Misplaced Pages

Hahn decomposition theorem

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Measurability theorem

In mathematics, the Hahn decomposition theorem, named after the Austrian mathematician Hans Hahn, states that for any measurable space ( X , Σ ) {\displaystyle (X,\Sigma )} and any signed measure μ {\displaystyle \mu } defined on the σ {\displaystyle \sigma } -algebra Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } , there exist two Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable sets, P {\displaystyle P} and N {\displaystyle N} , of X {\displaystyle X} such that:

  1. P N = X {\displaystyle P\cup N=X} and P N = {\displaystyle P\cap N=\varnothing } .
  2. For every E Σ {\displaystyle E\in \Sigma } such that E P {\displaystyle E\subseteq P} , one has μ ( E ) 0 {\displaystyle \mu (E)\geq 0} , i.e., P {\displaystyle P} is a positive set for μ {\displaystyle \mu } .
  3. For every E Σ {\displaystyle E\in \Sigma } such that E N {\displaystyle E\subseteq N} , one has μ ( E ) 0 {\displaystyle \mu (E)\leq 0} , i.e., N {\displaystyle N} is a negative set for μ {\displaystyle \mu } .

Moreover, this decomposition is essentially unique, meaning that for any other pair ( P , N ) {\displaystyle (P',N')} of Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subsets of X {\displaystyle X} fulfilling the three conditions above, the symmetric differences P P {\displaystyle P\triangle P'} and N N {\displaystyle N\triangle N'} are μ {\displaystyle \mu } -null sets in the strong sense that every Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset of them has zero measure. The pair ( P , N ) {\displaystyle (P,N)} is then called a Hahn decomposition of the signed measure μ {\displaystyle \mu } .

Jordan measure decomposition

A consequence of the Hahn decomposition theorem is the Jordan decomposition theorem, which states that every signed measure μ {\displaystyle \mu } defined on Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } has a unique decomposition into a difference μ = μ + μ {\displaystyle \mu =\mu ^{+}-\mu ^{-}} of two positive measures, μ + {\displaystyle \mu ^{+}} and μ {\displaystyle \mu ^{-}} , at least one of which is finite, such that μ + ( E ) = 0 {\displaystyle {\mu ^{+}}(E)=0} for every Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset E N {\displaystyle E\subseteq N} and μ ( E ) = 0 {\displaystyle {\mu ^{-}}(E)=0} for every Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset E P {\displaystyle E\subseteq P} , for any Hahn decomposition ( P , N ) {\displaystyle (P,N)} of μ {\displaystyle \mu } . We call μ + {\displaystyle \mu ^{+}} and μ {\displaystyle \mu ^{-}} the positive and negative part of μ {\displaystyle \mu } , respectively. The pair ( μ + , μ ) {\displaystyle (\mu ^{+},\mu ^{-})} is called a Jordan decomposition (or sometimes Hahn–Jordan decomposition) of μ {\displaystyle \mu } . The two measures can be defined as

μ + ( E ) := μ ( E P ) and μ ( E ) := μ ( E N ) {\displaystyle {\mu ^{+}}(E):=\mu (E\cap P)\qquad {\text{and}}\qquad {\mu ^{-}}(E):=-\mu (E\cap N)}

for every E Σ {\displaystyle E\in \Sigma } and any Hahn decomposition ( P , N ) {\displaystyle (P,N)} of μ {\displaystyle \mu } .

Note that the Jordan decomposition is unique, while the Hahn decomposition is only essentially unique.

The Jordan decomposition has the following corollary: Given a Jordan decomposition ( μ + , μ ) {\displaystyle (\mu ^{+},\mu ^{-})} of a finite signed measure μ {\displaystyle \mu } , one has

μ + ( E ) = sup B Σ ,   B E μ ( B ) and μ ( E ) = inf B Σ ,   B E μ ( B ) {\displaystyle {\mu ^{+}}(E)=\sup _{B\in \Sigma ,~B\subseteq E}\mu (B)\quad {\text{and}}\quad {\mu ^{-}}(E)=-\inf _{B\in \Sigma ,~B\subseteq E}\mu (B)}

for any E {\displaystyle E} in Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } . Furthermore, if μ = ν + ν {\displaystyle \mu =\nu ^{+}-\nu ^{-}} for a pair ( ν + , ν ) {\displaystyle (\nu ^{+},\nu ^{-})} of finite non-negative measures on X {\displaystyle X} , then

ν + μ + and ν μ . {\displaystyle \nu ^{+}\geq \mu ^{+}\quad {\text{and}}\quad \nu ^{-}\geq \mu ^{-}.}

The last expression means that the Jordan decomposition is the minimal decomposition of μ {\displaystyle \mu } into a difference of non-negative measures. This is the minimality property of the Jordan decomposition.

Proof of the Jordan decomposition: For an elementary proof of the existence, uniqueness, and minimality of the Jordan measure decomposition see Fischer (2012).

Proof of the Hahn decomposition theorem

Preparation: Assume that μ {\displaystyle \mu } does not take the value {\displaystyle -\infty } (otherwise decompose according to μ {\displaystyle -\mu } ). As mentioned above, a negative set is a set A Σ {\displaystyle A\in \Sigma } such that μ ( B ) 0 {\displaystyle \mu (B)\leq 0} for every Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset B A {\displaystyle B\subseteq A} .

Claim: Suppose that D Σ {\displaystyle D\in \Sigma } satisfies μ ( D ) 0 {\displaystyle \mu (D)\leq 0} . Then there is a negative set A D {\displaystyle A\subseteq D} such that μ ( A ) μ ( D ) {\displaystyle \mu (A)\leq \mu (D)} .

Proof of the claim: Define A 0 := D {\displaystyle A_{0}:=D} . Inductively assume for n N 0 {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} _{0}} that A n D {\displaystyle A_{n}\subseteq D} has been constructed. Let

t n := sup ( { μ ( B ) B Σ   and   B A n } ) {\displaystyle t_{n}:=\sup(\{\mu (B)\mid B\in \Sigma ~{\text{and}}~B\subseteq A_{n}\})}

denote the supremum of μ ( B ) {\displaystyle \mu (B)} over all the Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subsets B {\displaystyle B} of A n {\displaystyle A_{n}} . This supremum might a priori be infinite. As the empty set {\displaystyle \varnothing } is a possible candidate for B {\displaystyle B} in the definition of t n {\displaystyle t_{n}} , and as μ ( ) = 0 {\displaystyle \mu (\varnothing )=0} , we have t n 0 {\displaystyle t_{n}\geq 0} . By the definition of t n {\displaystyle t_{n}} , there then exists a Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset B n A n {\displaystyle B_{n}\subseteq A_{n}} satisfying

μ ( B n ) min ( 1 , t n 2 ) . {\displaystyle \mu (B_{n})\geq \min \!\left(1,{\frac {t_{n}}{2}}\right).}

Set A n + 1 := A n B n {\displaystyle A_{n+1}:=A_{n}\setminus B_{n}} to finish the induction step. Finally, define

A := D \ n = 0 B n . {\displaystyle A:=D{\Bigg \backslash }\bigcup _{n=0}^{\infty }B_{n}.}

As the sets ( B n ) n = 0 {\displaystyle (B_{n})_{n=0}^{\infty }} are disjoint subsets of D {\displaystyle D} , it follows from the sigma additivity of the signed measure μ {\displaystyle \mu } that

μ ( D ) = μ ( A ) + n = 0 μ ( B n ) μ ( A ) + n = 0 min ( 1 , t n 2 ) μ ( A ) . {\displaystyle \mu (D)=\mu (A)+\sum _{n=0}^{\infty }\mu (B_{n})\geq \mu (A)+\sum _{n=0}^{\infty }\min \!\left(1,{\frac {t_{n}}{2}}\right)\geq \mu (A).}

This shows that μ ( A ) μ ( D ) {\displaystyle \mu (A)\leq \mu (D)} . Assume A {\displaystyle A} were not a negative set. This means that there would exist a Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset B A {\displaystyle B\subseteq A} that satisfies μ ( B ) > 0 {\displaystyle \mu (B)>0} . Then t n μ ( B ) {\displaystyle t_{n}\geq \mu (B)} for every n N 0 {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} _{0}} , so the series on the right would have to diverge to + {\displaystyle +\infty } , implying that μ ( D ) = + {\displaystyle \mu (D)=+\infty } , which is a contradiction, since μ ( D ) 0 {\displaystyle \mu (D)\leq 0} . Therefore, A {\displaystyle A} must be a negative set.

Construction of the decomposition: Set N 0 = {\displaystyle N_{0}=\varnothing } . Inductively, given N n {\displaystyle N_{n}} , define

s n := inf ( { μ ( D ) D Σ   and   D X N n } ) . {\displaystyle s_{n}:=\inf(\{\mu (D)\mid D\in \Sigma ~{\text{and}}~D\subseteq X\setminus N_{n}\}).}

as the infimum of μ ( D ) {\displaystyle \mu (D)} over all the Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subsets D {\displaystyle D} of X N n {\displaystyle X\setminus N_{n}} . This infimum might a priori be {\displaystyle -\infty } . As {\displaystyle \varnothing } is a possible candidate for D {\displaystyle D} in the definition of s n {\displaystyle s_{n}} , and as μ ( ) = 0 {\displaystyle \mu (\varnothing )=0} , we have s n 0 {\displaystyle s_{n}\leq 0} . Hence, there exists a Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset D n X N n {\displaystyle D_{n}\subseteq X\setminus N_{n}} such that

μ ( D n ) max ( s n 2 , 1 ) 0. {\displaystyle \mu (D_{n})\leq \max \!\left({\frac {s_{n}}{2}},-1\right)\leq 0.}

By the claim above, there is a negative set A n D n {\displaystyle A_{n}\subseteq D_{n}} such that μ ( A n ) μ ( D n ) {\displaystyle \mu (A_{n})\leq \mu (D_{n})} . Set N n + 1 := N n A n {\displaystyle N_{n+1}:=N_{n}\cup A_{n}} to finish the induction step. Finally, define

N := n = 0 A n . {\displaystyle N:=\bigcup _{n=0}^{\infty }A_{n}.}

As the sets ( A n ) n = 0 {\displaystyle (A_{n})_{n=0}^{\infty }} are disjoint, we have for every Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset B N {\displaystyle B\subseteq N} that

μ ( B ) = n = 0 μ ( B A n ) {\displaystyle \mu (B)=\sum _{n=0}^{\infty }\mu (B\cap A_{n})}

by the sigma additivity of μ {\displaystyle \mu } . In particular, this shows that N {\displaystyle N} is a negative set. Next, define P := X N {\displaystyle P:=X\setminus N} . If P {\displaystyle P} were not a positive set, there would exist a Σ {\displaystyle \Sigma } -measurable subset D P {\displaystyle D\subseteq P} with μ ( D ) < 0 {\displaystyle \mu (D)<0} . Then s n μ ( D ) {\displaystyle s_{n}\leq \mu (D)} for all n N 0 {\displaystyle n\in \mathbb {N} _{0}} and

μ ( N ) = n = 0 μ ( A n ) n = 0 max ( s n 2 , 1 ) = , {\displaystyle \mu (N)=\sum _{n=0}^{\infty }\mu (A_{n})\leq \sum _{n=0}^{\infty }\max \!\left({\frac {s_{n}}{2}},-1\right)=-\infty ,}

which is not allowed for μ {\displaystyle \mu } . Therefore, P {\displaystyle P} is a positive set.

Proof of the uniqueness statement: Suppose that ( N , P ) {\displaystyle (N',P')} is another Hahn decomposition of X {\displaystyle X} . Then P N {\displaystyle P\cap N'} is a positive set and also a negative set. Therefore, every measurable subset of it has measure zero. The same applies to N P {\displaystyle N\cap P'} . As

P P = N N = ( P N ) ( N P ) , {\displaystyle P\triangle P'=N\triangle N'=(P\cap N')\cup (N\cap P'),}

this completes the proof. Q.E.D.

References

  • Billingsley, Patrick (1995). Probability and Measure -- Third Edition. Wiley Series in Probability and Mathematical Statistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 0-471-00710-2.
  • Fischer, Tom (2012). "Existence, uniqueness, and minimality of the Jordan measure decomposition". arXiv:1206.5449 .

External links

Measure theory
Basic concepts
Sets
Types of measures
Particular measures
Maps
Main results
Other results
For Lebesgue measure
Applications & related
Category: