Misplaced Pages

Kaplansky's theorem on projective modules

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.

In abstract algebra, Kaplansky's theorem on projective modules, first proven by Irving Kaplansky, states that a projective module over a local ring is free; where a not-necessarily-commutative ring is called local if for each element x, either x or 1 − x is a unit element. The theorem can also be formulated so to characterize a local ring (#Characterization of a local ring).

For a finite projective module over a commutative local ring, the theorem is an easy consequence of Nakayama's lemma. For the general case, the proof (both the original as well as later one) consists of the following two steps:

  • Observe that a projective module over an arbitrary ring is a direct sum of countably generated projective modules.
  • Show that a countably generated projective module over a local ring is free (by a " of the proof of Nakayama's lemma").

The idea of the proof of the theorem was also later used by Hyman Bass to show big projective modules (under some mild conditions) are free. According to (Anderson & Fuller 1992), Kaplansky's theorem "is very likely the inspiration for a major portion of the results" in the theory of semiperfect rings.

Proof

The proof of the theorem is based on two lemmas, both of which concern decompositions of modules and are of independent general interest.

Lemma 1 —  Let F {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}} denote the family of modules that are direct sums of some countably generated submodules (here modules can be those over a ring, a group or even a set of endomorphisms). If M {\displaystyle M} is in F {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}} , then each direct summand of M {\displaystyle M} is also in F {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}} .

Proof: Let N be a direct summand; i.e., M = N L {\displaystyle M=N\oplus L} . Using the assumption, we write M = i I M i {\displaystyle M=\bigoplus _{i\in I}M_{i}} where each M i {\displaystyle M_{i}} is a countably generated submodule. For each subset A I {\displaystyle A\subset I} , we write M A = i A M i , N A = {\displaystyle M_{A}=\bigoplus _{i\in A}M_{i},N_{A}=} the image of M A {\displaystyle M_{A}} under the projection M N M {\displaystyle M\to N\hookrightarrow M} and L A {\displaystyle L_{A}} the same way. Now, consider the set of all triples ( J {\displaystyle J} , B {\displaystyle B} , C {\displaystyle C} ) consisting of a subset J I {\displaystyle J\subset I} and subsets B , C F {\displaystyle B,C\subset {\mathfrak {F}}} such that M J = N J L J {\displaystyle M_{J}=N_{J}\oplus L_{J}} and N J , L J {\displaystyle N_{J},L_{J}} are the direct sums of the modules in B , C {\displaystyle B,C} . We give this set a partial ordering such that ( J , B , C ) ( J , B , C ) {\displaystyle (J,B,C)\leq (J',B',C')} if and only if J J {\displaystyle J\subset J'} , B B , C C {\displaystyle B\subset B',C\subset C'} . By Zorn's lemma, the set contains a maximal element ( J , B , C ) {\displaystyle (J,B,C)} . We shall show that J = I {\displaystyle J=I} ; i.e., N = N J = N B N F {\displaystyle N=N_{J}=\bigoplus _{N'\in B}N'\in {\mathfrak {F}}} . Suppose otherwise. Then we can inductively construct a sequence of at most countable subsets I 1 I 2 I {\displaystyle I_{1}\subset I_{2}\subset \cdots \subset I} such that I 1 J {\displaystyle I_{1}\not \subset J} and for each integer n 1 {\displaystyle n\geq 1} ,

M I n N I n + L I n M I n + 1 {\displaystyle M_{I_{n}}\subset N_{I_{n}}+L_{I_{n}}\subset M_{I_{n+1}}} .

Let I = 0 I n {\displaystyle I'=\bigcup _{0}^{\infty }I_{n}} and J = J I {\displaystyle J'=J\cup I'} . We claim:

M J = N J L J . {\displaystyle M_{J'}=N_{J'}\oplus L_{J'}.}

The inclusion {\displaystyle \subset } is trivial. Conversely, N J {\displaystyle N_{J'}} is the image of N J + L J + M I N J + M I {\displaystyle N_{J}+L_{J}+M_{I'}\subset N_{J}+M_{I'}} and so N J M J {\displaystyle N_{J'}\subset M_{J'}} . The same is also true for L J {\displaystyle L_{J'}} . Hence, the claim is valid.

Now, N J {\displaystyle N_{J}} is a direct summand of M {\displaystyle M} (since it is a summand of M J {\displaystyle M_{J}} , which is a summand of M {\displaystyle M} ); i.e., N J M = M {\displaystyle N_{J}\oplus M'=M} for some M {\displaystyle M'} . Then, by modular law, N J = N J ( M N J ) {\displaystyle N_{J'}=N_{J}\oplus (M'\cap N_{J'})} . Set N J ~ = M N J {\displaystyle {\widetilde {N_{J}}}=M'\cap N_{J'}} . Define L J ~ {\displaystyle {\widetilde {L_{J}}}} in the same way. Then, using the early claim, we have:

M J = M J N J ~ L J ~ , {\displaystyle M_{J'}=M_{J}\oplus {\widetilde {N_{J}}}\oplus {\widetilde {L_{J}}},}

which implies that

N J ~ L J ~ M J / M J M J J {\displaystyle {\widetilde {N_{J}}}\oplus {\widetilde {L_{J}}}\simeq M_{J'}/M_{J}\simeq M_{J'-J}}

is countably generated as J J I {\displaystyle J'-J\subset I'} . This contradicts the maximality of ( J , B , C ) {\displaystyle (J,B,C)} . {\displaystyle \square }

Lemma 2 — If M i , i I {\displaystyle M_{i},i\in I} are countably generated modules with local endomorphism rings and if N {\displaystyle N} is a countably generated module that is a direct summand of i I M i {\displaystyle \bigoplus _{i\in I}M_{i}} , then N {\displaystyle N} is isomorphic to i I M i {\displaystyle \bigoplus _{i\in I'}M_{i}} for some at most countable subset I I {\displaystyle I'\subset I} .

Proof: Let G {\displaystyle {\mathcal {G}}} denote the family of modules that are isomorphic to modules of the form i F M i {\displaystyle \bigoplus _{i\in F}M_{i}} for some finite subset F I {\displaystyle F\subset I} . The assertion is then implied by the following claim:

  • Given an element x N {\displaystyle x\in N} , there exists an H G {\displaystyle H\in {\mathcal {G}}} that contains x and is a direct summand of N.

Indeed, assume the claim is valid. Then choose a sequence x 1 , x 2 , {\displaystyle x_{1},x_{2},\dots } in N that is a generating set. Then using the claim, write N = H 1 N 1 {\displaystyle N=H_{1}\oplus N_{1}} where x 1 H 1 G {\displaystyle x_{1}\in H_{1}\in {\mathcal {G}}} . Then we write x 2 = y + z {\displaystyle x_{2}=y+z} where y H 1 , z N 1 {\displaystyle y\in H_{1},z\in N_{1}} . We then decompose N 1 = H 2 N 2 {\displaystyle N_{1}=H_{2}\oplus N_{2}} with z H 2 G {\displaystyle z\in H_{2}\in {\mathcal {G}}} . Note { x 1 , x 2 } H 1 H 2 {\displaystyle \{x_{1},x_{2}\}\subset H_{1}\oplus H_{2}} . Repeating this argument, in the end, we have: { x 1 , x 2 , } 0 H n {\textstyle \{x_{1},x_{2},\dots \}\subset \bigoplus _{0}^{\infty }H_{n}} ; i.e., N = 0 H n {\textstyle N=\bigoplus _{0}^{\infty }H_{n}} . Hence, the proof reduces to proving the claim and the claim is a straightforward consequence of Azumaya's theorem (see the linked article for the argument). {\displaystyle \square }

Proof of the theorem: Let N {\displaystyle N} be a projective module over a local ring. Then, by definition, it is a direct summand of some free module F {\displaystyle F} . This F {\displaystyle F} is in the family F {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {F}}} in Lemma 1; thus, N {\displaystyle N} is a direct sum of countably generated submodules, each a direct summand of F and thus projective. Hence, without loss of generality, we can assume N {\displaystyle N} is countably generated. Then Lemma 2 gives the theorem. {\displaystyle \square }

Characterization of a local ring

Kaplansky's theorem can be stated in such a way to give a characterization of a local ring. A direct summand is said to be maximal if it has an indecomposable complement.

Theorem —  Let R be a ring. Then the following are equivalent.

  1. R is a local ring.
  2. Every projective module over R is free and has an indecomposable decomposition M = i I M i {\displaystyle M=\bigoplus _{i\in I}M_{i}} such that for each maximal direct summand L of M, there is a decomposition M = ( j J M j ) L {\displaystyle M={\Big (}\bigoplus _{j\in J}M_{j}{\Big )}\bigoplus L} for some subset J I {\displaystyle J\subset I} .

The implication 1. 2. {\displaystyle 1.\Rightarrow 2.} is exactly (usual) Kaplansky's theorem and Azumaya's theorem. The converse 2. 1. {\displaystyle 2.\Rightarrow 1.} follows from the following general fact, which is interesting itself:

  • A ring R is local {\displaystyle \Leftrightarrow } for each nonzero proper direct summand M of R 2 = R × R {\displaystyle R^{2}=R\times R} , either R 2 = ( 0 × R ) M {\displaystyle R^{2}=(0\times R)\oplus M} or R 2 = ( R × 0 ) M {\displaystyle R^{2}=(R\times 0)\oplus M} .

( ) {\displaystyle (\Rightarrow )} is by Azumaya's theorem as in the proof of 1. 2. {\displaystyle 1.\Rightarrow 2.} . Conversely, suppose R 2 {\displaystyle R^{2}} has the above property and that an element x in R is given. Consider the linear map σ : R 2 R , σ ( a , b ) = a b {\displaystyle \sigma :R^{2}\to R,\,\sigma (a,b)=a-b} . Set y = x 1 {\displaystyle y=x-1} . Then σ ( x , y ) = 1 {\displaystyle \sigma (x,y)=1} , which is to say η : R R 2 , a ( a x , a y ) {\displaystyle \eta :R\to R^{2},a\mapsto (ax,ay)} splits and the image M {\displaystyle M} is a direct summand of R 2 {\displaystyle R^{2}} . It follows easily from that the assumption that either x or -y is a unit element. {\displaystyle \square }

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Anderson & Fuller 1992, Corollary 26.7.
  2. Anderson & Fuller 1992, Proposition 15.15.
  3. Matsumura 1989, Theorem 2.5.
  4. Lam 2000, Part 1. § 1.
  5. Bass 1963
  6. Anderson & Fuller 1992, Theorem 26.1.
  7. Anderson & Fuller 1992, Proof of Theorem 26.5.
  8. Anderson & Fuller 1992, Exercise 26.3.

References

Categories: