Misplaced Pages

Proportional rule (bankruptcy)

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.

The proportional rule is a division rule for solving bankruptcy problems. According to this rule, each claimant should receive an amount proportional to their claim. In the context of taxation, it corresponds to a proportional tax.

Formal definition

There is a certain amount of money to divide, denoted by E {\displaystyle E} (=Estate or Endowment). There are n claimants. Each claimant i has a claim denoted by c i {\displaystyle c_{i}} . Usually, i = 1 n c i > E {\displaystyle \sum _{i=1}^{n}c_{i}>E} , that is, the estate is insufficient to satisfy all the claims.

The proportional rule says that each claimant i should receive r c i {\displaystyle r\cdot c_{i}} , where r is a constant chosen such that i = 1 n r c i = E {\displaystyle \sum _{i=1}^{n}r\cdot c_{i}=E} . In other words, each agent gets c i j = 1 n c j E {\displaystyle {\frac {c_{i}}{\sum _{j=1}^{n}c_{j}}}\cdot E} .

Examples

Examples with two claimants:

  • P R O P ( 60 , 90 ; 100 ) = ( 40 , 60 ) {\displaystyle PROP(60,90;100)=(40,60)} . That is: if the estate is worth 100 and the claims are 60 and 90, then r = 2 / 3 {\displaystyle r=2/3} , so the first claimant gets 40 and the second claimant gets 60.
  • P R O P ( 50 , 100 ; 100 ) = ( 33.333 , 66.667 ) {\displaystyle PROP(50,100;100)=(33.333,66.667)} , and similarly P R O P ( 40 , 80 ; 100 ) = ( 33.333 , 66.667 ) {\displaystyle PROP(40,80;100)=(33.333,66.667)} .

Examples with three claimants:

  • P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 100 ) = ( 16.667 , 33.333 , 50 ) {\displaystyle PROP(100,200,300;100)=(16.667,33.333,50)} .
  • P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 200 ) = ( 33.333 , 66.667 , 100 ) {\displaystyle PROP(100,200,300;200)=(33.333,66.667,100)} .
  • P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 300 ) = ( 50 , 100 , 150 ) {\displaystyle PROP(100,200,300;300)=(50,100,150)} .

Characterizations

The proportional rule has several characterizations. It is the only rule satisfying the following sets of axioms:

  • Self-duality and composition-up;
  • Self-duality and composition-down;
  • No advantageous transfer;
  • Resource linearity;
  • No advantageous merging and no advantageous splitting.

Truncated-proportional rule

There is a variant called truncated-claims proportional rule, in which each claim larger than E is truncated to E, and then the proportional rule is activated. That is, it equals P R O P ( c 1 , , c n , E ) {\displaystyle PROP(c_{1}',\ldots ,c_{n}',E)} , where c i := min ( c i , E ) {\displaystyle c'_{i}:=\min(c_{i},E)} . The results are the same for the two-claimant problems above, but for the three-claimant problems we get:

  • T P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 100 ) = ( 33.333 , 33.333 , 33.333 ) {\displaystyle TPROP(100,200,300;100)=(33.333,33.333,33.333)} , since all claims are truncated to 100;
  • T P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 200 ) = ( 40 , 80 , 80 ) {\displaystyle TPROP(100,200,300;200)=(40,80,80)} , since the claims vector is truncated to (100,200,200).
  • T P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 300 ) = ( 50 , 100 , 150 ) {\displaystyle TPROP(100,200,300;300)=(50,100,150)} , since here the claims are not truncated.

Adjusted-proportional rule

The adjusted proportional rule first gives, to each agent i, their minimal right, which is the amount not claimed by the other agents. Formally, m i := max ( 0 , E j i c j ) {\displaystyle m_{i}:=\max(0,E-\sum _{j\neq i}c_{j})} . Note that i = 1 n c i E {\displaystyle \sum _{i=1}^{n}c_{i}\geq E} implies m i c i {\displaystyle m_{i}\leq c_{i}} .

Then, it revises the claim of agent i to c i := c i m i {\displaystyle c'_{i}:=c_{i}-m_{i}} , and the estate to E := E i m i {\displaystyle E':=E-\sum _{i}m_{i}} . Note that that E 0 {\displaystyle E'\geq 0} .

Finally, it activates the truncated-claims proportional rule, that is, it returns T P R O P ( c 1 , , c n , E ) = P R O P ( c 1 , , c n , E ) {\displaystyle TPROP(c_{1},\ldots ,c_{n},E')=PROP(c_{1}'',\ldots ,c_{n}'',E')} , where c i := min ( c i , E ) {\displaystyle c''_{i}:=\min(c'_{i},E')} .

With two claimants, the revised claims are always equal, so the remainder is divided equally. Examples:

  • A P R O P ( 60 , 90 ; 100 ) = ( 35 , 65 ) {\displaystyle APROP(60,90;100)=(35,65)} . The minimal rights are ( m 1 , m 2 ) = ( 10 , 40 ) {\displaystyle (m_{1},m_{2})=(10,40)} . The remaining claims are ( c 1 , c 2 ) = ( 50 , 50 ) {\displaystyle (c_{1}',c_{2}')=(50,50)} and the remaining estate is E = 50 {\displaystyle E'=50} ; it is divided equally among the claimants.
  • A P R O P ( 50 , 100 ; 100 ) = ( 25 , 75 ) {\displaystyle APROP(50,100;100)=(25,75)} . The minimal rights are ( m 1 , m 2 ) = ( 0 , 50 ) {\displaystyle (m_{1},m_{2})=(0,50)} . The remaining claims are ( c 1 , c 2 ) = ( 50 , 50 ) {\displaystyle (c_{1}',c_{2}')=(50,50)} and the remaining estate is E = 50 {\displaystyle E'=50} .
  • A P R O P ( 40 , 80 ; 100 ) = ( 30 , 70 ) {\displaystyle APROP(40,80;100)=(30,70)} . The minimal rights are ( m 1 , m 2 ) = ( 20 , 60 ) {\displaystyle (m_{1},m_{2})=(20,60)} . The remaining claims are ( c 1 , c 2 ) = ( 20 , 20 ) {\displaystyle (c_{1}',c_{2}')=(20,20)} and the remaining estate is E = 20 {\displaystyle E'=20} .

With three or more claimants, the revised claims may be different. In all the above three-claimant examples, the minimal rights are ( 0 , 0 , 0 ) {\displaystyle (0,0,0)} and thus the outcome is equal to TPROP, for example, A P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 200 ) = T P R O P ( 100 , 200 , 300 ; 200 ) = ( 20 , 40 , 40 ) {\displaystyle APROP(100,200,300;200)=TPROP(100,200,300;200)=(20,40,40)} .

See also

References

  1. William, Thomson (2003-07-01). "Axiomatic and game-theoretic analysis of bankruptcy and taxation problems: a survey". Mathematical Social Sciences. 45 (3): 249–297. doi:10.1016/S0165-4896(02)00070-7. ISSN 0165-4896.
  2. Young, H. P (1988-04-01). "Distributive justice in taxation". Journal of Economic Theory. 44 (2): 321–335. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(88)90007-5. ISSN 0022-0531.
  3. Moulin, Hervé (1985). "Egalitarianism and Utilitarianism in Quasi-Linear Bargaining". Econometrica. 53 (1): 49–67. doi:10.2307/1911723. ISSN 0012-9682. JSTOR 1911723.
  4. Moulin, Hervé (1985-06-01). "The separability axiom and equal-sharing methods". Journal of Economic Theory. 36 (1): 120–148. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(85)90082-1. ISSN 0022-0531.
  5. ^ Chun, Youngsub (1988-06-01). "The proportional solution for rights problems". Mathematical Social Sciences. 15 (3): 231–246. doi:10.1016/0165-4896(88)90009-1. ISSN 0165-4896.
  6. O'Neill, Barry (1982-06-01). "A problem of rights arbitration from the Talmud". Mathematical Social Sciences. 2 (4): 345–371. doi:10.1016/0165-4896(82)90029-4. hdl:10419/220805. ISSN 0165-4896.
  7. de Frutos, M. Angeles (1999-09-01). "Coalitional manipulations in a bankruptcy problem". Review of Economic Design. 4 (3): 255–272. doi:10.1007/s100580050037. hdl:10016/4282. ISSN 1434-4750. S2CID 195240195.
  8. Curiel, I. J.; Maschler, M.; Tijs, S. H. (1987-09-01). "Bankruptcy games". Zeitschrift für Operations Research. 31 (5): A143 – A159. doi:10.1007/BF02109593. ISSN 1432-5217. S2CID 206811949.
Category: