-06085-1.
- "Plotinus." The Columbia Electronic Encyclopedia, Sixth Edition. Columbia University Press, 2003.
- ^ Leete, Helen, 1938- (23 December 2016). Beauty and the mystic : Plotinus and Hawkins. Epping, N.S.W. ISBN 9780987524836. OCLC 967937243.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link) CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link) CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link) - Porphyry, On the Life of Plotinus and the Order of His Books, Ch. 3 (in Armstrong's Loeb translation, "he became eager to make acquaintance with the Persian philosophical discipline and that prevailing among the Indians").
- Porphyry, Vita Plotini, 9. See also Emma C. Clarke, John M. Dillon, and Jackson P. Hershbell (1999), Iamblichus on The Mysteries, page xix. SBL. who say that "to gain some credible chronology, one assumes that Ariston married Amphicleia some time after Plotinus's death"
- Mark Edwards, Neoplatonic Saints: The Lives of Plotinus and Proclus by Their Students, Liverpool University Press, 2000, p. 4 n. 20.
- Stace, W. T. (1960) The Teachings of the Mystics, New York, Signet, pp. 110–123
- Stace, W. T. (1960) The Teachings of the Mystics, New York, Signet, p. 122
- Plotinus (204—270 C.E.)
- Lander, Janis (2013). Spiritual Art and Art Education. Routledge. p. 76. ISBN 9781134667895.
- Plotinus (1950). The philosophy of Plotinus: representative books from the Enneads. Appleton-Century-Crofts. p. vii. Retrieved 1 February 2012.
- "Plotinus". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
- Stamatellos, Giannis. Plotinus and the Presocratics: A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences in Plotinus' Enneads. SUNY Series in Ancient Greek Philosophy. SUNY Press, 2007, p. 37 ISBN 0791470628
- ^ Neoplatonism and Gnosticism by Richard T. Wallis, Jay Bregman, International Society for Neoplatonic Studies, p. 55
- Richard T. Wallis; Jay Bregman (1992). "Pleroma and Noetic Cosmos: A Comparative Study". Neoplatonism and Gnosticism. SUNY Press. p. 99. ISBN 978-0-7914-1337-1.
- Schopenhauer wrote of this neoplatonist philosopher: "With Plotinus there even appears, probably for the first time in Western philosophy, idealism that had long been current in the East even at that time, for it taught (Enneads, iii, lib. vii, c.10) that the soul has made the world by stepping from eternity into time, with the explanation: 'For there is for this universe no other place than the soul or mind' (neque est alter hujus universi locus quam anima), indeed the ideality of time is expressed in the words: 'We should not accept time outside the soul or mind' (oportet autem nequaquam extra animam tempus accipere)." (Parerga and Paralipomena, Volume I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy," § 7)
- E. R. Dodds, 'The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the neoplatonic One,' The Classical Quarterly, v. 22, No. 3/4, 1928, pp. 129-142, esp. 140.
- Philip Merlan, From Platonism to Neoplatonism (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1954, 1968), p. 3.
- Detlef Thiel: Die Philosophie des Xenokrates im Kontext der Alten Akademie, München 2006, pp. 197ff. and note 64; Jens Halfwassen: Der Aufstieg zum Einen.
- ^ Plotinus: The Enneads. Cambridge University Press. 2017. ISBN 9781107001770.
- A Biographical History of Philosophy, by George Henry Lewes Published 1892, G. Routledge & Sons, LTD, p. 294
- Pseudo-Dionysius in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Dingeldein, Laura B. (2016). "Julian's Philosophy and His Religious Program". In DesRosiers, Nathaniel P.; Vuong, Lily C. (eds.). Religious Competition in the Greco-Roman World. Atlanta: SBL Press. pp. 119–129. ISBN 978-0884141587.
- Michael A. B. Deakin (2018-02-22). "Hypatia". Encyclopædia Britannica. Archived from the original on 2018-03-26.
- W. R. Inge (April 1900). "The Permanent Influence of Neoplatonism upon Christianity". The American Journal of Theology. 4 (2): 328–344. doi:10.1086/477376. JSTOR 3153114.
- Rhodes, Michael Craig (2014). "Pseudo-Dionysius' concept of God". International Journal of Philosophy and Theology. 75 (4): 306–318. doi:10.1080/21692327.2015.1011683. S2CID 170105090.
- Mendelson, Michael (2016). "Saint Augustine". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 ed.). Stanford: Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Gersh, Stephen (2012). "The First Principles of Latin Neoplatonism: Augustine, Macrobius, Boethius". Vivarium. 50 (2): 113–117, 120–125, 130–132, 134–138. doi:10.1163/15685349-12341236. JSTOR 41963885.
- "A History of Western Philosophy." Bertrand Russell. Simon and Schuster, INC. 1945. pp. 284–285
- ^ Heinz Halm, Shi'ism, Columbia University Press, 2004, p. 176.
- ^ Heinz Halm, Shi'ism, Columbia University Press, 2004, p. 177.
- Michaud, Derek (2017). Reason Turned into Sense: John Smith on Spiritual Sensation. Peeters. pp. 102–105, 114, 115, 129, 137, 146, 153, 154, 155, 172, 174, 175, 177–178, 180, 181, 181, 184, 185, 188, 195.
- "W. B. Yeats and "A Vision": Plotinus and the Principles".
- Samuel Taylor Coleridge (2019). The Notebooks of Samuel Taylor Coleridge, Volume 4: 1819-1826: Notes. Princeton University Press. p. 453. ISBN 978-0-691-65599-4.
- Anna Baldwin; Sarah Hutton; Senior Lecturer School of Humanities Sarah Hutton (24 March 1994). Platonism and the English Imagination. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-40308-5.
- Swami-krishnananda.org
- Vasudevacharya, M. (2017). The Maker and the Material. Milton Keynes, UK. p. 84. ISBN 978-1-925666-82-3.
- J. F. Staal (1961), Advaita and Neoplatonism: A critical study in comparative philosophy, Madras: University of Madras
- Frederick Charles Copleston. "Religion and the One 1979–1981". Giffordlectures.org. Archived from the original on 2010-04-09. Retrieved 2010-01-08.
- Special section "Fra Oriente e Occidente" in Annuario filosofico No. 6 (1990), including the articles "Plotino e l'India" by Aldo Magris and "L'India e Plotino" by Mario Piantelli
- Sarvepalli Radhakrishnan (ed.)(1952), History of Philosophy Eastern and Western, Vol.2. London: George Allen & Unwin. p. 114
- "Creator (or not?)". Gresham.ac.uk. Retrieved 2010-01-08.
- John Y. Fenton (1981), "Mystical Experience as a Bridge for Cross-Cultural Philosophy of Religion: A Critique", Journal of the American Academy of Religion, p. 55
- Dale Riepe (1967), "Emerson and Indian Philosophy", Journal of the History of Ideas 28(1):115 (1967)
Plotinus
By Plotinus
Bibliography
- Critical editions of the Greek text
- Émile Bréhier, Plotin: Ennéades (with French translation), Collection Budé, 1924–1938.
- Paul Henry and Hans-Rudolf Schwyzer (eds.), Editio maior (3 volumes), Paris, Desclée de Brouwer, 1951–1973.
- Paul Henry and Hans-Rudolf Schwyzer (eds.), Editio minor, Oxford, Oxford Classical Text, 1964–1982.
- Complete English translation
- Thomas Taylor, Collected Writings of Plotinus, Frome, Prometheus Trust, 1994. ISBN 1-898910-02-2 (contains approximately half of the Enneads)
- Plotinus. The Enneads (translated by Stephen MacKenna), London, Medici Society, 1917–1930 (an online version is available at Sacred Texts); 2nd edition, B. S. Page (ed.), 1956.
- A. H. Armstrong, Plotinus. Enneads (with Greek text), Loeb Classical Library, 7 vol., 1966–1988.
- Lloyd P. Gerson (ed.), George Boys-Stones, John M. Dillon, Lloyd P. Gerson, R.A. King, Andrew Smith and James Wilberding (trs.). The Enneads. Cambridge University Press, 2018.
- Lexica
- J. H. Sleeman and G. Pollet, Lexicon Plotinianum, Leiden, 1980.
- Roberto Radice (ed.), Lexicon II: Plotinus, Milan, Biblia, 2004. (Electronic edition by Roberto Bombacigno)
- The Life of Plotinus by Porphyry
- Porphyry, "On the Life of Plotinus and the Arrangement of his Works" in Mark Edwards (ed.), Neoplatonic Saints: The Lives of Plotinus and Proclus by their Students, Liverpool, Liverpool University Press, 2000.
- Anthologies of texts in translation, with annotations
- Kevin Corrigan, Reading Plotinus: A Practical Introduction to Neoplatonism, West Lafayette, Purdue University Press, 2005.
- John M. Dillon and Lloyd P. Gerson, Neoplatonic Philosophy: Introductory Readings, Hackett, 2004.
- Introductory works
- Erik Emilsson, Plotinus, New York: Routledge, 2017.
- Kevin Corrigan, Reading Plotinus. A Practical Introduction to Neoplatonism, Purdue University Press, 1995.
- Lloyd P. Gerson, Plotinus, New York, Routledge, 1994.
- Lloyd P. Gerson (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, Cambridge, 1996.
- Dominic J. O'Meara, Plotinus. An Introduction to the Enneads, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1993. (Reprinted 2005)
- John M. Rist, Plotinus. The Road to Reality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1967.
- Major commentaries in English
- Cinzia Arruzza, Plotinus: Ennead II.5, On What Is Potentially and What Actually, The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2015, ISBN 978-1-930972-63-6
- Michael Atkinson, Plotinus: Ennead V.1, On the Three Principal Hypostases, Oxford, 1983.
- Kevin Corrigan, Plotinus' Theory of Matter-Evil: Plato, Aristotle, and Alexander of Aphrodisias (II.4, II.5, III.6, I.8), Leiden, 1996.
- John N. Deck, Nature, Contemplation and the One: A Study in the Philosophy of Plotinus, University of Toronto Press, 1967; Paul Brunton Philosophical Foundation, 1991.
- John M. Dillon, H.J. Blumenthal, Plotinus: Ennead IV.3-4.29, "Problems Concerning the Soul", The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2015, ISBN 978-1-930972-89-6
- Eyjólfur K. Emilsson, Steven K. Strange, Plotinus: Ennead VI.4 & VI.5: On the Presence of Being, One and the Same, Everywhere as a Whole, The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2015, ISBN 978-1-930972-34-6
- Barrie Fleet, Plotinus: Ennead III.6, On the Impassivity of the Bodiless, Oxford, 1995.
- Barrie Fleet, Plotinus: Ennead IV.8, On the Descent of the Soul into Bodies, The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2012. ISBN 978-1-930972-77-3
- Lloyd P. Gerson, Plotinus: Ennead V.5, That the Intelligibles are not External to the Intellect, and on the Good, The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2013, ISBN 978-1-930972-85-8
- Sebastian R. P. Gertz, Plotinus: Ennead II.9, Against the Gnostics, The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2017, ISBN 978-1-930972-37-7
- Gary M. Gurtler, SJ, Plotinus: Ennead IV.4.30-45 & IV.5, "Problems Concerning the Soul", The Enneads of Plotinus Series edited by John M. Dillon and Andrew Smith, Parmenides Publishing, 2015, ISBN 978-1-930972-69-8
- W. Helleman-Elgersma, Soul-Sisters. A Commentary on Enneads IV, 3 (27), 1–8 of Plotinus, Amsterdam, 1980.
- James Luchte, Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn. London: Bloomsbury Publishing, 2011. ISBN 978-0567353313.
- Kieran McGroarty, Plotinus on Eudaimonia: A Commentary on Ennead I.4, Oxford, 2006.
- P. A. Meijer, Plotinus on the Good or the One (VI.9), Amsterdam, 1992.
- H. Oosthout, Modes of Knowledge and the Transcendental: An Introduction to Plotinus Ennead V.3, Amsterdam, 1991.
- J. Wilberding, Plotinus' Cosmology. A study of Ennead II. 1 (40), Oxford, 2006.
- A. M. Wolters, Plotinus on Eros: A Detailed Exegetical Study of Enneads III, 5, Amsterdam, 1972.
- General works on Neoplatonism
- Robert M. Berchman, From Philo to Origen: Middle Platonism in Transition, Chico, Scholars Press, 1984.
- Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy: Vol. 1, Part 2. ISBN 0-385-00210-6
- P. Merlan, "Greek Philosophy from Plato to Plotinus" in A. H. Armstrong (ed.), The Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy, Cambridge, 1967. ISBN 0-521-04054-X
- Pauliina Remes, Neoplatonism (Ancient Philosophies), University of California Press, 2008.
- Thomas Taylor, The fragments that remain of the lost writings of Proclus, surnamed the Platonic successor, London, 1825. (Selene Books reprint edition, 1987. ISBN 0-933601-11-5)
- Richard T. Wallis, Neoplatonism and Gnosticism, University of Oklahoma, 1984. ISBN 0-7914-1337-3 and ISBN 0-7914-1338-1
- Studies on some aspects of Plotinus' work
- R. B. Harris (ed.), Neoplatonism and Indian Thought, Albany, 1982.
- Giannis Stamatellos, Plotinus and the Presocratics. A Philosophical Study of Presocratic Influences in Plotinus' Enneads, Albany, 2008.
- N. Joseph Torchia, Plotinus, Tolma, and the Descent of Being, New York, Peter Lang, 1993. ISBN 0-8204-1768-8
- Antonia Tripolitis, The Doctrine of the Soul in the thought of Plotinus and Origen, Libra Publishers, 1978.
- M. F. Wagner (ed.), Neoplatonism and Nature. Studies in Plotinus' Enneads, Albany, 2002.
External links
- Works by Plotinus at Project Gutenberg
- Works by or about Plotinus at the Internet Archive
- Works by Plotinus at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)
- Direct links to each Tractate of the Enneads in English, Greek and French.
- Text of the Enneads
- Greek original (page scans of Adolf Kirchhoff's 1856 Teubner edition) with English (complete) and French (partial) translations;
- Online English translations
- Plotinus, The Six Enneads, translated by Stephen MacKenna (with B. S. Page), at Sacred Texts.
- The Internet Classics Archive of MIT The Six Enneads, translated into English by Stephen MacKenna and B.S. Page.
- On the Intelligible Beauty, translated by Thomas Taylor Ennead V viii(see also the Catalog of other books which include Porphyry, Plotinus' biographer – TTS Catalog).
- Philosophy Archive: An Essay on the Beautiful, translated into English by Thomas Taylor in 1917
- On the First Good and the Other Goods, Ennead 1.7. Translated by Eric S. Fallick, 2011
- On Dialectic, Ennead 1.3 Translated by Eric S. Fallick, 2015
- Encyclopedias
- Gerson, Lloyd P. "Plotinus". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Moore, Edward. "Plotinus". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Bibliographies
- In English, by Richard Dufour.
- In French by Pierre Thillet.
- Plotinus' Criticism of Aristotle's Categories (Enneads VI, 1-3) with an annotated bibliography
Ancient Greek schools of philosophy | |||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Proto-philosophy |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Pre-Socratic |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Classical |
| ||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
Hellenistic |
|
Metaphysics | |
---|---|
Theories |
|
Concepts |
|
Metaphysicians |
|
Notable works |
|
Related topics | |
- Plotinus
- 205 births
- 270 deaths
- 3rd-century Egyptian people
- 3rd-century Greek writers
- 3rd-century philosophers
- 3rd-century Romans
- 3rd-century writers
- Ancient Greek epistemologists
- Ancient Greek ethicists
- Ancient Greek logicians
- Ancient Greek metaphilosophers
- Ancient Greek metaphysicians
- Ancient Greek philosophers
- Ancient Greek philosophers of art
- Ancient Greek philosophers of mind
- Ancient Greek political philosophers
- Ancient Greek writers
- Ancient Lycopolitans
- Anti-Gnosticism
- Commentators on Aristotle
- Commentators on Plato
- Critics of atheism
- Egyptian philosophers
- Epistemologists
- Founders of philosophical traditions
- History of ethics
- History of logic
- History of philosophy
- Idealists
- Intellectual history
- Logicians
- Metaphilosophers
- Metaphysicians
- Moral philosophers
- Mystics
- Neoplatonist mystics
- Neoplatonists
- Ontologists
- Pagan anti-Gnosticism
- Philosophical theists
- Philosophers of art
- Philosophers of culture
- Philosophers of education
- Philosophers of ethics and morality
- Philosophers of logic
- Philosophers of mind
- Philosophers of religion
- Philosophy academics
- Philosophy teachers
- Philosophy writers
- Platonists
- Rationalists
- Roman-era Greeks
- Roman-era philosophers