Misplaced Pages

Reason: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editNext edit →Content deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 10:39, 2 October 2002 edit217.168.172.202 (talk) slight re-wording← Previous edit Revision as of 08:38, 25 December 2002 edit undoRyguasu (talk | contribs)1,467 edits cleaning up, rearranging, +Lakoff/Johnson quoteNext edit →
Line 1: Line 1:
In ], '''reason''' (from Latin ''ratio'', by way of French ''raison'') is the faculty by means of which or the process through which human beings perform thought, especially abstract thought. Many thinkers have pondered reason, and the various views on the nature of reason may not be compatible with one another.
'''Reason''' (through French ''raison'' from Latin ''ratio''), in ], is the faculty or process of drawing logical ]s.


'''Reason''' is sometimes narrowly defined as the faculty or process of drawing logical inferences. From ] onwards, such reasoning has been classified as either '']'', meaning "from the general to the particular", or '']'', meaning "from the particular to the general". In the ], ], an ] philosopher, added a third classification, '']'', by which he meant "from the best available information to the best explanation", which has become an important component of the ]. In modern usage, "inductive reasoning" sometimes includes almost all non-deductive reasoning, including what Peirce would call "abductive". (See also ], ].)
Thus we speak of '']'' as essentially a ] animal, it being implied that humans differ from all other ]s in that they can consciously draw inferences from ]s.
It is, however, exceedingly difficult in this respect to draw an absolute distinction between humans and other animals, observation of which undoubtedly suggests that the latter have a certain power of making inferences.
Compare ].


'''Reason''' has also been conceived more broadly. ] and ] explicate reason and its scope in this manner:
It is usually agreed, however, that inference by humans differs from that of animals in self-], and, though there can be no doubt that some animals ], it is difficult to find evidence for the presence of ] images in the minds of any but the most closely related animals.


:Reason includes not only our capacity for logical inference, but also our ability to conduct inquiry, to solve problems, to evaluate, to criticize, to deliberate about how we should act, and to reach an understanding of ourselves, other people, and the world. (Lakoff and Johnson 1999, pp. 3-4)
The term ''reason'' is also used in several narrower senses.
Thus reason is opposed to sensation, ], feeling, desire, as the faculty (the existence of which is denied by ]s) by which fundamental truths are intuitively apprehended.
These fundamental truths are the causes or "reasons" that things exist or happen.


'''Reason''' is often opposed to sensation, ], feeling, and desire.
For ], reason (''Vernunft'' in Kant's ]) is the power of synthesizing into unity, by means of comprehensive principles, the concepts provided by the ] (''Verstand'').
The reason which gives '']'' principles Kant calls "Pure Reason" (as in his <cite>]</cite>), as distinguished from the "Practical Reason" which is specially concerned with the performance of particular actions.


] see '''reason''' as the faculty by which fundamental truths are intuitively apprehended. These fundamental truths are the causes or "reasons" that things exist or happen. Empiricists, of course, deny the existence of such a faculty.
In ] the drawing of inference, or using the reasoning faculty, is called called ratiocination, or, more simply, "reasoning".
From ] onwards, reasoning is classified '']'', meaning "from the general to the particular", and '']'', meaning "from the particular to the general".
In the ], ], an ] philosopher, added to these a third, '']'', by which he meant "from the best available information to the best explanation", which has become an important component of the ].
See also ], ].


For ], '''reason''' (''Vernunft'' in Kant's ]) is the power of synthesizing into unity, by means of comprehensive principles, the concepts provided by the ] (''Verstand''). The reason which gives '']'' principles Kant calls "Pure Reason" (as in his <cite>]</cite>), as distinguished from the "Practical Reason" which is specially concerned with the performance of particular actions.
In ], reason, as distinguished from ], is the human intelligence exercised upon religious truth whether by way of discovery or by way of explanation.

In ], '''reason''', as distinguished from ], is the human intelligence exercised upon religious truth whether by way of discovery or by way of explanation.
The limits within which reason may be used have been laid down differently in different churches and periods of thought: on the whole, modern ], especially in the ] churches, tends to allow to reason a wide field, reserving, however, as the sphere of faith the ultimate (]) truths of theology. The limits within which reason may be used have been laid down differently in different churches and periods of thought: on the whole, modern ], especially in the ] churches, tends to allow to reason a wide field, reserving, however, as the sphere of faith the ultimate (]) truths of theology.

Regardless of how it is conceived, '''reason''' has often been seen as a uniquely human trait, which separates us from the other ]s.

These days, the idea of reason as an independent faculty of the mind, separate from emotions, and unique to humanity, is under attack from a number of sources. Consider, for example, ] and ]'s theories about the "embodied mind". (See the Lakoff article for more information.)

== References ==

* ] and ] (1999). ''Philosophy In The Flesh''. Basic Books.

Revision as of 08:38, 25 December 2002

In philosophy, reason (from Latin ratio, by way of French raison) is the faculty by means of which or the process through which human beings perform thought, especially abstract thought. Many thinkers have pondered reason, and the various views on the nature of reason may not be compatible with one another.

Reason is sometimes narrowly defined as the faculty or process of drawing logical inferences. From Aristotle onwards, such reasoning has been classified as either deductive reasoning, meaning "from the general to the particular", or inductive reasoning, meaning "from the particular to the general". In the 19th century, Charles Peirce, an American philosopher, added a third classification, abductive reasoning, by which he meant "from the best available information to the best explanation", which has become an important component of the scientific method. In modern usage, "inductive reasoning" sometimes includes almost all non-deductive reasoning, including what Peirce would call "abductive". (See also logic, syllogism.)

Reason has also been conceived more broadly. George Lakoff and Mark Johnson explicate reason and its scope in this manner:

Reason includes not only our capacity for logical inference, but also our ability to conduct inquiry, to solve problems, to evaluate, to criticize, to deliberate about how we should act, and to reach an understanding of ourselves, other people, and the world. (Lakoff and Johnson 1999, pp. 3-4)

Reason is often opposed to sensation, perception, feeling, and desire.

Rationalists see reason as the faculty by which fundamental truths are intuitively apprehended. These fundamental truths are the causes or "reasons" that things exist or happen. Empiricists, of course, deny the existence of such a faculty.

For Immanuel Kant, reason (Vernunft in Kant's German language) is the power of synthesizing into unity, by means of comprehensive principles, the concepts provided by the intellect (Verstand). The reason which gives a priori principles Kant calls "Pure Reason" (as in his The Critique of Pure Reason), as distinguished from the "Practical Reason" which is specially concerned with the performance of particular actions.

In theology, reason, as distinguished from faith, is the human intelligence exercised upon religious truth whether by way of discovery or by way of explanation. The limits within which reason may be used have been laid down differently in different churches and periods of thought: on the whole, modern Christianity, especially in the Protestant churches, tends to allow to reason a wide field, reserving, however, as the sphere of faith the ultimate (supernatural) truths of theology.

Regardless of how it is conceived, reason has often been seen as a uniquely human trait, which separates us from the other animals.

These days, the idea of reason as an independent faculty of the mind, separate from emotions, and unique to humanity, is under attack from a number of sources. Consider, for example, George Lakoff and Mark Johnson's theories about the "embodied mind". (See the Lakoff article for more information.)

References