Revision as of 17:45, 30 September 2017 view sourceFlightTime (talk | contribs)Autopatrolled, Extended confirmed users, Page movers, File movers, New page reviewers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers, Template editors157,572 editsm Reverted good faith edits by Royer2356 2017! (talk): Bad link. (Using Twinkle← Previous edit | Revision as of 20:06, 1 October 2017 view source 5.156.150.171 (talk) ←Replaced content with 'time is a fake time Done by hackxor from a school called MEIS Have fun wikipedia U piece of sh.it'Tag: blankingNext edit → | ||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
time is a fake time | |||
{{About||the concept in physics|Time in physics|the magazine|Time (magazine)|other uses}} | |||
{{Use dmy dates|date=November 2012}} | |||
{{Time sidebar}} | |||
{{Classical mechanics}} | |||
] in an ] can be used to measure the passage of time. It also concretely represents the ] as being between the ] and the ].]] | |||
'''Time''' is the indefinite continued ] of ] and ] that occur in apparently ] succession from the ] through the ] to the ].<ref> | |||
{{cite web |url=http://oxforddictionaries.com/definition/time |title=Oxford Dictionaries:Time |quote=The indefinite continued progress of existence and events in the past, present, and future regarded as a whole |date=2011 |publisher=Oxford University Press |accessdate=18 May 2017}} | |||
</ref><ref name=DefRefs02/><ref> | |||
{{Cite journal | url=http://ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=time | title=Time | work=The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language | edition=Fourth | publisher=Houghton Mifflin Company | date=2011 | quote=A nonspatial continuum in which events occur in apparently irreversible succession from the past through the present to the future. {{inconsistent citations}}}} | |||
</ref> Time is a component quantity of various ]s used to ] events, to compare the duration of events or the intervals between them, and to ] ] of ] in ] or in the ] ].<ref> | |||
the measured or measurable period during which an action, process, or condition exists or continues : duration; a nonspatial continuum which is measured in terms of events that succeed one another from past through present to future | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
Compact ] A limited stretch or space of continued existence, as the interval between two successive events or acts, or the period through which an action, condition, or state continues. (1971). | |||
</ref><ref name=DefRefs01/><ref name=Poidevin/> Time is often referred to as a '''fourth dimension''', along with ] ]s.<ref>"Newton did for time what the Greek geometers did for space, idealized it into an exactly measurable dimension." ''About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution'', Paul Davies, p. 31, Simon & Schuster, 1996, {{isbn|978-0684818221}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Done by hackxor from a school called MEIS | |||
Time has long been an important subject of study in ], ], and ], but defining it in a manner applicable to all fields without ] has consistently eluded scholars.<ref name=DefRefs02/><ref name=DefRefs01/><ref name=Poidevin/><ref name=Carroll2009> | |||
{{cite book | |||
|url=https://books.google.com/?id=Uak1wtcXrjwC | |||
|title=From Eternity to Here: The Quest for the Ultimate Theory of Time | |||
|author=Sean M Carroll |date=2009 |publisher=Dutton | |||
|isbn=978-0-525-95133-9 }} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
Adam Frank, ''Cosmology and Culture at the Twilight of the Big Bang'', "the time we imagine for the cosmos and the time we imagined into the human experience turn out to be woven so tightly together that we have lost the ability to see each of them for what it is." p. xv, Free Press, 2011, {{isbn|978-1439169599}} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
St. Augustine, ''Confessions'', Simon & Brown, 2012, {{isbn|978-1613823262}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Nevertheless, diverse fields such as business, ], sports, the sciences, and the ] all incorporate some notion of time into their respective ].<ref name=MLB> | |||
{{cite web | |||
| last=Official Baseball Rules | |||
| first=2011 Edition | |||
| title=Rules 8.03 and 8.04 | |||
| publisher=Major League Baseball | |||
| date=2011 | |||
| url=http://mlb.mlb.com/mlb/downloads/y2011/Official_Baseball_Rules.pdf | |||
| format=Free PDF download | |||
| quote=Rule 8.03 Such preparatory pitches shall not consume more than one minute of time...Rule 8.04 When the bases are unoccupied, the pitcher shall deliver the ball to the batter within 12 seconds...The 12-second timing starts when the pitcher is in possession of the ball and the batter is in the box, alert to the pitcher. The timing stops when the pitcher releases the ball. | |||
| accessdate=18 May 2017}} | |||
</ref><ref name=guiness> | |||
{{cite web | |||
| title=Guinness Book of Baseball World Records | |||
| publisher=Guinness World Records, Ltd. | |||
| url=http://www.baseball-almanac.com/recbooks/rb_guin.shtml | |||
| quote=The record for the fastest time for circling the bases is 13.3 seconds, set by Evar Swanson at Columbus, Ohio in 1932...The greatest reliably recorded speed at which a baseball has been pitched is 100.9 mph by Lynn Nolan Ryan (California Angels) at Anaheim Stadium in California on 20 August 1974. | accessdate=7 July 2012}} | |||
</ref><ref name=Zeigler> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| last=Zeigler | |||
| first=Kenneth | |||
| title=Getting organized at work : 24 lessons to set goals, establish priorities, and manage your time | |||
| publisher=McGraw-Hill | |||
| date=2008 | |||
| url=https://books.google.com/?id=acPPD6lCCxcC&printsec=frontcover&dq=Getting+organized+at+work+:+24+lessons+to+set+goals,+establish+priorities,+and+manage+your+time#v=onepage&q=Getting%20organized%20at%20work%20%3A%2024%20lessons%20to%20set%20goals%2C%20establish%20priorities%2C%20and%20manage%20your%20time&f=false | |||
| isbn=9780071591386 | |||
| mr= | |||
| zbl= | |||
| jfm=}} 108 pages. | |||
</ref> | |||
Have fun wikipedia U piece of sh.it | |||
Two contrasting viewpoints on time divide prominent ]s. | |||
One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the ]—a ] independent of events, in which events occur in ]. | |||
] subscribed to this ] view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as ].<ref name=Rynasiewicz> | |||
{{cite web | |||
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/newton-stm/ | |||
|title=Newton's Views on Space, Time, and Motion | |||
|date=12 August 2004 | |||
|first=Robert : Johns Hopkins University | |||
|last=Rynasiewicz | |||
|publisher=Stanford University | |||
|work=] | |||
|quote=Newton did not regard space and time as genuine substances (as are, paradigmatically, bodies and minds), but rather as real entities with their own manner of existence as necessitated by God's existence ... To paraphrase: Absolute, true, and mathematical time, from its own nature, passes equably without relation to anything external, and thus without reference to any change or way of measuring of time (e.g., the hour, day, month, or year). | |||
|accessdate=5 February 2012}} | |||
</ref><ref name=Markosian > | |||
{{cite encyclopedia | |||
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/time/#3 | |||
|last=Markosian | |||
|first=Ned | |||
|title=Time | |||
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2002 Edition) | |||
|editor=Edward N. Zalta | |||
|quote=The opposing view, normally referred to either as “Platonism with Respect to Time” or as “Absolutism with Respect to Time”, has been defended by Plato, Newton, and others. On this view, time is like an empty container into which events may be placed; but it is a container that exists independently of whether or not anything is placed in it. | |||
|accessdate=23 September 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
The opposing view is that ''time'' does not refer to any kind of "container" that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead part of a fundamental intellectual structure (together with ] and ]) within which humans sequence and compare events. This second view, in the tradition of ]<ref name=Burnham> | |||
{{cite web | |||
|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/leib-met/#H7 | |||
|title=Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) Metaphysics – 7. Space, Time, and Indiscernibles | |||
|first=Douglas : Staffordshire University | |||
|last=Burnham | |||
|date=2006 | |||
|work=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy | |||
|quote=First of all, Leibniz finds the idea that space and time might be substances or substance-like absurd (see, for example, "Correspondence with Clarke," Leibniz's Fourth Paper, §8ff). In short, an empty space would be a substance with no properties; it will be a substance that even God cannot modify or destroy.... That is, space and time are internal or intrinsic features of the complete concepts of things, not extrinsic.... Leibniz's view has two major implications. First, there is no absolute location in either space or time; location is always the situation of an object or event relative to other objects and events. Second, space and time are not in themselves real (that is, not substances). Space and time are, rather, ideal. Space and time are just metaphysically illegitimate ways of perceiving certain virtual relations between substances. They are phenomena or, strictly speaking, illusions (although they are illusions that are well-founded upon the internal properties of substances).... It is sometimes convenient to think of space and time as something "out there," over and above the entities and their relations to each other, but this convenience must not be confused with reality. Space is nothing but the order of co-existent objects; time nothing but the order of successive events. This is usually called a relational theory of space and time. | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and ],<ref name=Mattey> | |||
{{cite web | |||
|url=http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIMELEC.HTM | |||
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20050314201600/http://www-philosophy.ucdavis.edu/mattey/kant/TIMELEC.HTM | |||
|dead-url=yes | |||
|archive-date=14 March 2005 | |||
|title=Critique of Pure Reason, Lecture notes: Philosophy 175 UC Davis | |||
|date=22 January 1997 | |||
|last=Mattey | |||
|first=G. J. : UC Davis | |||
|quote=What is correct in the Leibnizian view was its anti-metaphysical stance. Space and time do not exist in and of themselves, but in some sense are the product of the way we represent things. The are ideal, though not in the sense in which Leibniz thought they are ideal (figments of the imagination). The ideality of space is its mind-dependence: it is only a condition of sensibility.... Kant concluded ... "absolute space is not an object of outer sensation; it is rather a fundamental concept which first of all makes possible all such outer sensation."...Much of the argumentation pertaining to space is applicable, ''mutatis mutandis'', to time, so I will not rehearse the arguments. As space is the form of outer intuition, so time is the form of inner intuition.... Kant claimed that time is real, it is "the real form of inner intuition." | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011 | |||
|df= | |||
}} | |||
</ref><ref name=McCormick> | |||
{{cite web | |||
|title=Immanuel Kant (1724–1804) Metaphysics: 4. Kant's Transcendental Idealism | |||
|url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/kantmeta/#H4 | |||
|work=The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy | |||
|first=Matt : California State University, Sacramento | |||
|last=McCormick | |||
|date=2006 | |||
|quote=Time, Kant argues, is also necessary as a form or condition of our intuitions of objects. The idea of time itself cannot be gathered from experience because succession and simultaneity of objects, the phenomena that would indicate the passage of time, would be impossible to represent if we did not already possess the capacity to represent objects in time.... Another way to put the point is to say that the fact that the mind of the knower makes the ''a priori'' contribution does not mean that space and time or the categories are mere figments of the imagination. Kant is an empirical realist about the world we experience; we can know objects as they appear to us. He gives a robust defense of science and the study of the natural world from his argument about the mind's role in making nature. All discursive, rational beings must conceive of the physical world as spatially and temporally unified, he argues. | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
holds that ''time'' is neither an event nor a thing, and thus is not itself measurable nor can it be travelled. | |||
] is unambiguously operationally defined as "what a ] reads".<ref name=DefRefs01/><ref name=Burnham/><ref>{{cite book |title=Process instruments and controls handbook |edition=3 |first1=Douglas M. |last1=Considine |first2=Glenn D. |last2=Considine |publisher=McGraw-Hill |year=1985 |isbn=0-07-012436-1 |pages=18–61 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kt1UAAAAMAAJ}}</ref> See ]. Time is one of the seven fundamental ] in both the ] and ]. Time is used to define other quantities—such as ]—so defining time in terms of such quantities would result in circularity of definition.<ref name="TrialogueP3">Duff, Okun, Veneziano, ''ibid.'' p. 3. "There is no well established terminology for the fundamental constants of Nature. ... The absence of accurately defined terms or the uses (i.e., actually misuses) of ill-defined terms lead to confusion and proliferation of wrong statements." | |||
</ref> | |||
An ] of time, wherein one says that observing a certain number of repetitions of one or another standard cyclical event (such as the passage of a free-swinging pendulum) constitutes one standard unit such as the ], is highly useful in the conduct of both advanced experiments and everyday affairs of life. The operational definition leaves aside the question whether there is something called time, apart from the counting activity just mentioned, that flows and that can be measured. Investigations of a single continuum called ] bring questions about space into questions about time, questions that have their roots in the works of early students of ]. | |||
Temporal measurement has occupied scientists and ], and was a prime motivation in ] and ]. Periodic events and periodic motion have long served as standards for units of time. Examples include the apparent motion of the sun across the sky, the phases of the moon, the swing of a pendulum, and the beat of a heart. Currently, the international unit of time, the ], is defined by measuring the ] ] of ] atoms (see ]). Time is also of significant social importance, having economic value ("]") as well as personal value, due to an ] of the limited time in each day and in ]. | |||
== Temporal measurement and history == | |||
Generally speaking, methods of temporal measurement, or ], take two distinct forms: the ], a mathematical tool for organising intervals of time,<ref name="Richards">{{cite book |title=Mapping Time: The Calendar and its History |last=Richards |first=E. G. |date=1998 |pages=3–5 |publisher=]}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and the ], a physical mechanism that counts the passage of time. In day-to-day life, the clock is consulted for periods less than a day whereas the calendar is consulted for periods longer than a day. Increasingly, personal electronic devices display both calendars and clocks simultaneously. The number (as on a clock dial or calendar) that marks the occurrence of a specified event as to hour or date is obtained by counting from a fiducial epoch—a central reference point. | |||
=== History of the calendar === | |||
{{Main article|Calendar}} | |||
Artifacts from the ] suggest that the moon was used to reckon time as early as 6,000 years ago.<ref name="Rudgley">{{cite book |title=The Lost Civilizations of the Stone Age |last=Rudgley |first=Richard |authorlink=Richard Rudgley |date=1999 |pages=86–105 |publisher=Simon & Schuster |location=New York}} | |||
</ref> | |||
]s were among the first to appear, either 12 or 13 ]s (either 354 or 384 days). Without ] to add days or months to some years, seasons quickly drift in a calendar based solely on twelve lunar months. ]s have a thirteenth month added to some years to make up for the difference between a full year (now known to be about 365.24 days) and a year of just twelve lunar months. The numbers twelve and thirteen came to feature prominently in many cultures, at least partly due to this relationship of months to years. Other early forms of calendars originated in Mesoamerica, particularly in ancient Mayan civilization. These calendars were religiously and astronomically based, with 18 months in a year and 20 days in a month, plus five epagemonal days at the end of the year.<ref>Van Stone, Mark. "The Maya Long Count Calendar: An Introduction." Archaeoastronomy 24.(2011): 8-11. Academic Search Complete. Web. 20 Feb. 2016.</ref> | |||
The reforms of ] in 45 BC put the ] on a ]. This ] was faulty in that its intercalation still allowed the astronomical ]s and ]es to advance against it by about 11 minutes per year. ] introduced a correction in 1582; the ] was only slowly adopted by different nations over a period of centuries, but it is now the most commonly used calendar around the world, by far. | |||
During the French Revolution, a new clock and calendar were invented in attempt to de-Christianize time and create a more rational system in order to replace the Gregorian calendar. The French Republican Calendar's days consisted of ten hours of a hundred minutes of a hundred seconds, which marked a deviation from the 12-based ] system used in many other devices by many cultures. The system was later abolished in 1806.<ref>"French Republican Calendar | Chronology." Encyclopædia Britannica Online. Encyclopædia Britannica, n.d. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.</ref> | |||
===History of time measurement devices=== | |||
] in ]]] | |||
] | |||
{{Main article|History of timekeeping devices}} | |||
{{See also|Clock}} | |||
A large variety of ] have been invented to measure time. The study of these devices is called ]. | |||
An ]ian device that dates to c.1500 BC, similar in shape to a bent ], measured the passage of time from the shadow cast by its crossbar on a nonlinear rule. The T was oriented eastward in the mornings. At ], the device was turned around so that it could cast its shadow in the evening direction.<ref>Barnett, Jo Ellen ''Time's Pendulum: The Quest to Capture Time—from Sundials to Atomic Clocks'' Plenum, 1998 {{isbn|0-306-45787-3}} p.28 | |||
</ref> | |||
A ] uses a ] to cast a shadow on a set of markings calibrated to the ]. The position of the shadow marks the hour in ]. The idea to separate the day into smaller parts is credited to Egyptians because of their sundials, which operated on a duodecimal system. The importance of the number 12 is due the number of lunar cycles in a year and the number of stars used to count the passage of night.<ref>Lombardi, Michael A. "Why Is a Minute Divided into 60 Seconds, an Hour into 60 Minutes, Yet There Are Only 24 Hours in a Day?" Scientific American. Springer Nature, 5 Mar. 2007. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.</ref> | |||
The most precise timekeeping device of the ] was the ], or ''clepsydra'', one of which was found in the tomb of Egyptian pharaoh ] (1525–1504 BC). They could be used to measure the hours even at night, but required manual upkeep to replenish the flow of water. The ] and the people from ] (southeastern Mesopotamia) regularly maintained timekeeping records as an essential part of their astronomical observations. Arab inventors and engineers in particular made improvements on the use of water clocks up to the Middle Ages.<ref>Barnett, ''ibid'', p.37 | |||
</ref> | |||
In the 11th century, ] and ] invented the first mechanical clocks driven by an ] mechanism. | |||
], 2007 ]] | |||
The ] uses the flow of sand to measure the flow of time. They were used in navigation. ] used 18 glasses on each ship for his circumnavigation of the globe (1522).<ref>Laurence Bergreen, ''Over the Edge of the World: Magellan's Terrifying Circumnavigation of the Globe'', HarperCollins Publishers, 2003, hardcover 480 pages, {{isbn|0-06-621173-5}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Incense sticks and candles were, and are, commonly used to measure time in temples and churches across the globe. Waterclocks, and later, mechanical clocks, were used to mark the events of the abbeys and monasteries of the Middle Ages. ] (1292–1336), abbot of St. Alban's abbey, famously built a mechanical clock as an astronomical ] about 1330.<ref>North, J. (2004) ''God's Clockmaker: Richard of Wallingford and the Invention of Time''. Oxbow Books. {{isbn|1-85285-451-0}} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
Watson, E (1979) "The St Albans Clock of Richard of Wallingford". ''Antiquarian Horology'' 372–384. | |||
</ref> | |||
Great advances in accurate time-keeping were made by ] and especially ] with the invention of pendulum driven clocks along with the invention of the minute hand by Jost Burgi.<ref name="Clocks 2016">"History of Clocks." About.com Inventors. About.com, n.d. Web. 21 Feb. 2016.</ref> | |||
The English word ] probably comes from the Middle Dutch word ''klocke'' which, in turn, derives from the medieval Latin word ''clocca'', which ultimately derives from Celtic and is cognate with French, Latin, and German words that mean ]. The passage of the hours at sea were marked by bells, and denoted the time (see ]). The hours were marked by bells in abbeys as well as at sea. | |||
]s, such as this one unveiled in 2004, are expected to greatly improve ] location.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/miniclock.cfm |title=NIST Unveils Chip-Scale Atomic Clock |date=27 August 2004 |accessdate=9 June 2011}}</ref>]] | |||
Clocks can range from ]es, to more exotic varieties such as the ]. They can be driven by a variety of means, including gravity, springs, and various forms of electrical power, and regulated by a variety of means such as a ]. | |||
Alarm clocks first appeared in ancient Greece around 250 BC with a water clock that would set off a whistle. This idea was later mechanized by Levi Hutchins and Seth E. Thomas.<ref name="Clocks 2016"/> | |||
A ] is a portable timekeeper that meets certain precision standards. Initially, the term was used to refer to the ], a timepiece used to determine ] by means of ], a precision firstly achieved by ]. More recently, the term has also been applied to the ], a watch that meets precision standards set by the Swiss agency ]. | |||
The most accurate timekeeping devices are ]s, which are accurate to seconds in many millions of years,<ref>{{cite news |url=http://www.canada.com/vancouversun/news/story.html?id=e24ccfa7-44eb-40b7-8b67-daf8263569ff |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120211190407/http://www.canada.com/vancouversun/news/story.html?id=e24ccfa7-44eb-40b7-8b67-daf8263569ff |dead-url=yes |archive-date=11 February 2012 |title=New atomic clock can keep time for 200 million years: Super-precise instruments vital to deep space navigation |date=16 February 2008 |work=Vancouver Sun |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and are used to calibrate other clocks and timekeeping instruments. | |||
Atomic clocks use the frequency of ]s in certain atoms to measure the second. One of the most common atoms used is ], most modern atomic clocks probe caesium with microwaves to determine the frequency of these electron vibrations.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://www.nist.gov/public_affairs/releases/n99-22.cf |title=NIST-F1 Cesium Fountain Clock |accessdate=24 July 2015}}</ref> Since 1967, the International System of Measurements bases its unit of time, the second, on the properties of ] atoms. ] defines the second as 9,192,631,770 cycles of the radiation that corresponds to the transition between two electron spin energy levels of the ground state of the <sup>133</sup>Cs atom. | |||
Today, the ] in coordination with the ] can be used to synchronize timekeeping systems across the globe. | |||
{{clear right}} | |||
In medieval philosophical writings, the '''atom''' was a unit of time referred to as the smallest possible division of time. The earliest known occurrence in English is in ]'s ''Enchiridion'' (a science text) of 1010–1012,<ref>{{cite web|title=Byrhtferth of Ramsey|year= 2008|publisher='']''|accessdate=15 September 2008|url=http://search.eb.com/eb/article-9438957}} | |||
</ref> where it was defined as 1/564 of a ''momentum'' (1½ minutes),<ref>"atom", ], Draft Revision September 2008 (contains relevant citations from Byrhtferth's ''Enchiridion'')</ref> and thus equal to 15/94 of a second. It was used in the '']'', the process of calculating the date of ]. | |||
{{As of| May 2010}}, the smallest time interval uncertainty in direct measurements is on the order of 12 ]s (1.2 × 10<sup>−17</sup> seconds), about 3.7 × 10<sup>26</sup> ]s.<ref>{{cite web | url=http://www.physorg.com/news192909576.html | title=12 attoseconds is the world record for shortest controllable time | date=12 May 2010 | accessdate=19 April 2012}} | |||
</ref> | |||
=== Units of time === | |||
{{See also|Time (Orders of magnitude)|Unit of time#List}} | |||
The ] (s) is the ] base unit. A ] (min) is 60 seconds in length, and an ] is 60 minutes in length. A ] is 24 hours or 86400 seconds in length. | |||
== Definitions and standards == | |||
The Mean ] system defines the second as 1/86,400 of the mean ], which is the year-average of the solar day. The solar day is the time interval between two successive solar ]s, i.e., the time interval between two successive passages of the Sun across the local meridian. The local meridian is an imaginary line that runs from celestial north pole to celestial south pole passing directly over the head of the observer. At the local meridian the Sun reaches it's highest point on it's daily arc across the sky. | |||
In 1874 the British Association for the Advancement of Science introduced the CGS (centimetre/gramme/second system) combining fundamental units of length, mass and time. The second is "elastic", because tidal friction is slowing the earth's rotation rate. For use in calculating ephemerides of celestial motion, therefore, in 1952 astronomers introduced the "ephemeris second", currently defined as | |||
{{quote|the fraction 1/31,556,925.9747 of the ] for 1900 January 0 at 12 hours ].}}<ref>''Whitaker's Almanac 2013'' (ed. Ruth Northey), London 2012, p 1131, {{isbn|978-1-4081-7207-0}}.</ref> | |||
{{clear left}} | |||
The CGS system has been superseded by the ''Système international''. The ] for time is the ] ]. The ], which incorporates the SI, also defines larger units of time equal to fixed integer multiples of one second (1 s), such as the ], ] and ]. These are not part of the SI, but may be used alongside the SI. Other units of time such as the ] and the ] are not equal to fixed multiples of 1 s, and instead exhibit significant variations in duration.<ref name="si_units">{{cite book|title=The International System of Units (SI), 7th Edition |url=http://www1.bipm.org/utils/en/pdf/si-brochure.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20040427205458/http://www1.bipm.org/utils/en/pdf/si-brochure.pdf |dead-url=yes |archive-date=27 April 2004 |format=PDF |date=1998 |author=Organisation Intergouvernementale de la Convention du Métre |accessdate=9 April 2011 |df= }} | |||
</ref> | |||
The official SI definition of the second is as follows:<ref name="si_units"/><ref name="second">{{cite web |title=Base unit definitions: Second |url=http://physics.nist.gov/cuu/Units/second.html |publisher=] |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
{{quote|The second is the duration of 9,192,631,770 periods of the radiation corresponding to the transition between the two hyperfine levels of the ground state of the ] 133 atom.}} | |||
{{clear left}} | |||
At its 1997 meeting, the CIPM affirmed that this definition refers to a caesium atom in its ground state at a temperature of 0 K.<ref name="si_units"/> | |||
The current definition of the second, coupled with the current definition of the metre, is based on the ], which affirms our spacetime to be a ]. The definition of the second in mean solar time, however, is unchanged. | |||
=== World time === | |||
While in theory, the concept of a single worldwide universal time-scale may have been conceived of many centuries ago, in practicality the technical ability to create and maintain such a time-scale did not become possible until the mid-19th century. The timescale adopted was Greenwich Mean Time, created in 1847. A few countries have replaced it with Coordinated Universal Time, ]. | |||
==== History of the development of UTC ==== | |||
With the advent of the ], a greater understanding and agreement on the nature of time itself became increasingly necessary and helpful. In 1847 in Britain, ] (GMT) was first created for use by the British railways, the British navy, and the British shipping industry. Using telescopes, GMT was calibrated to the ] at the ] in the UK. | |||
As international commerce continued to increase throughout Europe, in order to achieve a more efficiently functioning modern society, an agreed upon, and highly accurate '''''international standard''''' of time measurement became necessary. In order to find or determine such a time-standard, three steps had to be followed: | |||
# An internationally agreed upon time-standard had to be defined. | |||
# This new time-standard then had to be consistently and accurately measured. | |||
# The new time-standard then had to be freely shared and distributed around the world. | |||
The development of what is now known as ] came about historically as an effort which first began as a collaboration between 41 nations, officially agreed to and signed at the ], in Washington D.C. in 1884. At this conference, the local mean solar time at the Royal Observatory, Greenwich in ] was chosen to define the "universal day", counted from 0 hours at Greenwich mean midnight. This agreed with the civil Greenwich Mean Time used on the island of Great Britain since 1847. In contrast astronomical GMT began at mean noon, i.e. astronomical day ''X'' began at noon of civil day ''X''. The purpose of this was to keep one night's observations under one date. The civil system was adopted as of 0 hours (civil) 1 January 1925. Nautical GMT began 24 hours before astronomical GMT, at least until 1805 in the ], but persisted much later elsewhere because it was mentioned at the 1884 conference. In 1884, the Greenwich meridian was used for two - thirds of all charts and maps as their ].{{sfn|Howse|1997|pp= 133-137}} | |||
Among the 41 nations represented at the conference, the advanced time-technologies that had already come into use in Britain were fundamental components of the agreed upon method of arriving at a universal and agreed upon international time. In 1928 Greenwich Mean Time was rebranded for scientific purposes by the ] as ] (UT). This was to avoid confusion with the previous system where the day had begun at noon. As the general public had always begun the day at midnight the timescale continued to be presented to them as Greenwich Mean Time. By 1956, universal time had been split into various versions - UT2, which smoothed for polar motion and seasonal effects, was presented to the public as Greenwich Mean Time. Later, UT1 (which smooths only for polar motion) became the default form of UT used by astronomers and hence the form used in navigation, sunrise and sunset and moonrise and moonset tables where the name Greenwich Mean Time continues to be employed. Greenwich Mean Time is also the preferred method of describing the timescale used by legislators. Even to the present day, UT is still based on an international telescopic system. Observations at the Greenwich Observatory itself ceased in 1954, though the location is still used as the basis for the coordinate system. Because the rotational period of Earth is not perfectly constant, the duration of a second would vary if calibrated to a telescope-based standard like GMT, where the second is defined as 1/86 400 of the mean solar day. | |||
For the better part of the first century following the "International Meridian Conference," until 1960, the methods and definitions of time-keeping that had been laid out at the conference proved to be adequate to meet time tracking needs of science. Still, with the advent of the "electronic revolution" in the latter half of the 20th century, the technologies that had been available at the time of the Convention of the Metre proved to be in need of further refinement in order to meet the needs of the ever-increasing precision that the "electronic revolution" had begun to require. | |||
==== The ephemeris second ==== | |||
An invariable second (the "ephemeris second") had been defined, use of which removed the errors in ephemerides resulting from the use of the variable mean solar second as the time argument. In 1960 this ephemeris second was made the basis of the "coordinated universal time" which was being derived from atomic clocks. It is a specified fraction of the mean tropical year as at 1900 and, being based on historical telescope observations, corresponds roughly to the mean solar second of the early nineteenth century.<ref name="USNO"> | |||
{{cite web | |||
|title=Leap Seconds | |||
|publisher=Time Service Department, ] | |||
|url=http://tycho.usno.navy.mil/leapsec.html | |||
|accessdate=22 November 2015 | |||
|deadurl=yes | |||
|archiveurl=https://www.webcitation.org/666iH0vl1?url=http://tycho.usno.navy.mil/leapsec.html | |||
|archivedate=12 March 2012 | |||
|df= | |||
}} | |||
</ref> | |||
==== The SI second ==== | |||
In 1967 a further step was taken with the introduction of the SI second, essentially the ephemeris second as measured by atomic clocks and formally defined in atomic terms.<ref name=mark58> | |||
{{cite journal | |||
|author=W Markowitz, RG Hall, L Essen, JVL Parry | |||
|year=1958 | |||
|url=http://www.leapsecond.com/history/1958-PhysRev-v1-n3-Markowitz-Hall-Essen-Parry.pdf | |||
|title=Frequency of cesium in terms of ephemeris time | |||
|journal=] | |||
|volume=1 |issue= 3|pages=105–107 | |||
|doi=10.1103/PhysRevLett.1.105 | |||
|bibcode=1958PhRvL...1..105M | |||
|last2=Hall | |||
|last3=Essen | |||
|last4=Parry | |||
}}</ref> | |||
The SI second (Standard Internationale second) is based directly on the measurement of the atomic-clock observation of the frequency oscillation of caesium atoms. It is the basis of all atomic timescales, e.g. coordinated universal time, GPS time, International Atomic Time, etc. Atomic clocks do not measure nuclear decay rates, which is a common misconception, but rather measure a certain natural vibrational frequency of caesium-133.<ref> {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150223231150/http://tycho.usno.navy.mil/cesium.html |date=23 February 2015 }} USNO, downloaded 28 June 2016.</ref> Coordinated universal time is subject to one constraint which does not affect the other atomic timescales. As it has been adopted as the civil timescale by some countries (most countries have opted to retain mean solar time) it is not permitted to deviate from GMT by more than 0.9 second. This is achieved by the occasional insertion of a leap second. | |||
==== Current application of UTC ==== | |||
Most countries use mean solar time. Australia, Canada (Quebec only), Colombia, France, Germany, New Zealand, Papua New Guinea (Bougainville only), Paraguay, Portugal, Switzerland, the United States and Venezuela use UTC. However, UTC is widely used by the scientific community in countries where mean solar time is official. ] is based on the SI second, which was first defined in 1967, and is based on the use of atomic clocks. Some other less used but closely related time-standards include ], ], and ]. | |||
Between 1967 and 1971, UTC was periodically adjusted by fractional amounts of a second in order to adjust and refine for variations in mean solar time, with which it is aligned. After 1 January 1972, UTC time has been defined as being offset from atomic time by a whole number of seconds, changing only when a ] is added to keep radio - controlled clocks synchronized with the rotation of the Earth. | |||
The ] also broadcasts a very precise time signal worldwide, along with instructions for converting GPS time to UTC. GPS-time is based on, and regularly synchronized with or from, UTC-time. | |||
Earth is split up into a number of ]s. Most time zones are exactly one hour apart, and by convention compute their local time as an offset from GMT. For example, time zones at sea are based on GMT. In many locations (but not at sea) these offsets vary twice yearly due to ] transitions. | |||
=== Time conversions === | |||
These conversions are accurate at the millisecond level for time systems involving earth rotation (UT1 & TT). Conversions between atomic time systems (TAI, GPS, and UTC) are accurate at the microsecond level. | |||
{| class="wikitable" style="text-align:center; font-size:80%" | |||
|- | |||
! System | |||
! Description | |||
! UT1 | |||
! UTC | |||
! TT | |||
! TAI | |||
! GPS | |||
|- | |||
| UT1 | |||
| Mean Solar Time | |||
| UT1 | |||
| UTC = UT1 - DUT1 | |||
| TT = UT1 + 32.184 s + LS - DUT1 | |||
| TAI = UT1 - DUT1 + LS | |||
| GPS = UT1 - DUT1 + LS - 19 s | |||
|- | |||
| UTC | |||
| Civil Time | |||
| UT1 = UTC + DUT1 | |||
| UTC | |||
| TT = UTC + 32.184 s + LS | |||
| TAI = UTC + LS | |||
| GPS = UTC + LS - 19 s | |||
|- | |||
| TT | |||
| Terrestrial (Ephemeris) Time | |||
| UT1 = TT - 32.184 s - LS + DUT1 | |||
| UTC = TT - 32.184 s - LS | |||
| TT | |||
| TAI = TT - 32.184 s | |||
| GPS = TT - 51.184 s | |||
|- | |||
| TAI | |||
| Atomic Time | |||
| UT1 = TAI + DUT1 - LS | |||
| UTC = TAI - LS | |||
| TT = TAI + 32.184 s | |||
| TAI | |||
| GPS = TAI - 19 s | |||
|- | |||
| GPS | |||
| GPS Time | |||
| UT1 = GPS + DUT1 - LS + 19 s | |||
| UTC = GPS - LS + 19 s | |||
| TT = GPS + 51.184 s | |||
| TAI = GPS + 19 s | |||
| GPS | |||
|} | |||
Definitions: | |||
# LS = TAI - UTC = Leap Seconds from http://maia.usno.navy.mil/ser7/tai-utc.dat | |||
# DUT1 = UT1 - UTC from http://maia.usno.navy.mil/ser7/ser7.dat or http://maia.usno.navy.mil/search/search.html | |||
=== Sidereal time === | |||
] is the measurement of time relative to a distant star (instead of solar time that is relative to the sun). It is used in astronomy to predict when a star will be overhead. Due to the orbit of the earth around the sun a sidereal day is about 4 minutes (1/366th) less than a solar day. | |||
=== Chronology === | |||
{{Main article|Chronology}} | |||
Another form of time measurement consists of studying the ]. Events in the past can be ordered in a sequence (creating a ]), and can be put into chronological groups (]). One of the most important systems of periodization is the ], which is a system of periodizing the events that shaped the ] and its life. Chronology, periodization, and interpretation of the past are together known as the study of ]. | |||
=== Time-like concepts: terminology === | |||
The term "time" is generally used for many close but different concepts, including: | |||
*]<ref>IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-08</ref> as an object—one point on the time axes. Being an object, it has no value; | |||
*]<ref>IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-010; ISO 80000-3:2006, item 3-7</ref> as an object—part of the time axes limited by two instants. Being an object, it has no value; | |||
*]<ref>IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-012: "mark attributed to an instant by means of a specified time scale</ref> as a quantity characterising an instant. As a quantity, it has a value which may be expressed in a variety of ways, for example "2014-04-26T09:42:36,75" in ] format, or more colloquially such as "today, 9:42 a.m."; | |||
*]<ref>IEC 60050-113:2011, item 113-01-013: "range of a time interval (113-01-10)"</ref> as a quantity characterizing a time interval.<ref>ISO 80000-3:2006, item 3-7</ref> As a quantity, it has a value, such as a number of minutes, or may be described in terms of the quantities (such as times and dates) of its beginning and end. | |||
== Religion == | |||
] shown ] ]] | |||
{{Further information|Time and fate deities}} | |||
=== Linear and cyclical time === | |||
{{See also|Time cycles|Wheel of time}} | |||
Ancient cultures such as ], ], ], and other Native American Tribes - plus the ]ns, ], ], ], ], and others - have a concept of a ]: they regard time as ] and ],{{clarify|How polynomials relate to this|date=February 2014}} consisting of repeating ages that happen to every being of the Universe between birth and extinction.{{citation needed|date=August 2015}} | |||
In general, the Islamic and ] world-view regards time as ]<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| last1 = Rust | |||
| first1 = Eric Charles | |||
| title = Religion, Revelation and Reason | |||
| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=AcSw6GDlLVwC | |||
| publisher = Mercer University Press | |||
| publication-date = 1981 | |||
| page = 60 | |||
| isbn = 9780865540583 | |||
| accessdate = 2015-08-20 | |||
| quote = Profane time, as ] points out, is linear. As man dwelt increasingly in the profane and a sense of history developed, the desire to escape into the sacred began to drop in the background. The myths, tied up with cyclic time, were not so easily operative. So secular man became content with his linear time. He could not return to cyclic time and re-enter sacred space though its myths. Just here, as Eliade sees it, a new religious structure became available. In the Judaeo-Christian religions - Judaism, Christianity, Islam - history is taken seriously, and linear time is accepted. The cyclic time of the primordial mythical consciousness has been transformed into the time of profane man, but the mythical consciousness remains. It has been historicized. The Christian mythos and its accompanying ritual are bound up, for example, with history and center in authentic history, especially the Christ-event. Sacred space, the Transcendent Presence, is thus opened up to secular man because it meets him where he is, in the linear flow of secular time. The Christian myth gives such time a beginning in creation, a center in the Christ-event, and an end in the final consummation. | |||
}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and ]al,<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| editor1-last = Betz | |||
| editor1-first = Hans Dieter | |||
| title = Religion Past & Present: Encyclopedia of Theology and Religion | |||
| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=kjIOAQAAMAAJ | |||
| volume = 4: Dev-Ezr | |||
| edition = 4 | |||
| publisher = Brill | |||
| publication-date = 2008 | |||
| page = 101 | |||
| isbn = 9789004146884 | |||
| accessdate = 2015-08-20 | |||
| quote = God produces a creation with a directional time structure . | |||
}} | |||
</ref> | |||
beginning with the act of ] by ]. The traditional ] view sees time ending, teleologically,<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| last1 = Lundin | |||
| first1 = Roger | |||
| last2 = Thiselton | |||
| first2 = Anthony C. | |||
| author-link2 = Anthony Thiselton | |||
| last3 = Walhout | |||
| first3 = Clarence | |||
| title = The Promise of Hermeneutics | |||
| url = https://books.google.com/books?id=3Y2F6rSq9VMC | |||
| publisher = Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing | |||
| publication-date = 1999 | |||
| page = 121 | |||
| isbn = 9780802846358 | |||
| accessdate = 2015-08-20 | |||
| quote = We need to note the close ties between teleology, eschatology, and utopia. In Christian theology, the understanding of the teleology of particular actions is ultimately related to the teleology of history in general, which is the concern of eschatology. | |||
}} | |||
</ref> | |||
with the ] end of the present order of things, the "]". | |||
In the ] book ], traditionally ascribed to ] (970–928 BC), time (as the Hebrew word עידן, זמן ''`iddan(age, as in "Ice age") zĕman(time)'' is often translated) was traditionally regarded{{by whom|date=August 2015}} as a medium for the passage of ] events.{{citation needed|date=January 2015}} (Another word, زمان" זמן" ''zamān'', meant ''time fit for an event'', and is used as the modern ], ], and ] equivalent to the English word "time".) | |||
{{Clear}} | |||
=== Time in Greek mythology === | |||
The Greek language denotes two distinct principles, ] and ]. The former refers to numeric, or chronological, time. The latter, literally "the right or opportune moment", relates specifically to metaphysical or Divine time. In theology, Kairos is qualitative, as opposed to quantitative.{{citation needed|date=May 2017}} | |||
In Greek mythology, Chronos (Ancient Greek: Χρόνος) is identified as the Personification of Time. His name in Greek means "time" and is alternatively spelled Chronus (Latin spelling) or Khronos. Chronos is usually portrayed as an old, wise man with a long, gray beard, such as "Father Time". Some English words whose etymological root is khronos/chronos include ''chronology'', ''chronometer'', ''chronic'', ''anachronism'', ''synchronise'', and ''chronicle''. | |||
=== Time in Kabbalah === | |||
According to ], "time" is a ]<ref>{{cite book |title=Kabbalah and Modernity: Interpretations, Transformations, Adaptations |first1=Boʿaz |last1=Hus |first2=Marco |last2=Pasi |first3=Kocku |last3=Von Stuckrad |publisher=BRILL |date=2011 |isbn=9004182845 |page= |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=mIGMsLiol7EC}}</ref> and an ].<ref>{{cite book |title=Alef, Mem, Tau: Kabbalistic Musings on Time, Truth, and Death |edition= |first1=Elliot R. |last1=Wolfson |publisher=University of California Press |date=2006 |isbn=0-520-93231-5 |page=111 |url=https://books.google.com/books?hl=en&lr=&id=ozhPY2fcNCcC}} </ref> Both the future and the past are recognised to be combined and simultaneously present. | |||
== Philosophy == | |||
{{Main article|Philosophy of space and time|Temporal finitism}} | |||
Two distinct viewpoints on time divide many prominent philosophers. | |||
One view is that time is part of the fundamental structure of the ], a ] in which events occur in ]. ] subscribed to this ] view, and hence it is sometimes referred to as ].<ref name=Markosian /> | |||
An opposing view is that ''time'' does not refer to any kind of actually existing dimension that events and objects "move through", nor to any entity that "flows", but that it is instead an intellectual concept (together with space and number) that enables humans to sequence and compare events.<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
|title=Research Trends in Geographic Information Science | |||
|first1=Gerhard |last1=Navratil | |||
|publisher=Springer Japan | |||
|date=2009 | |||
|isbn=3-540-88243-X | |||
|page=217 | |||
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=q8w728aa1CkC | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
This second view, in the tradition of ]<ref name="Burnham"/> | |||
and ],<ref name="Mattey"/><ref name="McCormick"/> | |||
holds that space and time "do not exist in and of themselves, but ... are the product of the way we represent things", because we can know objects only as they ] to us. | |||
Furthermore, it may be that there is a ] component to time, but whether or not time itself is "felt", as a sensation, or is a judgment, is a matter of debate.<ref name=DefRefs02> | |||
* {{cite web|url=http://www.yourdictionary.com/time |title=Webster's New World College Dictionary |date=2010 |quote=1.indefinite, unlimited duration in which things are considered as happening in the past, present, or future; every moment there has ever been or ever will be… a system of measuring duration 2.the period between two events or during which something exists, happens, or acts; measured or measurable interval |accessdate=9 April 2011 }} | |||
* {{cite web|url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=The American Heritage Stedman's Medical Dictionary |date=2002 |quote=A duration or relation of events expressed in terms of past, present, and future, and measured in units such as minutes, hours, days, months, or years. |accessdate=9 April 2011 }} | |||
* {{cite web|url=http://www.collinslanguage.com/results.aspx?context=3&reversed=False&action=define&homonym=-1&text=time |title=Collins Language.com |publisher=HarperCollins |date=2011 |quote=1. The continuous passage of existence in which events pass from a state of potentiality in the future, through the present, to a state of finality in the past. 2. ''physics'' a quantity measuring duration, usually with reference to a periodic process such as the rotation of the earth or the frequency of electromagnetic radiation emitted from certain atoms. In classical mechanics, time is absolute in the sense that the time of an event is independent of the observer. According to the theory of relativity it depends on the observer's frame of reference. Time is considered as a fourth coordinate required, along with three spatial coordinates, to specify an event. |accessdate=18 December 2011 |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20111002190630/http://www.collinslanguage.com/results.aspx?context=3&reversed=False&action=define&homonym=-1&text=time |archivedate=2 October 2011 |df= }} | |||
* {{cite web|url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=The American Heritage Science Dictionary @dictionary.com |date=2002 |quote=1. A continuous, measurable quantity in which events occur in a sequence proceeding from the past through the present to the future. 2a. An interval separating two points of this quantity; a duration. 2b. A system or reference frame in which such intervals are measured or such quantities are calculated. |accessdate=9 April 2011 }} | |||
* {{cite web|url=http://scienceworld.wolfram.com/physics/Time.html |title=Eric Weisstein's World of Science |date=2007 |quote=A quantity used to specify the order in which events occurred and measure the amount by which one event preceded or followed another. In special relativity, ct (where c is the speed of light and t is time), plays the role of a fourth dimension. |accessdate=9 April 2011 }} | |||
</ref><ref name=DefRefs01> | |||
* {{cite web |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/time/ |title=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=2010 |quote=Time is what clocks measure. We use time to place events in sequence one after the other, and we use time to compare how long events last... Among philosophers of physics, the most popular short answer to the question "What is physical time?" is that it is not a substance or object but rather a special system of relations among instantaneous events. This working definition is offered by Adolf Grünbaum who applies the contemporary mathematical theory of continuity to physical processes, and he says time is a linear continuum of instants and is a distinguished one-dimensional sub-space of four-dimensional spacetime. |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
* {{cite web |url=http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/time?r=66 |title=Dictionary.com Unabridged, based on Random House Dictionary |date=2010 |quote=1. the system of those sequential relations that any event has to any other, as past, present, or future; indefinite and continuous duration regarded as that in which events succeed one another.... 3. (sometimes initial capital letter) a system or method of measuring or reckoning the passage of time: mean time; apparent time; Greenwich Time. 4. a limited period or interval, as between two successive events: a long time.... 14. a particular or definite point in time, as indicated by a clock: What time is it? ... 18. an indefinite, frequently prolonged period or duration in the future: Time will tell if what we have done here today was right. |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
* {{cite book | url=https://books.google.com/?id=HrHvAAAAMAAJ&q=%22time+is+what+clocks+measure%22&dq=%22time+is+what+clocks+measure%22 | title=Physics | |||
| first1=Donald G. | last1=Ivey | first2=J.N.P. |last2=Hume | |||
| volume=1 | page=65 | date=1974 | |||
| publisher=Ronald Press | |||
| quote=Our operational definition of time is that time is what clocks measure.}} | |||
</ref><ref name=Poidevin> | |||
{{cite encyclopedia | |||
|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience | |||
|title=The Experience and Perception of Time | |||
|last=Le Poidevin | |||
|first=Robin | |||
|date=Winter 2004 | |||
|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | |||
|editor=Edward N. Zalta | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
|last=Carrol, Sean | |||
| first=Chapter One, Section Two, Plume, 2010 | |||
| title=From Eternity to Here | |||
| isbn=978-0452296541 | |||
| quote=As human beings we 'feel' the passage of time.}} | |||
</ref><ref name=lehar> | |||
Lehar, Steve. (2000). , ''Consciousness and Cognition''. | |||
</ref> | |||
The '']'', the earliest texts on ] and ] dating back to the late ], describe ancient ], in which the ] goes through repeated cycles of creation, destruction and rebirth, with each cycle lasting 4,320 million years.<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
|title=Who needs the past?: indigenous values and archaeology | |||
|edition=2nd | |||
|first1=Robert |last1=Layton | |||
|publisher=Routledge | |||
|date=1994 | |||
|isbn=0-415-09558-1 | |||
|page=7 | |||
|accessdate=9 April 2011 | |||
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7TPIDL9RdsoC}}, | |||
</ref> | |||
] ], including ] and ], wrote essays on the nature of time.<ref>Dagobert Runes, ''Dictionary of Philosophy'', p. 318 | |||
</ref> | |||
], in the ], identified time with the period of motion of the heavenly bodies. ], in Book IV of his ] defined time as 'number of movement in respect of the before and after'.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://classics.mit.edu//Aristotle/physics.4.iv.html |title=Physics by Aristotle |last1=Hardie |first1=R. P. |last2=Gaye |first2=R. K. |publisher=MIT |accessdate=4 May 2014}}"''Time then is a kind of number. (Number, we must note, is used in two senses-both of what is counted or the countable and also of that with which we count. Time obviously is what is counted, not that with which we count: there are different kinds of thing.) It is clear, then, that time is 'number of movement in respect of the before and after', and is continuous since it is an attribute of what is continuous. ''"</ref> | |||
In Book 11 of his '']'', ] ruminates on the nature of time, asking, "What then is time? If no one asks me, I know: if I wish to explain it to one that asketh, I know not." He begins to define time by what it is not rather than what it is,<ref> | |||
{{cite book |url=http://en.wikisource.org/Nicene_and_Post-Nicene_Fathers:_Series_I/Volume_I/Confessions/Book_XI/Chapter_14 |authorlink=Augustine of Hippo |author=Augustine of Hippo |title=Confessions |accessdate=9 April 2011}} Book 11, Chapter 14. | |||
</ref> | |||
an approach similar to that taken in other ]. However, Augustine ends up calling time a "distention" of the mind (Confessions 11.26) by which we simultaneously grasp the past in memory, the present by attention, and the future by expectation. | |||
In contrast to ancient Greek philosophers who believed that the universe had an infinite past with no beginning, ] and ] developed the concept of the universe having a finite past with a beginning. | |||
This view is shared by Abrahamic faiths as they believe time started by creation, therefore the only thing being infinite is God and everything else, including time, is finite. | |||
] believed in absolute space and absolute time; Leibniz believed that time and space are relational.<ref>Gottfried Martin, ''Kant's Metaphysics and Theory of Science'' | |||
</ref> | |||
The differences between Leibniz's and Newton's interpretations came to a head in the famous ]. | |||
{{Quote box | |||
|quote=Time is not an empirical concept. For neither co-existence nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time did not exist as a foundation ''a priori''. Without this presupposition we could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or in succession. | |||
|source=], '']'' (1781), trans. Vasilis Politis (London: Dent., 1991), p.54. | |||
|align=right | |||
|width=35% | |||
|quoted=1 | |||
}} | |||
], in the '']'', described time as an '']'' intuition that allows us (together with the other ''a priori'' intuition, space) to comprehend ].<ref name="kant"> | |||
{{cite book |url=http://ebooks.adelaide.edu.au/k/kant/immanuel/k16p/ |last=Kant |first=Immanuel |authorlink=Immanuel Kant |title=The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edition |date=1787 |accessdate=9 April 2011}} translated by ], eBooks@Adelaide, 2004 | |||
</ref> | |||
With Kant, neither space nor time are conceived as ], but rather both are elements of a systematic mental framework that necessarily structures the experiences of any rational agent, or observing subject. Kant thought of time as a fundamental part of an ] conceptual framework, together with space and number, within which we sequence events, ] their duration, and compare the motions of objects. In this view, ''time'' does not refer to any kind of entity that "flows," that objects "move through," or that is a "container" for events. Spatial ]s are used to ] the extent of and distances between ], and temporal measurements are used to quantify the durations of and between ]. Time was designated by Kant as the purest possible ] of a pure concept or category. | |||
] believed that time was neither a real homogeneous medium nor a mental construct, but possesses what he referred to as '']''. Duration, in Bergson's view, was creativity and memory as an essential component of reality.<ref>Bergson, Henri (1907) ''Creative Evolution''. trans. by Arthur Mitchell. Mineola: Dover, 1998. | |||
</ref> | |||
According to ] we do not exist inside time, we ''are'' time. Hence, the relationship to the past is a present awareness of ''having been'', which allows the past to exist in the present. The relationship to the future is the state of anticipating a potential possibility, task, or engagement. It is related to the human propensity for caring and being concerned, which causes "being ahead of oneself" when thinking of a pending occurrence. Therefore, this concern for a potential occurrence also allows the future to exist in the present. The present becomes an experience, which is qualitative instead of quantitative. Heidegger seems to think this is the way that a linear relationship with time, or temporal existence, is broken or transcended.<ref name=Balslev> | |||
{{Cite book | |||
| last=Balslev | |||
| first=Anindita N. | |||
|author2=Jitendranath Mohanty | |||
| title=Religion and Time | |||
| publisher=Brill Academic Publishers | |||
| series=Studies in the History of Religions, 54. | |||
| date=November 1992 | |||
| location=The Netherlands | |||
| pages=53, 54, 55, 56, 57, 58, and 59 | |||
| url=https://books.google.com/?id=y94cKeEVa3sC&printsec=frontcover&dq=Religion+and+time#v=onepage&q=Heidegger&f=false | |||
| isbn=978-90-04-09583-0}} | |||
</ref> | |||
We are not stuck in sequential time. We are able to remember the past and project into the future—we have a kind of random access to our representation of temporal existence; we can, in our thoughts, step out of (ecstasis) sequential time.<ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| title=Being and Time | |||
| author=Martin Heidegger | |||
| page=425 | |||
| url=https://books.google.com/?id=S57m5gW0L-MC&pg=PA425&lpg=PA425&dq=heidegger+sequence#v=onepage&q=heidegger%20sequence&f=false | |||
| date=1962 | |||
| chapter=V | |||
| isbn=978-0-631-19770-6}} | |||
</ref> | |||
=== Time as "unreal" === | |||
In 5th century BC ], ] the ], in a fragment preserved from his chief work ''On Truth'', held that: ''"Time is not a reality (hypostasis), but a concept (noêma) or a measure (metron)."'' | |||
] went further, maintaining that time, motion, and change were illusions, leading to the ] of his follower ].<ref>{{cite web |author=Harry Foundalis |title=You are about to disappear |url=http://www.foundalis.com/phi/WhyTimeFlows.htm |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Time as an illusion is also a common theme in ] thought.<ref> | |||
{{cite web |title=Buddhism and the illusion of time |url=http://www.buddhasvillage.com/teachings/time.htm |first=Tom |last=Huston |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
{{cite book | |||
| url=https://books.google.com/?id=kfsyfoO1IlYC&pg=RA1-PR19&dq=The+fundamental+wisdom+of+the+middle+way+time#v=onepage&q&f=false | |||
| last=Garfield|first=Jay L.|title=The fundamental wisdom of the middle way: Nāgārjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā|date=1995|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York|isbn=978-0-19-509336-0}} | |||
</ref> | |||
]'s 1908 '']'' argues that, since every event has the characteristic of being both present and not present (i.e., future or past), that time is a self-contradictory idea (see also ]). | |||
These arguments often center on what it means for something to be ''unreal''. Modern physicists generally believe that time is as ''real'' as space—though others, such as ] in his book '']'', argue that quantum equations of the universe take their true form when expressed in the timeless ] containing every possible ''now'' or momentary configuration of the universe, called ']' by Barbour.<ref> | |||
{{cite web |title=Time is an illusion? |url=http://physicsandphysicists.blogspot.com/2007/03/time-is-illusion.html |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
A modern philosophical theory called ] views the past and the future as human-mind interpretations of movement instead of real parts of time (or "dimensions") which coexist with the present. This theory rejects the existence of all direct interaction with the past or the future, holding only the present as tangible. This is one of the philosophical arguments against time travel. This contrasts with ] (all time: present, past and future, is real) and the ] (the present and the past are real, but the future is not). | |||
== Physical definition == | |||
{{Classical mechanics|cTopic=Fundamental concepts}} | |||
{{Main article|Time in physics}} | |||
Until ] reinterpretation of the physical concepts associated with time and space, time was considered to be the same everywhere in the universe, with all observers measuring the same time interval for any event.<ref>Herman M. Schwartz, ''Introduction to Special Relativity'', McGraw-Hill Book Company, 1968, hardcover 442 pages, see {{isbn|0-88275-478-5}} (1977 edition), pp. 10–13 | |||
</ref> | |||
Non-relativistic ] is based on this Newtonian idea of time. | |||
Einstein, in his ],<ref>A. Einstein, H. A. Lorentz, H. Weyl, H. Minkowski, ''The Principle of Relativity'', Dover Publications, Inc, 2000, softcover 216 pages, {{isbn|0-486-60081-5}}, See pp. 37–65 for an English translation of Einstein's original 1905 paper. | |||
</ref> | |||
postulated the constancy and finiteness of the speed of light for all observers. He showed that this postulate, together with a reasonable definition for what it means for two events to be simultaneous, requires that distances appear compressed and time intervals appear lengthened for events associated with objects in motion relative to an inertial observer. | |||
The theory of special relativity finds a convenient formulation in ]time, a mathematical structure that combines three dimensions of space with a single dimension of time. In this formalism, distances in space can be measured by how long light takes to travel that distance, e.g., a ] is a measure of distance, and a meter is now defined in terms of how far light travels in a certain amount of time. Two ] in Minkowski spacetime are separated by an '']'', which can be either ], ], or ]. Events that have a time-like separation cannot be simultaneous in any ], there must be a temporal component (and possibly a spatial one) to their separation. Events that have a space-like separation will be simultaneous in some frame of reference, and there is no frame of reference in which they do not have a spatial separation. Different observers may calculate different distances and different time intervals between two events, but the ''invariant interval'' between the events is independent of the observer (and his velocity). | |||
=== Classical mechanics === | |||
In non-relativistic ], Newton's concept of "relative, apparent, and common time" can be used in the formulation of a prescription for the synchronization of clocks. Events seen by two different observers in motion relative to each other produce a mathematical concept of time that works sufficiently well for describing the everyday phenomena of most people's experience. In the late nineteenth century, physicists encountered problems with the classical understanding of time, in connection with the behavior of electricity and magnetism. Einstein resolved these problems by invoking a method of synchronizing clocks using the constant, finite speed of light as the maximum signal velocity. This led directly to the result that observers in motion relative to one another measure different elapsed times for the same event. | |||
]s are absolute, the "present" is a relative concept different for observers in relative motion.]] | |||
=== Spacetime === | |||
{{Main article|Spacetime}} | |||
Time has historically been closely related with space, the two together merging into spacetime in ] ] and ]. According to these theories, the concept of time depends on the ], and the human perception as well as the measurement by instruments such as clocks are different for observers in relative motion. For example, if a spaceship carrying a clock flies through space at (very nearly) the speed of light, its crew does not notice a change in the speed of time on board their vessel because everything traveling at the same speed slows down at the same rate (including the clock, the crew's thought processes, and the functions of their bodies). However, to a stationary observer watching the spaceship fly by, the spaceship appears flattened in the direction it is traveling and the clock on board the spaceship appears to move very slowly. | |||
On the other hand, the crew on board the spaceship also perceives the observer as slowed down and flattened along the spaceship's direction of travel, because both are moving at very nearly the speed of light relative to each other. Because the outside universe appears flattened to the spaceship, the crew perceives themselves as quickly traveling between regions of space that (to the stationary observer) are many light years apart. This is reconciled by the fact that the crew's perception of time is different from the stationary observer's; what seems like seconds to the crew might be hundreds of years to the stationary observer. In either case, however, causality remains unchanged: the ] is the set of events that can send light signals to an entity and the ] is the set of events to which an entity can send light signals.<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ev9zrt__lec |title=Albert Einstein's Theory of Relativity |publisher=YouTube |date=30 November 2011 |accessdate=24 September 2013}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=V7vpw4AH8QQ |title=Time Travel: Einstein's big idea (Theory of Relativity) |publisher=YouTube |date=9 January 2007 |accessdate=24 September 2013}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|last=Hours |first=After |url=http://www.cracked.com/article_19659_7-theories-time-that-would-make-doc-browns-head-explode.html |title=7 Theories on Time That Would Make Doc Brown's Head Explode |publisher=Cracked.com |date=11 February 2012 |accessdate=24 September 2013}}</ref> | |||
=== Time dilation === | |||
]: Event B is simultaneous with A in the green reference frame, but it occurred before in the blue frame, and occurs later in the red frame.]] | |||
{{Main article|Time dilation}} | |||
] showed in his thought experiments that people travelling at different speeds, while agreeing on ], measure different time separations between events, and can even observe different chronological orderings between non-causally related events. Though these effects are typically minute in the human experience, the effect becomes much more pronounced for objects moving at speeds approaching the speed of light. ]s exist for a well known average fraction of a second in a lab relatively at rest, but when travelling close to the speed of light they are measured to travel farther and exist for much longer than when at rest. According to the ], in the high-speed particle's ], it exists, on the average, for a standard amount of time known as its ], and the distance it travels in that time is zero, because its velocity is zero. Relative to a frame of reference at rest, time seems to "slow down" for the particle. Relative to the high-speed particle, distances seem to shorten. Einstein showed how both temporal and spatial dimensions can be altered (or "warped") by high-speed motion. | |||
Einstein (''The Meaning of Relativity''): "Two ] taking place at the points A and B of a system K are simultaneous if they appear at the same instant when observed from the middle point, M, of the interval AB. Time is then defined as the ensemble of the indications of similar clocks, at rest relative to K, which register the same simultaneously." | |||
Einstein wrote in his book, ''Relativity'', that ], i.e., two events that appear simultaneous to an observer in a particular inertial reference frame need not be judged as simultaneous by a second observer in a different inertial frame of reference. | |||
=== Relativistic time versus Newtonian time === | |||
] of a rapidly accelerating observer in a relativistic universe. The events ("dots") that pass the two diagonal lines in the bottom half of the image (the past ] of the observer in the origin) are the events visible to the observer.]] | |||
The animations visualise the different treatments of time in the Newtonian and the relativistic descriptions. At the heart of these differences are the ] and ]s applicable in the Newtonian and relativistic theories, respectively. | |||
In the figures, the vertical direction indicates time. The horizontal direction indicates distance (only one spatial dimension is taken into account), and the thick dashed curve is the spacetime trajectory ("]") of the observer. The small dots indicate specific (past and future) events in spacetime. | |||
The slope of the world line (deviation from being vertical) gives the relative velocity to the observer. Note how in both pictures the view of spacetime changes when the observer accelerates. | |||
In the Newtonian description these changes are such that ''time'' is absolute:<ref>{{cite book |title=Elements of Newtonian Mechanics |edition=illustrated |first1=Jens M. |last1=Knudsen |first2=Poul |last2=Hjorth |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |year=2012 |isbn=978-3-642-97599-8 |page=30 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=rkP1CAAAQBAJ}} </ref> the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event occurs in the 'now' (i.e., whether an event passes the horizontal line through the observer). | |||
However, in the relativistic description the ''observability of events'' is absolute: the movements of the observer do not influence whether an event passes the "]" of the observer. Notice that with the change from a Newtonian to a relativistic description, the concept of ''absolute time'' is no longer applicable: events move up-and-down in the figure depending on the acceleration of the observer. | |||
=== Arrow of time === | |||
{{Main article|Arrow of time}} | |||
Time appears to have a direction—the past lies behind, fixed and immutable, while the future lies ahead and is not necessarily fixed. Yet for the most part the laws of physics do not specify an ], and allow any process to proceed both forward and in reverse. This is generally a consequence of time being modelled by a parameter in the system being analysed, where there is no "proper time": the direction of the arrow of time is sometimes arbitrary. Examples of this include the ] arrow of time, which points away from the ], ], and the radiative arrow of time, caused by ] only travelling forwards in time (see ]). In ], the ] implies that there should be a small counterbalancing time asymmetry to preserve ] as stated above. The standard description of ] in ] is also time asymmetric (see ]). The ] states that ] must increase over time (see ]). This can be in either direction - Brian Greene theorizes that, according to the equations, the change in entropy occurs symmetrically whether going forward or backward in time. So entropy tends to increase in either direction, and our current low-entropy universe is a statistical aberration, in the similar manner as tossing a coin often enough that eventually heads will result ten times in a row. However, this theory is not supported empirically in local experiment.<ref>{{cite book|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yZujlUD1oAAC|last=Greene|first=Brian|title=The Fabric of the Cosmos - Chapter 6: Chance and the Arrow|date=2005|location=London}}</ref> | |||
=== Quantized time === | |||
{{See also|Chronon}} | |||
Time quantization is a hypothetical concept. In the modern established physical theories (the ] of Particles and Interactions and ]) time is not quantized. | |||
] (~ 5.4 × 10<sup>−44</sup> seconds) is the unit of time in the system of ] known as ]. Current established physical theories are believed to fail at this time scale, and many physicists expect that the Planck time might be the smallest unit of time that could ever be measured, even in principle. Tentative physical theories that describe this time scale exist; see for instance ]. | |||
== Time travel == | |||
{{Main article|Time travel}} | |||
{{See also|Time travel in fiction|Wormhole|Twin paradox}} | |||
Time travel is the concept of moving backwards or forwards to different points in time, in a manner analogous to moving through space, and different from the normal "flow" of time to an earthbound observer. In this view, all points in time (including future times) "persist" in some way. Time travel has been a ] in ] since the 19th century. Travelling backwards in time has never been verified, presents many theoretical problems, and may be an impossibility.<ref>{{cite journal|url=http://prespacetime.com/index.php/pst/article/view/10|title=Informational Time and Space|first=Gunn|last=Quznetsov|date=30 March 2010|publisher=|volume=1|issue=2|accessdate=30 December 2016|via=Prespacetime Journal}}</ref> Any technological device, whether fictional or hypothetical, that is used to achieve time travel is known as a ]. | |||
A central problem with time travel to the past is the violation of ]; should an effect precede its cause, it would give rise to the possibility of a ]. Some interpretations of time travel resolve this by accepting the possibility of travel between ], ], or ]s. | |||
Another solution to the problem of causality-based temporal paradoxes is that such paradoxes cannot arise simply because they have not arisen. As illustrated in numerous works of fiction, ] either ceases to exist in the past or the outcomes of such decisions are predetermined. As such, it would not be possible to enact the ] because it is a historical fact that your grandfather was not killed before his child (your parent) was conceived. This view doesn't simply hold that history is an unchangeable constant, but that any change made by a hypothetical future time traveller would already have happened in his or her past, resulting in the reality that the traveller moves from. More elaboration on this view can be found in the ]. | |||
== Time perception == | |||
]]] | |||
{{Main article|Time perception}} | |||
The ] refers to the time duration wherein one's ]s are considered to be in the present. The experienced present is said to be ‘specious’ in that, unlike the objective present, it is an interval and not a durationless instant. The term ''specious present'' was first introduced by the psychologist ], and later developed by ].<ref name="Andersen">{{cite journal|author=Andersen, Holly |author2=Rick Grush |title=A brief history of time-consciousness: historical precursors to James and Husserl |publisher=Journal of the History of Philosophy |date=2009 |volume=47 |issue=2 |pages=277–307 |url=http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/bhtc/Andersen&Grush.pdf |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20080216100320/http://mind.ucsd.edu/papers/bhtc/Andersen%26Grush.pdf |dead-url=yes |archive-date=16 February 2008 |format=PDF |accessdate=9 April 2011 |df= }} | |||
</ref> | |||
=== Biopsychology === | |||
The brain's judgment of time is known to be a highly distributed system, including at least the ], ] and ] as its components. One particular component, the ], is responsible for the ], while other cell clusters appear capable of shorter-range (]) timekeeping. | |||
Psychoactive drugs can impair the judgment of time. ]s can lead both humans and rats to overestimate time intervals,<ref>{{cite journal |quotes=|last=Wittmann |first=M. |author2=Leland DS |author3=Churan J |author4=Paulus MP. |date=8 October 2007|title=Impaired time perception and motor timing in stimulant-dependent subjects |journal=Drug Alcohol Depend. |volume=90 |issue=2–3 |pages=183–92 |pmid=17434690 |pmc=1997301 |doi=10.1016/j.drugalcdep.2007.03.005 }} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
{{cite journal |last=Cheng |first=Ruey-Kuang |author2=Macdonald, Christopher J. |author3=Meck, Warren H. |date=2006 |title=Differential effects of cocaine and ketamine on time estimation: Implications for neurobiological models of interval timing |journal=Pharmacology, biochemistry and behavior |volume=85 |issue=1 |pages=114–122 |pmid=16920182 |doi=10.1016/j.pbb.2006.07.019 |url=http://cat.inist.fr/?aModele=afficheN&cpsidt=18303059 |format=online abstract |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
while ]s can have the opposite effect.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Tinklenberg |first=Jared R. |author2=Walton T. Roth1 |author3=Bert S. Kopell |date=January 1976 |title=Marijuana and ethanol: Differential effects on time perception, heart rate, and subjective response |journal=Psychopharmacology | |||
|volume=49 |issue=3 |pages=275–279 |pmid=826945 |doi=10.1007/BF00426830 |url=http://www.springerlink.com/content/q1227453r481x439/ |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
The level of activity in the brain of ]s such as ] and ] may be the reason for this.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Arzy |first=Shahar |author2=Istvan Molnar-Szakacs |author3=Olaf Blanke |date=18 June 2008 |title=Self in Time: Imagined Self-Location Influences Neural Activity Related to Mental Time Travel |journal=The Journal of Neuroscience |volume=28 |issue=25 |pages=6502–6507 |pmid=18562621|doi=10.1523/JNEUROSCI.5712-07.2008 |url=http://www.jneurosci.org/content/28/25/6502.abstract |format=Abstract |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Such chemicals will either excite or inhibit the firing of ]s in the brain, with a greater firing rate allowing the brain to register the occurrence of more events within a given interval (speed up time) and a decreased firing rate reducing the brain's capacity to distinguish events occurring within a given interval (slow down time).<ref name="Carter 186–187">{{cite book |title=The Human Brain Book |first1=Rita |last1=Carter |publisher=Dorling Kindersley Publishing |date=2009 |isbn=978-0-7566-5441-2 |pages=186–187 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=eCV6cwU3qm0C}}</ref> | |||
] is the use of response time in perceptual-motor tasks to infer the content, duration, and temporal sequencing of cognitive operations. | |||
=== Development of awareness and understanding of time in children === | |||
Children's expanding cognitive abilities allow them to understand time more clearly. Two- and three-year-olds' understanding of time is mainly limited to "now and not now." Five- and six-year-olds can grasp the ideas of past, present, and future. Seven- to ten-year-olds can use clocks and calendars.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/growing-friendships/201403/time-management-kids |title=Time Management for Kids |last= Kennedy-Moore |first=Eileen |date=28 March 2014 |work= |publisher=Psychology Today |accessdate=26 April 2014}}</ref> | |||
=== Alterations === | |||
In addition to psychoactive drugs, judgments of time can be altered by ]s (like the ]),<ref name="Wada">Wada Y, Masuda T, Noguchi K, 2005, "Temporal illusion called 'kappa effect' in event perception" Perception 34 ECVP Abstract Supplement | |||
</ref> age,<ref>{{cite web|url=https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg16422180.900-look-how-time-flies|title=Look how time flies.. |last=Robert |first=Adler |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and ].<ref>{{Cite journal |url=http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/content~content=a790232921~db=all |title=Hypnosis and the perception of time |publisher=International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis |volume=27 |issue=1 |date=January 1979|pages=29–41 |doi=10.1080/00207147908407540|author=Bowers, Kenneth |journal=International Journal of Clinical and Experimental Hypnosis |pmid=541126 |last2=Brenneman |first2=HA |postscript=<!--None--> }} | |||
</ref> | |||
The sense of time is impaired in some people with neurological diseases such as ] and ]. | |||
Psychologists assert that time seems to go faster with age, but the literature on this age-related perception of time remains controversial.<ref>{{cite book |title=Studies on the structure of time: from physics to psycho(patho)logy |chapter=Subjective Time Versus Proper (Clock) Time |editor1-first=R. |editor1-last=Buccheri | |||
|editor2-first=V. |editor2-last=Di Gesù |editor3-first=Metod |editor3-last=Saniga |first1=Ronald P. |last1=Gruber |first2=Lawrence F. |last2=Wagner |first3=Richard A. |last3=Block |publisher=Springer |date=2000 | |||
|isbn=0-306-46439-X |page=54 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LMsDqsvcxckC |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Those who support this notion argue that young people, having more excitatory neurotransmitters, are able to cope with faster external events.<ref name="Carter 186–187"/> | |||
== Use of time == | |||
{{See also|Time management|Time discipline}} | |||
In ] and ], ] is the general name given to ] and ] rules, conventions, customs, and expectations governing the measurement of time, the ] and awareness of time measurements, and people's expectations concerning the observance of these customs by others. ]<ref>{{cite book | last = Russell Hochschild | first = Arlie | author-link = Arlie Russell Hochschild | title = ] | publisher = Metropolitan Books | location = New York | year = 1997 }} {{isbn|9780805044713}}</ref><ref>{{cite news | last = Russell Hochschild | first = Arlie | author-link = Arlie Russell Hochschild|url=https://www.nytimes.com/1997/04/20/magazine/there-s-no-place-like-work.html?scp=1&sq=%22there%27s%20no%20place%20like%20work%22&st=cse|title=There's no place like work|work= ] | publisher = The New York Times | date= 20 April 1997 }}</ref> and ]<ref>{{cite book | last = Elias | first = Norbert | author-link = Norbert Elias | title = Time: an essay | publisher = Blackwell | location = Oxford, UK Cambridge, USA | year = 1992 | isbn = 9780631157984 }}</ref> have written on the use of time from a sociological perspective. | |||
The use of time is an important issue in understanding ], ], and ]. ] is a developing field of study. The question concerns how time is allocated across a number of activities (such as time spent at home, at work, shopping, etc.). Time use changes with ], as the ] or the ] created new opportunities to use time in different ways. However, some aspects of time use are relatively stable over long periods of time, such as the amount of time spent traveling to work, which despite major changes in ], has been observed to be about 20–30 minutes one-way for a large number of cities over a long period. | |||
] is the organization of tasks or events by first estimating how much time a task requires and when it must be completed, and adjusting events that would interfere with its completion so it is done in the appropriate amount of time. Calendars and day planners are common examples of time management tools. | |||
A sequence of events, or series of events, is a ] of items, facts, events, actions, changes, or procedural steps, arranged in time order (chronological order), often with ] relationships among the items.<ref>{{cite web|title=Sequence - Order of Important Events|url=http://www.austinschools.org/curriculum/la/resources/documents/instResources/LA_res_Seq_ORS_Module.pdf|publisher=]|date=2009}} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
{{cite web|title=Sequence of Events Worksheets |url=http://www.reference.com/motif/Science/sequence-of-events-worksheets |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20101013032311/http://www.reference.com/motif/Science/sequence-of-events-worksheets |dead-url=yes |archive-date=13 October 2010 |publisher=] |df= }} | |||
</ref><ref> | |||
{{cite web|author1=Compiled by David Luckham |author2=Roy Schulte |lastauthoramp=yes |title=Event Processing Glossary—Version 2.0|url=http://www.complexevents.com/2011/08/23/event-processing-glossary-version-2-0/|publisher=Complex Event Processing}} | |||
</ref> | |||
Because of ], cause precedes ], or cause and effect may appear together in a single item, but effect never precedes cause. A sequence of events can be presented in text, ], ]s, or ]s. The description of the items or events may include a ]. A sequence of events that includes the time along with place or location information to describe a sequential path may be referred to as a ]. | |||
Uses of a sequence of events include stories,<ref>{{cite web|author=Richard Nordquist|title=narrative|url=http://grammar.about.com/od/mo/g/narrative2term.htm|publisher=]}} | |||
</ref> | |||
] events (]), directions and steps in ],<ref>{{cite web|author=David J. Piasecki|title=Inventory Accuracy Glossary|url=http://www.accuracybook.com/glossary.htm|publisher=AccuracyBook.com (OPS Publishing)}} | |||
</ref> | |||
and timetables for scheduling activities. A sequence of events may also be used to help describe ] in science, technology, and medicine. A sequence of events may be focused on past events (e.g., stories, history, chronology), on future events that must be in a predetermined order (e.g., ]s, ], procedures, timetables), or focused on the observation of past events with the expectation that the events will occur in the future (e.g., processes, projections). The use of a sequence of events occurs in fields as diverse as ]s (]), ] ('']''), ] (]), ] (]), and ]<ref>{{cite web|title=Utility Communications Architecture (UCA) glossary|url=http://www.nettedautomation.com/glossary_menue/glossary_uca.html|publisher=NettedAutomation}} | |||
</ref> | |||
(]). A specific example of a sequence of events is the ]. | |||
== Spatial conceptualization of time == | |||
Although time is regarded as an abstract concept, there is increasing evidence that time is ] in the mind in terms of space.<ref name=":0">{{Cite journal|last=Núñez|first=Rafael|last2=Cooperrider|first2=Kensy|last3=Doan|first3=D|last4=Wassmann|first4=Jürg|date=2012-07-01|title=Contours of time: Topographic construals of past, present, and future in the Yupno valley of Papua New Guinea|url=http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S0010027712000571|journal=Cognition|volume=124|issue=1|pages=25–35|doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2012.03.007}}</ref> That is, instead of thinking about time in a general, abstract way, humans think about time in a spatial way and mentally organize it as such. Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal events in a specific way. | |||
This spatial representation of time is often represented in the mind as a Mental Time Line (MTL).<ref name=":1">{{Cite journal|last=Bottini|first=Roberto|last2=Crepaldi|first2=Davide|last3=Casasanto|first3=Daniel|last4=Crollen|first4=Virgine|last5=Collignon|first5=Olivier|date=2015-08-01|title=Space and time in the sighted and blind|url=http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S001002771500075X|journal=Cognition|volume=141|pages=67–72|doi=10.1016/j.cognition.2015.04.004}}</ref> Using space to think about time allows humans to mentally organize temporal order. These origins are shaped by many environmental factors<ref name=":0" />––for example, ] appears to play a large role in the different types of MTLs, as reading/] provides an everyday temporal orientation that differs from culture to culture.<ref name=":1" /> In western cultures, the MTL may unfold rightward (with the past on the left and the future on the right) since people read and write from left to right.<ref name=":1" /> Western calendars also continue this trend by placing the past on the left with the future progressing toward the right. Conversely, Arabic, Farsi, Urdu and ] speakers read from right to left, and their MTLs unfold leftward (past on the right with future on the left), and evidence suggests these speakers organize time events in their minds like this as well.<ref name=":1" /> | |||
This linguistic evidence that abstract concepts are based in spatial concepts also reveals that the way humans mentally organize time events varies across cultures––that is, a certain specific mental organization system is not universal. So, although Western cultures typically associate past events with the left and future events with the right according to a certain MTL, this kind of horizontal, egocentric MTL is not the spatial organization of all cultures. Although most developed nations use an egocentric spatial system, there is recent evidence that some cultures use an allocentric spatialization, often based on environmental features.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
A recent study of the indigenous Yupno people of ] focused on the directional gestures used when individuals used time-related words.<ref name=":0" /> When speaking of the past (such as "last year" or "past times"), individuals gestured downhill, where the river of the valley flowed into the ocean. When speaking of the future, they gestured uphill, toward the source of the river. This was common regardless of which direction the person faced, revealing that the Yupno people may use an allocentric MTL, in which time flows uphill.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
A similar study of the Pormpuraawans, an ] in Australia, revealed a similar distinction in which when asked to organize photos of a man aging "in order," individuals consistently placed the youngest photos to the east and the oldest photos to the west, regardless of which direction they faced.<ref name=":2">{{cite web|url=http://pss.sagepub.com/content/early/2010/10/19/0956797610386621.full|title=Remembrances of Times East|website=Psychological Science|pmid=20959511|access-date=2016-12-07}}</ref> This directly clashed with an American group which consistently organized the photos from left to right. Therefore, this group also appears to have an allocentric MTL, but based on the cardinal directions instead of geographical features.<ref name=":2" /> | |||
The wide array of distinctions in the way different groups think about time leads to the broader question that different groups may also think about other abstract concepts in different ways as well, such as causality and number.<ref name=":0" /> | |||
== See also == | |||
{{Misplaced Pages books}} | |||
]]] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
=== Books === | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] and ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* ''The Physical Basis of The Direction of Time'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
* '']'' by ] | |||
=== Organizations === | |||
''Leading scholarly organisations for researchers on the history and technology of time and timekeeping'' | |||
* ]—AHS (United Kingdom) | |||
* ] (Switzerland) | |||
* ]—DGC (Germany) | |||
* ]—NAWCC (United States) | |||
{{col-begin}} | |||
{{col-break|width=25%}} | |||
=== Miscellaneous arts and sciences === | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] (NTP) | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
{{col-break|width=25%}} | |||
===Miscellaneous units of time=== | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
* ] | |||
{{col-end}} | |||
== References == | |||
{{Reflist|30em}} | |||
== Further reading == | |||
<div style="font-size:90%;"> | |||
{{div col|2}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Julian Barbour |last=Barbour |first=Julian |title=The End of Time: The Next Revolution in Our Understanding of the Universe |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1999 |isbn=0-19-514592-5}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=David S. Landes |last=Landes |first=David |title=] |publisher=] |date=2000 |isbn=0-674-00282-2}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Das |first=Tushar Kanti |title=The Time Dimension: An Interdisciplinary Guide |date=1990 |location=New York |publisher=Praeger |isbn=0-275-92681-8 }}- Research bibliography | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Paul Davies |last=Davies |first=Paul |title=About Time: Einstein's Unfinished Revolution |date=1996 |isbn=0-684-81822-1 |publisher=Simon & Schuster Paperbacks |location=New York}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Richard Feynman |last=Feynman |first=Richard |title=The Character of Physical Law |date=1994 |origyear=1965 |location=Cambridge (Mass) |publisher=The MIT Press |isbn=0-262-56003-8 |pages=108–126 |url=http://mitpress.mit.edu/catalog/item/default.asp?ttype=2&tid=5277}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Peter Galison |last=Galison |first=Peter |title=Einstein's Clocks and Poincaré's Maps: Empires of Time |date=1992 |location=New York |publisher=W. W. Norton |isbn=0-393-02001-0}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Highfield |first=Roger |title=Arrow of Time: A Voyage through Science to Solve Time's Greatest Mystery |publisher=Random House |date=1992 |isbn=0-449-90723-6}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Mermin |last=Mermin |first=N. David |title=It's About Time: Understanding Einstein's Relativity |date=2005 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=0-691-12201-6 |url=http://press.princeton.edu/titles/8112.html}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Roger Penrose |last=Penrose |first=Roger |title=The Emperor's New Mind: Concerning Computers, Minds, and the Laws of Physics |date=1999 |origyear=1989 |location=New York |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=0-19-286198-0 |pages=391–417 |url=http://ukcatalogue.oup.com/product/9780192861986.do |accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Price |first=Huw |title=Time's Arrow and Archimedes' Point |date=1996 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=0-19-511798-0 |url=http://sydney.edu.au/time/price/TAAP.html|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Hans Reichenbach |last=Reichenbach |first=Hans |title=The Direction of Time |date=1999 |origyear=1956 |location=New York |publisher=Dover |isbn=0-486-40926-0 |url=http://store.doverpublications.com/0486409260.html}} | |||
* ], '']'' | |||
* {{cite book |last=Quznetsov |first=Gunn A. |title=Logical Foundation of Theoretical Physics |publisher=Nova Sci. Publ. |date=2006 |isbn=1-59454-948-6}} | |||
* {{cite book |authorlink=Gerald James Whitrow |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=The Nature of Time |publisher=Holt, Rinehart and Wilson (New York) |date=1973}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=The Natural Philosophy of Time |publisher=Clarendon Press (Oxford) |date=1980}} | |||
* {{cite book |last=Whitrow |first=Gerald J. |title=Time in History. The evolution of our general awareness of time and temporal perspective |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1988 |isbn=0-19-285211-6}} | |||
* {{cite book|last=Rovelli |first=Carlo |title=What is time? What is space? |publisher=Di Renzo Editore |location=Rome |date=2006 |isbn=88-8323-146-5 |url=http://www.direnzo.it/main.phtml?Language=en&Doc=0001&ISBN=8883231465 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20070127102006/http://www.direnzo.it/main.phtml?Language=en&Doc=0001&ISBN=8883231465 |dead-url=yes |archive-date=27 January 2007 |df= }} | |||
* ], (2005) ''Art, Time and Technology: Histories of the Disappearing Body'', Berg | |||
* Craig Callendar, ''Introducing Time'', Icon Books, 2010, {{isbn|978-1848311206}} | |||
* Benjamin Gal-Or, ''Cosmology, Physics and Philosophy'', Springer Verlag, 1981, 1983, 1987, {{isbn|0-387-90581-2}}, {{isbn|0-387-96526-2}}. | |||
* Roberto Mangabeira Unger and Lee Smolin, '']'', Cambridge University Press, 2014, {{isbn|978-1-107-07406-4}}. | |||
</div> | |||
{{div col end}} | |||
== External links == | |||
{{Sister project links|n=no|s=no|v=no}} | |||
* | |||
* from Planck Time to the lifespan of the universe | |||
* | |||
* {{In Our Time|Time|p005465z|Time}} | |||
* in the '']'', by Bradley Dowden. | |||
* {{cite encyclopedia|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2004/entries/time-experience|title=The Experience and Perception of Time|last=Le Poidevin|first=Robin|date=Winter 2004|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor=Edward N. Zalta|accessdate=9 April 2011}} | |||
* | |||
{{Nature nav}} | |||
{{Time topics}} | |||
{{Navboxes | |||
|title=Time articles: Detailed navigation | |||
|titlestyle=background:#ee9; border:1px solid silver; padding:0.2em 1em 0.2em 6.5em; | |||
|list1= | |||
{{Time measurement and standards}} | |||
{{Chronology}} | |||
{{Time in religion and mythology}} | |||
{{Time in philosophy}} | |||
{{metaphysics}} | |||
}} | |||
{{SI base quantities}} | |||
{{Authority control}} | |||
{{Portal bar|Time|Physics}} | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] | |||
] |
Revision as of 20:06, 1 October 2017
time is a fake time
Done by hackxor from a school called MEIS
Have fun wikipedia U piece of sh.it