Misplaced Pages

Prime avoidance lemma

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
(Redirected from Prime avoidance) Result concerning ideals of commutative rings
You can help expand this article with text translated from the corresponding article in French. (October 2018) Click for important translation instructions.
  • View a machine-translated version of the French article.
  • Machine translation, like DeepL or Google Translate, is a useful starting point for translations, but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate, rather than simply copy-pasting machine-translated text into the English Misplaced Pages.
  • Do not translate text that appears unreliable or low-quality. If possible, verify the text with references provided in the foreign-language article.
  • You must provide copyright attribution in the edit summary accompanying your translation by providing an interlanguage link to the source of your translation. A model attribution edit summary is Content in this edit is translated from the existing French Misplaced Pages article at ]; see its history for attribution.
  • You may also add the template {{Translated|fr|Lemme d'évitement des idéaux premiers}} to the talk page.
  • For more guidance, see Misplaced Pages:Translation.

In algebra, the prime avoidance lemma says that if an ideal I in a commutative ring R is contained in a union of finitely many prime ideals Pi's, then it is contained in Pi for some i.

There are many variations of the lemma (cf. Hochster); for example, if the ring R contains an infinite field or a finite field of sufficiently large cardinality, then the statement follows from a fact in linear algebra that a vector space over an infinite field or a finite field of large cardinality is not a finite union of its proper vector subspaces.

Statement and proof

The following statement and argument are perhaps the most standard.

Statement: Let E be a subset of R that is an additive subgroup of R and is multiplicatively closed. Let I 1 , I 2 , , I n , n 1 {\displaystyle I_{1},I_{2},\dots ,I_{n},n\geq 1} be ideals such that I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} are prime ideals for i 3 {\displaystyle i\geq 3} . If E is not contained in any of I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} 's, then E is not contained in the union I i {\displaystyle \cup I_{i}} .

Proof by induction on n: The idea is to find an element that is in E and not in any of I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} 's. The basic case n = 1 is trivial. Next suppose n ≥ 2. For each i, choose

z i E j i I j {\displaystyle z_{i}\in E-\cup _{j\neq i}I_{j}}

where the set on the right is nonempty by inductive hypothesis. We can assume z i I i {\displaystyle z_{i}\in I_{i}} for all i; otherwise, some z i {\displaystyle z_{i}} avoids all the I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} 's and we are done. Put

z = z 1 z n 1 + z n {\displaystyle z=z_{1}\dots z_{n-1}+z_{n}} .

Then z is in E but not in any of I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} 's. Indeed, if z is in I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} for some i n 1 {\displaystyle i\leq n-1} , then z n {\displaystyle z_{n}} is in I i {\displaystyle I_{i}} , a contradiction. Suppose z is in I n {\displaystyle I_{n}} . Then z 1 z n 1 {\displaystyle z_{1}\dots z_{n-1}} is in I n {\displaystyle I_{n}} . If n is 2, we are done. If n > 2, then, since I n {\displaystyle I_{n}} is a prime ideal, some z i , i < n {\displaystyle z_{i},i<n} is in I n {\displaystyle I_{n}} , a contradiction.

E. Davis' prime avoidance

There is the following variant of prime avoidance due to E. Davis.

Theorem —  Let A be a ring, p 1 , , p r {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{1},\dots ,{\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} prime ideals, x an element of A and J an ideal. For the ideal I = x A + J {\displaystyle I=xA+J} , if I p i {\displaystyle I\not \subset {\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} for each i, then there exists some y in J such that x + y p i {\displaystyle x+y\not \in {\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} for each i.

Proof: We argue by induction on r. Without loss of generality, we can assume there is no inclusion relation between the p i {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} 's; since otherwise we can use the inductive hypothesis.

Also, if x p i {\displaystyle x\not \in {\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} for each i, then we are done; thus, without loss of generality, we can assume x p r {\displaystyle x\in {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} . By inductive hypothesis, we find a y in J such that x + y I 1 r 1 p i {\displaystyle x+y\in I-\cup _{1}^{r-1}{\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} . If x + y {\displaystyle x+y} is not in p r {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} , we are done. Otherwise, note that J p r {\displaystyle J\not \subset {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} (since x p r {\displaystyle x\in {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} ) and since p r {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} is a prime ideal, we have:

p r J p 1 p r 1 {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}\not \supset J\,{\mathfrak {p}}_{1}\cdots {\mathfrak {p}}_{r-1}} .

Hence, we can choose y {\displaystyle y'} in J p 1 p r 1 {\displaystyle J\,{\mathfrak {p}}_{1}\cdots {\mathfrak {p}}_{r-1}} that is not in p r {\displaystyle {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} . Then, since x + y p r {\displaystyle x+y\in {\mathfrak {p}}_{r}} , the element x + y + y {\displaystyle x+y+y'} has the required property. {\displaystyle \square }

Application

Let A be a Noetherian ring, I an ideal generated by n elements and M a finite A-module such that I M M {\displaystyle IM\neq M} . Also, let d = depth A ( I , M ) {\displaystyle d=\operatorname {depth} _{A}(I,M)} = the maximal length of M-regular sequences in I = the length of every maximal M-regular sequence in I. Then d n {\displaystyle d\leq n} ; this estimate can be shown using the above prime avoidance as follows. We argue by induction on n. Let { p 1 , , p r } {\displaystyle \{{\mathfrak {p}}_{1},\dots ,{\mathfrak {p}}_{r}\}} be the set of associated primes of M. If d > 0 {\displaystyle d>0} , then I p i {\displaystyle I\not \subset {\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} for each i. If I = ( y 1 , , y n ) {\displaystyle I=(y_{1},\dots ,y_{n})} , then, by prime avoidance, we can choose

x 1 = y 1 + i = 2 n a i y i {\displaystyle x_{1}=y_{1}+\sum _{i=2}^{n}a_{i}y_{i}}

for some a i {\displaystyle a_{i}} in A {\displaystyle A} such that x 1 1 r p i {\displaystyle x_{1}\not \in \cup _{1}^{r}{\mathfrak {p}}_{i}} = the set of zero divisors on M. Now, I / ( x 1 ) {\displaystyle I/(x_{1})} is an ideal of A / ( x 1 ) {\displaystyle A/(x_{1})} generated by n 1 {\displaystyle n-1} elements and so, by inductive hypothesis, depth A / ( x 1 ) ( I / ( x 1 ) , M / x 1 M ) n 1 {\displaystyle \operatorname {depth} _{A/(x_{1})}(I/(x_{1}),M/x_{1}M)\leq n-1} . The claim now follows.

Notes

  1. Proof of the fact: suppose the vector space is a finite union of proper subspaces. Consider a finite product of linear functionals, each of which vanishes on a proper subspace that appears in the union; then it is a nonzero polynomial vanishing identically, a contradiction.
  2. Matsumura 1986, Exercise 16.8.
  3. Adapted from the solution to Matsumura 1986, Exercise 1.6.

References

Category: