Misplaced Pages

Natural number: Difference between revisions

Article snapshot taken from Wikipedia with creative commons attribution-sharealike license. Give it a read and then ask your questions in the chat. We can research this topic together.
Browse history interactively← Previous editContent deleted Content addedVisualWikitext
Revision as of 21:18, 3 October 2015 editCBM (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, File movers, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers55,390 editsm Reverted edits by 66.87.64.242 (talk) to last version by CBM← Previous edit Latest revision as of 18:43, 7 January 2025 edit undoEyer (talk | contribs)Extended confirmed users, IP block exemptions, Pending changes reviewers, Rollbackers16,688 editsm Reverted 2 edits by 109.43.179.239 (talk) to last revision by David EppsteinTags: Twinkle Undo 
(933 intermediate revisions by more than 100 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Number used for counting}}
{{about|“positive integers” and “non-negative integers”|all the numbers ..., −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, ...|Integer}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=May 2021}}
]


In ], the '''natural numbers''' are the ]s ], ], ], ], and so on, possibly excluding 0.<ref name="Enderton"/> Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the '''non-negative integers''' {{math|1=0, 1, 2, 3, ...}}, while others start with 1, defining them as the '''positive integers''' {{nobr|{{math|1, 2, 3, ...}} .{{efn|See {{section link|#Emergence as a term}}}} }} Some authors acknowledge both definitions whenever convenient.<ref name=":1">{{cite web |last=Weisstein |first=Eric W. |title=Natural Number |url=https://mathworld.wolfram.com/NaturalNumber.html |access-date=11 August 2020 |website=mathworld.wolfram.com |language=en}}</ref> Sometimes, the '''whole numbers''' are the natural numbers plus zero. In other cases, the ''whole numbers'' refer to all of the ]s, including negative integers.<ref>{{cite dictionary |first1=Jack G. |last1=Ganssle |first2=Michael |last2=Barr |name-list-style=amp |year=2003 |dictionary=Embedded Systems Dictionary |isbn=978-1-57820-120-4 |title=integer |pages=138 (integer), 247 (signed integer), & 276 (unsigned integer) |publisher=Taylor & Francis |via=Google Books |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zePGx82d_fwC |access-date=28 March 2017 |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170329150719/https://books.google.com/books?id=zePGx82d_fwC |archive-date=29 March 2017}}</ref> The '''counting numbers''' are another term for the natural numbers, particularly in primary school education, and are ambiguous as well although typically start at 1.<ref name=MathWorld_CountingNumber>{{MathWorld|title=Counting Number|id=CountingNumber}}</ref>
], two apples, three apples, ...)]]


The natural numbers are used for counting<!-- Please, do not link this word that is used in its common language meaning, and not in any technical meaning --> things, like "there are ''six'' coins on the table", in which case they are called '']s''. They are also used to put things in order,<!-- Please, do not link this word that is used in its common language meaning, and not in any technical meaning --> like "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country", which are called '']s''. Natural numbers are also used as labels, like ] on a sports team, where they serve as '']s'' and do not have mathematical properties.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Woodin |first1=Greg |first2=Bodo |last2=Winter |title=Numbers in Context: Cardinals, Ordinals, and Nominals in American English |journal=Cognitive Science |volume=48|number=6 |year=2024 |article-number=e13471 |doi=10.1111/cogs.13471 |doi-access=free|pmid=38895756 |pmc=11475258 }}</ref>
In ], the '''natural numbers''' (sometimes called the '''whole numbers''')<ref name=MathWorld_WholeNumber>{{MathWorld|title=Whole Number|id=WholeNumber}}</ref><ref name=ConciseOxford_WholeNumber>{{harvtxt|Clapham|Nicholson|2014}}: "'''whole number''' An integer, though sometimes it is taken to mean only non-negative integers, or just the positive integers."</ref><ref name=JamesJames_WholeNumber>{{harvtxt|James|James|1992}} give definitions of "whole number" under several ]s:<br />
INTEGER … ''Syn.'' whole number.<br />
NUMBER … whole number. A nonnegative integer.<br />
WHOLE … whole number.<br />
{{spaces|4}}(1) One of the integers 0, 1, 2, 3, … .<br />
{{spaces|4}}(2) A positive integer; ''i.e.'', a natural number.<br />
{{spaces|4}}(3) An integer, positive, negative, or zero.
</ref><ref>
The ''] for Mathematics'' say: "Whole numbers. The numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, ...." (Glossary, p. 87) ()<br />
Definitions from ''], Grades 1-8: Mathematics'', ] (2005) ()<br />
{{spaces|4}}"'''natural numbers.''' The counting numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, ...." (Glossary, p. 128)<br />
{{spaces|4}}"'''whole number.''' Any one of the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ...." (Glossary, p. 134)<br />
{{harvtxt|Musser|Peterson|Burger|2013|p=57}}: "As mentioned earlier, the study of the set of whole numbers, ''W'' = {0, 1, 2, 3, 4, ...}, is the foundation of elementary school mathematics."<br />
These ] books define the ''whole numbers'':
* {{harvtxt|Szczepanski|Kositsky|2008}}: "Another important collection of numbers is the ''whole numbers'', the natural numbers together with zero." (Chapter 1: ''The Whole Story'', p. 4). On the inside front cover, the authors say: "We based this book on the state standards for pre-algebra in California, Florida, New York, and Texas, ..."
* {{harvtxt|Bluman|2010}}: "When 0 is added to the set of natural numbers, the set is called the whole numbers." (Chapter 1: ''Whole Numbers'', p. 1)
:Both books define the ''natural numbers'' to be: "1, 2, 3, …".
</ref> are those used for ] (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ] (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). In common language, words used for counting are "]" and words used for ordering are "]".


The natural numbers form a ], commonly symbolized as a bold {{math|'''N'''}} or ] {{tmath|\N}}. Many other ]s are built from the natural numbers. For example, the ]s are made by adding 0 and negative numbers. The ]s add fractions, and the ]s add infinite decimals. ]s add the ]. This chain of extensions canonically ] the natural numbers in the other number systems.<ref>{{harvtxt|Mendelson|2008|page=x}} says: "The whole fantastic hierarchy of number systems is built up by purely set-theoretic means from a few simple assumptions about natural numbers."</ref><ref>{{harvtxt|Bluman|2010|page=1}}: "Numbers make up the foundation of mathematics."</ref>
Another use of natural numbers is for what ] call ]s, such as the model number of a product, where the "natural number" is used only for naming (as distinct from a ] where the order properties of the natural numbers distinguish later uses from earlier uses) and generally lacks any meaning of ''number'' as used in mathematics.


Natural numbers are studied in different areas of math. ] looks at things like how numbers divide evenly (]), or how ]s are spread out. ] studies counting and arranging numbered objects, such as ]s and ].
If ] is included in the set of natural numbers, this set is then called whole numbers. Some authors begin the natural numbers with {{num|0}}, (which is the set of whole numbers) corresponding to the '''non-negative integers''' {{nowrap|1=0, 1, 2, 3, ...}}, whereas others start with 1, corresponding to the '''positive integers''' {{nowrap|1={{num|1}}, {{num|2}}, {{num|3}}, ...}}.<ref>
{{MathWorld|title=Natural Number|id=NaturalNumber}}</ref><ref>
{{Citation
| url = http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/natural%20number
| title = natural number
| work = Merriam-Webster.com
| publisher = ]
| accessdate = 4 October 2014
}}
</ref><ref>{{harvtxt|Carothers|2000}} says: "ℕ is the set of natural numbers (positive integers)" (p. 3)</ref><ref name="Mac Lane & Birkhoff 1999 p15">{{harvtxt|Mac Lane|Birkhoff|1999}} include zero in the natural numbers: 'Intuitively, the set ℕ = {0, 1, 2, ... } of all ''natural numbers'' may be described as follows: ℕ contains an "initial" number 0; ...'. They follow that with their version of the Peano Postulates. (p. 15)</ref> This distinction is of no fundamental concern for the natural numbers as such, since their core construction is the ] ]. Including the number 0 just supplies an ] for the ] of ], which makes up together with the multiplication the usual arithmetic in the natural numbers, to be completed within the ]s and the ]s, only.


==History==
The whole numbers are the basis from which many other number sets may be built by extension: the ]s, by including an unresolved negation operation; the ]s, by including with the integers an unresolved division operation; the ]s by including with the rationals the termination of Cauchy sequences; the ]s, by including with the real numbers the unresolved square root of minus one; the ]s, by including with real numbers the infinitesimal value epsilon; vectors, by including a vector structure with reals; matrices, by having vectors of vectors; the ]; and so on.<ref>{{harvtxt|Mendelson|2008}} says: "The whole fantastic hierarchy of number systems is built up by purely set-theoretic means from a few simple assumptions about natural numbers." (Preface, p. x)</ref><ref>{{harvtxt|Bluman|2010}}: "Numbers make up the foundation of mathematics." (p. 1)</ref> Therefore, the natural numbers are canonically ] (identified) in the other number systems.
<!--This section is linked from ]-->


===Ancient roots===
Properties of the natural numbers, such as ] and the distribution of ]s, are studied in ]. Problems concerning counting and ordering, such as ] and ], are studied in ].
{{further|Prehistoric counting}}


] (on exhibition at the ])<ref name=RBINS_intro>{{cite web |title=Introduction |series=] |publisher=] |location=Brussels, Belgium |url=https://www.naturalsciences.be/expo/old_ishango/en/ishango/introduction.html |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160304051733/https://www.naturalsciences.be/expo/old_ishango/en/ishango/introduction.html |archive-date=4 March 2016}}</ref><ref name=RBINS_flash>{{cite web |title=Flash presentation |series=] |publisher=] |place=Brussels, Belgium |url=http://ishango.naturalsciences.be/Flash/flash_local/Ishango-02-EN.html |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160527164619/http://ishango.naturalsciences.be/Flash/flash_local/Ishango-02-EN.html |archive-date=27 May 2016}}</ref><ref name=UNESCO>{{cite web |title=The Ishango Bone, Democratic Republic of the Congo |website=]'s Portal to the Heritage of Astronomy |url=http://www2.astronomicalheritage.net/index.php/show-entity?identity=4&idsubentity=1 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141110195426/http://www2.astronomicalheritage.net/index.php/show-entity?identity=4&idsubentity=1 |archive-date=10 November 2014}}, on permanent display at the ], Brussels, Belgium.</ref> is believed to have been used 20,000&nbsp;years ago for natural number arithmetic.]]
In common language, for example in ], natural numbers may be called '''counting numbers'''<ref name=MathWorld_CountingNumber>{{MathWorld|title=Counting Number|id=CountingNumber}}</ref> to distinguish them from the ]s which are used for ].


The most primitive method of representing a natural number is to use one's fingers, as in ]. Putting down a ] for each object is another primitive method. Later, a set of objects could be tested for equality, excess or shortage—by striking out a mark and removing an object from the set.
==History==
<!--This section is linked from ]-->
] (on exhibition at the ])<ref name=RBINS_intro>, ], Brussels, Belgium.</ref><ref name=RBINS_flash>, ], Brussels, Belgium.</ref><ref name=UNESCO>, on permanent display at the ], Brussels, Belgium. ]'s Portal to the Heritage of Astronomy</ref> is believed to have been used 20,000 years ago for natural number arithmetic.]]


The first major advance in abstraction was the use of ] to represent numbers. This allowed systems to be developed for recording large numbers. The ancient ] developed a powerful system of numerals with distinct ] for&nbsp;1, 10, and all powers of&nbsp;10 up to over 1&nbsp;million. A stone carving from ], dating back from around 1500&nbsp;BCE and now at the ] in Paris, depicts&nbsp;276 as 2&nbsp;hundreds, 7&nbsp;tens, and 6&nbsp;ones; and similarly for the number&nbsp;4,622. The ]ns had a ] system based essentially on the numerals for&nbsp;1 and&nbsp;10, using base sixty, so that the symbol for sixty was the same as the symbol for one—its value being determined from context.<ref>{{cite book |first=Georges |last=Ifrah |year=2000 |title=The Universal History of Numbers |publisher=Wiley |isbn=0-471-37568-3}}</ref>
The most primitive method of representing a natural number is to put down a mark for each object. Later, a set of objects could be tested for equality, excess or shortage, by striking out a mark and removing an object from the set.


A much later advance was the development of the idea that&nbsp;{{num|0}} can be considered as a number, with its own numeral. The use of a&nbsp;0 ] in place-value notation (within other numbers) dates back as early as 700&nbsp;BCE by the Babylonians, who omitted such a digit when it would have been the last symbol in the number.{{efn| A tablet found at Kish ... thought to date from around 700&nbsp;BC, uses three hooks to denote an empty place in the positional notation. Other tablets dated from around the same time use a single hook for an empty place.<ref>{{cite web |title=A history of Zero |website=MacTutor History of Mathematics |url=http://www-history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/history/HistTopics/Zero.html |url-status=live |access-date=23 January 2013 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130119083234/http://www-history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/history/HistTopics/Zero.html |archive-date=19 January 2013}}</ref>}} The ] and ]s used&nbsp;0 as a separate number as early as the {{nowrap|1st century BCE}}, but this usage did not spread beyond ].<ref>{{cite book |first=Charles C. |last=Mann |year=2005 |title=1491: New Revelations of the Americas before Columbus |page=19 |publisher=Knopf |isbn=978-1-4000-4006-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Jw2TE_UNHJYC&pg=PA19 |url-status=live |via=Google Books |access-date=3 February 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150514105855/https://books.google.com/books?id=Jw2TE_UNHJYC&pg=PA19 |archive-date=14 May 2015}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |first=Brian |last=Evans |year=2014 |title=The Development of Mathematics Throughout the Centuries: A brief history in a cultural context |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-118-85397-9 |chapter=Chapter 10. Pre-Columbian Mathematics: The Olmec, Maya, and Inca Civilizations |via=Google Books |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3CPwAgAAQBAJ&pg=PT73}}</ref> The use of a numeral&nbsp;0 in modern times originated with the Indian mathematician ] in 628&nbsp;CE. However, 0 had been used as a number in the medieval ] (the calculation of the date of Easter), beginning with ] in 525&nbsp;CE, without being denoted by a numeral. Standard ] do not have a symbol for&nbsp;0; instead, ''nulla'' (or the genitive form ''nullae'') from {{Lang|la|nullus}}, the Latin word for "none", was employed to denote a&nbsp;0 value.<ref>{{cite web |first=Michael |last=Deckers |title=Cyclus Decemnovennalis Dionysii – Nineteen year cycle of Dionysius |url=http://hbar.phys.msu.ru/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm |publisher=Hbar.phys.msu.ru |date=25 August 2003 |access-date=13 February 2012 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190115083618/http://hbar.phys.msu.ru/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm |archive-date=15 January 2019 |url-status=live }}</ref>
The first major advance in abstraction was the use of ] to represent numbers. This allowed systems to be developed for recording large numbers. The ancient ] developed a powerful system of numerals with distinct ] for&nbsp;1, 10, and all the powers of&nbsp;10 up to over 1&nbsp;million. A stone carving from ], dating from around 1500&nbsp;BC and now at the ] in Paris, depicts&nbsp;276 as 2&nbsp;hundreds, 7&nbsp;tens, and 6&nbsp;ones; and similarly for the number&nbsp;4,622. The ]ns had a ] system based essentially on the numerals for&nbsp;1 and&nbsp;10, using base sixty, so that the symbol for sixty was the same as the symbol for one, its value being determined from context.<ref>Georges Ifrah, ''The Universal History of Numbers'', Wiley, 2000, ISBN 0-471-37568-3</ref>


The first systematic study of numbers as ]s is usually credited to the ] philosophers ] and ]. Some Greek mathematicians treated the number&nbsp;1 differently than larger numbers, sometimes even not as a number at all.{{efn|This convention is used, for example, in ], see D.&nbsp;Joyce's web edition of Book VII.<ref name=EuclidVIIJoyce>{{cite book |author=Euclid |author-link=Euclid |editor-first=D. |editor-last=Joyce|editor-link=David E. Joyce (mathematician) |chapter=Book VII, definitions 1 and 2 |title=] |publisher=Clark University |chapter-url=http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookVII/defVII1.html }}</ref>}} ], for example, defined a unit first and then a number as a multitude of units, thus by his definition, a unit is not a number and there are no unique numbers (e.g., any two units from indefinitely many units is a 2).<ref name="Mueller 2006 p. 58">{{cite book |last=Mueller |first=Ian |year=2006 |title=Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in ] |page=58 |publisher=Dover Publications |location=Mineola, New York |isbn=978-0-486-45300-2 |oclc=69792712}}</ref> However, in the definition of ] which comes shortly afterward, Euclid treats 1 as a number like any other.<ref>{{cite book |author=Euclid |author-link=Euclid |editor-first=D. |editor-last=Joyce |chapter=Book VII, definition 22 |title=] |publisher=Clark University |chapter-url=http://aleph0.clarku.edu/~djoyce/java/elements/bookVII/defVII22.html |quote=A perfect number is that which is equal to the sum of its own parts. }} In definition VII.3 a "part" was defined as a number, but here 1 is considered to be a part, so that for example {{math|1=6 = 1 + 2 + 3}} is a perfect number.</ref>
A much later advance was the development of the idea that&nbsp;{{num|0}} can be considered as a number, with its own numeral. The use of a&nbsp;0 ] in place-value notation (within other numbers) dates back as early as 700&nbsp;BC by the Babylonians, but they omitted such a digit when it would have been the last symbol in the number.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www-history.mcs.st-and.ac.uk/history/HistTopics/Zero.html |title=A history of Zero |quote=... a tablet found at Kish ... thought to date from around 700 BC, uses three hooks to denote an empty place in the positional notation. Other tablets dated from around the same time use a single hook for an empty place |website=MacTutor History of Mathematics |accessdate=2013-01-23}}</ref> The ] and ]s used&nbsp;0 as a separate number as early as the {{nowrap|1st century BC}}, but this usage did not spread beyond ].<ref>{{citation|title=1491: New Revelations Of The Americas Before Columbus|first=Charles C.|last=Mann|publisher=Knopf|year=2005|isbn=9781400040063|page=19|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Jw2TE_UNHJYC&pg=PA19}}.</ref><ref>{{citation|title=The Development of Mathematics Throughout the Centuries: A Brief History in a Cultural Context|first=Brian|last=Evans|publisher=John Wiley & Sons|year=2014|isbn=9781118853979|contribution=Chapter 10. Pre-Columbian Mathematics: The Olmec, Maya, and Inca Civilizations|contribution-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3CPwAgAAQBAJ&pg=PT73}}.</ref> The use of a numeral&nbsp;0 in modern times originated with the ]n mathematician ] in 628. However, 0 had been used as a number in the medieval ] (the calculation of the date of ]), beginning with ] in 525, without being denoted by a numeral (standard ] do not have a symbol for&nbsp;0); instead ''nulla'' (or the genitive form ''nullae'') from ''nullus'', the Latin word for "none", was employed to denote a&nbsp;0 value.<ref>{{cite web |author=Michael L. Gorodetsky |url=http://hbar.phys.msu.ru/gorm/chrono/paschata.htm |title=Cyclus Decemnovennalis Dionysii – Nineteen year cycle of Dionysius |publisher=Hbar.phys.msu.ru |date=2003-08-25 |accessdate=2012-02-13}}</ref>


Independent studies on numbers also occurred at around the same time in ], China, and ].<ref>{{cite book |first=Morris |last=Kline |year=1990 |orig-year=1972 |title=Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=0-19-506135-7}}</ref>
The first systematic study of numbers as ]s is usually credited to the ] philosophers ] and ]. Some Greek mathematicians treated the number&nbsp;1 differently than larger numbers, sometimes even not as a number at all.<ref>This convention is used, for example, in ], see .</ref>


===Emergence as a term===
Independent studies also occurred at around the same time in ], ], and ].<ref>Morris Kline, ''Mathematical Thought From Ancient to Modern Times'', Oxford University Press, 1990 , ISBN 0-19-506135-7</ref>
] used the term ''progression naturelle'' (natural progression) in 1484.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Chuquet |first1=Nicolas|author-link=Nicolas Chuquet |title=Le Triparty en la science des nombres|date=1881 |orig-date=1484 |url=https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k62599266/f75.image |language=fr}}</ref> The earliest known use of "natural number" as a complete English phrase is in 1763.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Emerson |first1=William |title=The method of increments|date=1763 |page=113 |url=https://archive.org/details/bim_eighteenth-century_the-method-of-increments_emerson-william_1763/page/112/mode/2up}}</ref><ref name="MacTutor"/> The 1771 Encyclopaedia Britannica defines natural numbers in the logarithm article.<ref name="MacTutor">{{cite web |title=Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (N) |url=https://mathshistory.st-andrews.ac.uk/Miller/mathword/n/ |website=Maths History |language=en}}</ref>


Starting at 0 or 1 has long been a matter of definition. In 1727, ] wrote that his notions of distance and element led to defining the natural numbers as including or excluding 0.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Fontenelle |first1=Bernard de |title=Eléments de la géométrie de l'infini |date=1727 |page=3 |url=https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k64762n/f31.item |language=fr}}</ref> In 1889, ] used N for the positive integers and started at 1,<ref>{{cite book |title=Arithmetices principia: nova methodo |date=1889 |publisher=Fratres Bocca |url=https://archive.org/details/arithmeticespri00peangoog/page/n12/mode/2up|page=12 |language=Latin}}</ref> but he later changed to using N<sub>0</sub> and N<sub>1</sub>.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Peano |first1=Giuseppe |title=Formulaire des mathematiques |date=1901 |publisher=Paris, Gauthier-Villars |page=39 |url=https://archive.org/details/formulairedesmat00pean/page/38/mode/2up|language=fr}}</ref> Historically, most definitions have excluded 0,<ref name="MacTutor"/><ref>{{cite book |last1=Fine |first1=Henry Burchard |title=A College Algebra |date=1904 |publisher=Ginn |page=6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=RR4PAAAAIAAJ&dq=%22natural%20number%22&pg=PA6 |language=en}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |title=Advanced Algebra: A Study Guide to be Used with USAFI Course MC 166 Or CC166 |date=1958 |publisher=United States Armed Forces Institute |page=12 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=184i06Py1ZYC&dq=%22natural%20number%22%201&pg=PA12 |language=en}}</ref> but many mathematicians such as ], ], ], ], ], and ] have preferred to include 0.<ref>{{cite web |title=Natural Number |url=https://archive.lib.msu.edu/crcmath/math/math/n/n035.htm |website=archive.lib.msu.edu}}</ref><ref name="MacTutor"/>
===Modern definitions===
{{refimprove section|date=October 2014}}


Mathematicians have noted tendencies in which definition is used, such as algebra texts including 0,<ref name="MacTutor"/>{{efn|name=MacLaneBirkhoff1999p15|{{harvtxt|Mac Lane|Birkhoff|1999|page=15}} include zero in the natural numbers: 'Intuitively, the set <math>\N=\{0,1,2,\ldots\}</math> of all ''natural numbers'' may be described as follows: <math>\N</math> contains an "initial" number {{math|0}}; ...'. They follow that with their version of the ].}} number theory and analysis texts excluding 0,<ref name="MacTutor"/><ref name="Křížek">{{cite book |last1=Křížek |first1=Michal |last2=Somer |first2=Lawrence |last3=Šolcová |first3=Alena |title=From Great Discoveries in Number Theory to Applications |date=21 September 2021 |publisher=Springer Nature |isbn=978-3-030-83899-7 |page=6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tklEEAAAQBAJ&dq=natural%20numbers%20zero&pg=PA6 |language=en}}</ref><ref>See, for example, {{harvtxt|Carothers|2000|p=3}} or {{harvtxt|Thomson|Bruckner|Bruckner|2008|p=2}}</ref> logic and set theory texts including 0,<ref>{{cite book |last1=Gowers |first1=Timothy |title=The Princeton companion to mathematics |date=2008 |publisher=Princeton university press |location=Princeton |isbn=978-0-691-11880-2 |page=17}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Bagaria |first1=Joan |title=Set Theory |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ |publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=Winter 2014 |year=2017 |access-date=13 February 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150314173026/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ |archive-date=14 March 2015 |url-status=live}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Goldrei |first1=Derek |title=Classic Set Theory: A guided independent study |url=https://archive.org/details/classicsettheory00gold |url-access=limited |date=1998 |publisher=Chapman & Hall/CRC |location=Boca Raton, Fla. |isbn=978-0-412-60610-6 |page= |edition=1. ed., 1. print|chapter=3}}</ref> dictionaries excluding 0,<ref name="MacTutor"/><ref>{{cite dictionary|url=http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/natural%20number|title=natural number|dictionary=Merriam-Webster.com|publisher=]|access-date=4 October 2014|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20191213133201/https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/natural%20number| archive-date=13 December 2019|url-status=live}}</ref> school books (through high-school level) excluding 0, and upper-division college-level books including 0.<ref name="Enderton">{{cite book |last1=Enderton |first1=Herbert B. |title=Elements of set theory |date=1977 |publisher=Academic Press |location=New York |isbn=0122384407 |page=66}}</ref> There are exceptions to each of these tendencies and as of 2023 no formal survey has been conducted. Arguments raised include ]<ref name="Křížek"/> and the size of the ]. ]s often ] when enumerating items like ] and ] or ].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Brown |first1=Jim |title=In defense of index origin 0 |journal=ACM SIGAPL APL Quote Quad |date=1978 |volume=9 |issue=2 |page=7 |doi=10.1145/586050.586053|s2cid=40187000 }}</ref><ref>{{cite web |last1=Hui |first1=Roger |title=Is index origin 0 a hindrance? |url=http://www.jsoftware.com/papers/indexorigin.htm |website=jsoftware.com |access-date=19 January 2015 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20151020195547/http://www.jsoftware.com/papers/indexorigin.htm |archive-date=20 October 2015 |url-status=live}}</ref> Including 0 began to rise in popularity in the 1960s.<ref name="MacTutor"/> The ] standard included 0 in the natural numbers in its first edition in 1978 and this has continued through its present edition as ].<ref name=ISO80000/>
In ] ], there was mathematical and philosophical discussion about the exact nature of the natural numbers. A school of Naturalism stated that the natural numbers were a direct consequence of the human psyche. ] was one of its advocates, as was ] who summarized "God made the integers, all else is the work of man".


===Formal construction===
In opposition to the Naturalists, the constructivists saw a need to improve the logical rigor in the ].<ref>"Much of the mathematical work of the twentieth century has been devoted to examining the logical foundations and structure of the subject." {{harv|Eves|1990|p=606}}</ref> In the 1860s, ] suggested a recursive definition for natural numbers thus stating they were not really natural but a consequence of definitions. Later, two classes of such formal definitions were constructed; later, they were shown to be equivalent in most practical applications.


In 19th century Europe, there was mathematical and philosophical discussion about the exact nature of the natural numbers. ] stated that axioms can only be demonstrated in their finite application, and concluded that it is "the power of the mind" which allows conceiving of the indefinite repetition of the same act.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Poincaré |first1=Henri|translator1-first=William John|translator1-last= Greenstreet |title=La Science et l'hypothèse|trans-title=Science and Hypothesis|orig-date=1902|date=1905|chapter=On the nature of mathematical reasoning|chapter-url=https://en.wikisource.org/Science_and_Hypothesis/Chapter_1|at=VI}}</ref> ] summarized his belief as "God made the integers, all else is the work of man".{{efn|The English translation is from Gray. In a footnote, Gray attributes the German quote to: "Weber 1891–1892, 19, quoting from a lecture of Kronecker's of 1886."<ref>{{cite book
] were initiated by ] and he initially defined a natural number as the class of all sets that are in one-to-one correspondence with a particular set, but this definition turned out to lead to paradoxes including ]. Therefore, this formalism was modified so that a natural number is defined as a particular set, and any set that can be put into one-to-one correspondence with that set is said to have that number of elements.<ref>{{harvnb|Eves|1990|loc=Chapter 15}}</ref>
|last=Gray |first=Jeremy |author-link=Jeremy Gray
|year=2008
|title=Plato's Ghost: The modernist transformation of mathematics
|page=153
|publisher=Princeton University Press
|isbn=978-1-4008-2904-0
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ldzseiuZbsIC&q=%22God+made+the+integers%2C+all+else+is+the+work+of+man.%22
|url-status=live
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170329150904/https://books.google.com/books?id=ldzseiuZbsIC&q=%22God+made+the+integers%2C+all+else+is+the+work+of+man.%22#v=snippet&q=%22God%20made%20the%20integers%2C%20all%20else%20is%20the%20work%20of%20man.%22&f=false
|archive-date=29 March 2017
}}</ref><ref>{{cite book
|last=Weber |first=Heinrich L.
|year=1891–1892
|chapter=Kronecker
|chapter-url=http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PPN=PPN37721857X_0002&DMDID=dmdlog6
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180809110042/http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/img/?PPN=PPN37721857X_0002&DMDID=dmdlog6
|archive-date=9 August 2018
|title=''Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung''
|trans-title=Annual report of the German Mathematicians Association
|pages=2:5–23. (The quote is on p.&nbsp;19)
|postscript=;
}} {{cite web
|title=access to ''Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung''
|url=http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/toc/?PPN=PPN37721857X_0002
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170820201100/http://www.digizeitschriften.de/dms/toc/?PPN=PPN37721857X_0002
|archive-date=20 August 2017
}}</ref>}}


The ] saw a need to improve upon the logical rigor in the ].{{efn|"Much of the mathematical work of the twentieth century has been devoted to examining the logical foundations and structure of the subject." {{harv|Eves|1990|p=606}} }} In the 1860s, ] suggested a ] for natural numbers, thus stating they were not really natural—but a consequence of definitions. Later, two classes of such formal definitions emerged, using set theory and Peano's axioms respectively. Later still, they were shown to be equivalent in most practical applications.
The second class of definitions was introduced by ] and is now called ]. It is based on an ] of the properties of ]s: each natural number has a successor and every non-zero natural number has a unique predecessor. Peano arithmetic is ] with several weak systems of set theory. One such system is ] with the ] replaced by its negation. Theorems that can be proved in ZFC but cannot be proved using the Peano Axioms include ].<ref>L. Kirby; J. Paris, ''Accessible Independence Results for Peano Arithmetic'', Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society 14 (4): 285. doi:10.1112/blms/14.4.285, 1982.</ref>


] were initiated by ]. He initially defined a natural number as the class of all sets that are in one-to-one correspondence with a particular set. However, this definition turned out to lead to paradoxes, including ]. To avoid such paradoxes, the formalism was modified so that a natural number is defined as a particular set, and any set that can be put into one-to-one correspondence with that set is said to have that number of elements.<ref>{{harvnb|Eves|1990|loc=Chapter 15}}</ref>
With all these definitions it is convenient to include&nbsp;0 (corresponding to the ]) as a natural number. Including&nbsp;0 is now the common convention among ]<ref>{{cite web|last1=Bagaria|first1=Joan|title=Set Theory|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/|publisher=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition)}}</ref> and ]ians.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Goldrei|first1=Derek|title=Classic set theory : a guided independent study|date=1998|publisher=Chapman & Hall/CRC|location=Boca Raton, Fla. |isbn=0-412-60610-0|page=33|edition=1. ed., 1. print|chapter=3}}</ref> Other mathematicians also include&nbsp;0<ref name="Mac Lane & Birkhoff 1999 p15" /> although many have kept the older tradition and take&nbsp;1 to be the first natural number.<ref>This is common in texts about ]. See, for example, {{harvtxt|Carothers|2000|p=3}} or {{harvtxt|Thomson|Bruckner|Bruckner|2000|p=2}}.</ref> ]s often ] when enumerating items like loop counters and string- or array- elements.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Brown|first1=Jim|title=In Defense of Index Origin 0|journal=ACM SIGAPL APL Quote Quad|date=1978|volume=9|issue=2|pages=7 - 7|doi=10.1145/586050.586053|url=http://dl.acm.org/citation.cfm?id=586053|accessdate=19 January 2015}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|last1=Hui|first1=Roger|title=Is Index Origin 0 a Hindrance?|url=http://www.jsoftware.com/papers/indexorigin.htm|website=http://www.jsoftware.com|publisher=JSoftware / Roger Hui|accessdate=19 January 2015}}</ref>

In 1881, ] provided the first ] of natural-number arithmetic.<ref>{{cite journal|last= Peirce|first= C.&nbsp;S.|author-link= Charles Sanders Peirce|year= 1881|title= On the Logic of Number|url= https://archive.org/details/jstor-2369151|journal= American Journal of Mathematics|volume= 4|issue= 1|pages= 85–95|doi= 10.2307/2369151|mr= 1507856|jstor= 2369151}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|last= Shields|first= Paul|year= 1997|title= Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce|url= https://archive.org/details/studiesinlogicof00nath|url-access= registration|chapter= 3. Peirce's Axiomatization of Arithmetic|chapter-url= https://books.google.com/books?id=pWjOg-zbtMAC&pg=PA43|editor1-last= Houser
|editor1-first= Nathan|editor2-last= Roberts|editor2-first= Don D.|editor3-last= Van Evra|editor3-first= James|publisher= Indiana University Press|isbn= 0-253-33020-3|pages= 43–52}}</ref> In 1888, ] proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic,<ref>{{cite book |title=Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? |date=1893 |publisher=F. Vieweg |url=https://archive.org/details/wassindundwasso00dedegoog/page/n42/mode/2up |language=German|at=71–73}}</ref> and in&nbsp;1889, Peano published a simplified version of Dedekind's axioms in his book ''The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method'' ({{langx|la|]}}). This approach is now called ]. It is based on an ] of the properties of ]s: each natural number has a successor and every non-zero natural number has a unique predecessor. Peano arithmetic is ] with several weak systems of ]. One such system is ] with the ] replaced by its negation.<ref>{{cite journal
| last1 = Baratella | first1 = Stefano
| last2 = Ferro | first2 = Ruggero
| doi = 10.1002/malq.19930390138
| issue = 3
| journal = Mathematical Logic Quarterly
| mr = 1270381
| pages = 338–352
| title = A theory of sets with the negation of the axiom of infinity
| volume = 39
| year = 1993}}</ref> Theorems that can be proved in ZFC but cannot be proved using the Peano Axioms include ].<ref>{{cite journal | last1=Kirby | first1=Laurie | last2=Paris | first2=Jeff | title=Accessible Independence Results for Peano Arithmetic | journal=Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society | publisher=Wiley | volume=14 | issue=4 | year=1982 | issn=0024-6093 | doi=10.1112/blms/14.4.285 | pages=285–293}}</ref>


==Notation== ==Notation==
The ] of all natural numbers is standardly denoted {{math|'''N'''}} or <math>\mathbb N.</math><ref name=":1"/><ref>{{cite web |title=Listing of the Mathematical Notations used in the Mathematical Functions Website: Numbers, variables, and functions |url=https://functions.wolfram.com/Notations/1/ |access-date=27 July 2020 |website=functions.wolfram.com}}</ref> Older texts have occasionally employed {{math|''J''}} as the symbol for this set.<ref>{{cite book |url=https://archive.org/details/1979RudinW |title=Principles of Mathematical Analysis |last=Rudin |first=W. |publisher=McGraw-Hill |year=1976 |isbn=978-0-07-054235-8 |location=New York |page=25}}</ref>
]).]]

Mathematicians use '''N''' or <math>\mathbb{N}</math> (an N in ], displayed as {{unicode|ℕ}} in ]) to refer to the ] of all natural numbers. This set is ]: it is ] but ] by definition. This is also expressed by saying that the ] of the set is ] <math>(\aleph_0)</math>.<ref>{{MathWorld |urlname=CardinalNumber |title=Cardinal Number}}</ref>
Since natural numbers may contain {{math|0}} or not, it may be important to know which version is referred to. This is often specified by the context, but may also be done by using a subscript or a superscript in the notation, such as:<ref name="ISO80000"/><ref name="Grimaldi">{{cite book |last1=Grimaldi |first1=Ralph P. |title=Discrete and Combinatorial Mathematics: An applied introduction |publisher=Pearson Addison Wesley |isbn=978-0-201-72634-3 |edition=5th |year=2004}}</ref>
* Naturals without zero: <math>\{1,2,...\}=\mathbb{N}^*= \mathbb N^+=\mathbb{N}_0\smallsetminus\{0\} = \mathbb{N}_1</math>
* Naturals with zero: <math>\;\{0,1,2,...\}=\mathbb{N}_0=\mathbb N^0=\mathbb{N}^*\cup\{0\}</math>

Alternatively, since the natural numbers naturally form a ] of the ]s (often {{nowrap|denoted <math>\mathbb Z</math>),}} they may be referred to as the positive, or the non-negative integers, respectively.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Grimaldi |first1=Ralph P. |title=A review of discrete and combinatorial mathematics |date=2003 |publisher=Addison-Wesley |location=Boston |isbn=978-0-201-72634-3 |page=133 |edition=5th}}</ref> To be unambiguous about whether 0 is included or not, sometimes a superscript "<math>*</math>" or "+" is added in the former case, and a subscript (or superscript) "0" is added in the latter case:<ref name=ISO80000 >{{cite book |title=ISO 80000-2:2019 |chapter-url=https://cdn.standards.iteh.ai/samples/64973/329519100abd447ea0d49747258d1094/ISO-80000-2-2019.pdf#page=10 |publisher=]| chapter = Standard number sets and intervals | date=19 May 2020 |page=4|url=https://www.iso.org/standard/64973.html}}</ref>


:<math>\{1, 2, 3,\dots\} = \{x \in \mathbb Z : x > 0\}=\mathbb Z^+= \mathbb{Z}_{>0}</math>
To be unambiguous about whether 0 is included or not, sometimes an index (or superscript) "0" is added in the former case, and a superscript "<math>*</math>" or subscript "<math>1</math>" is added in the latter case:{{citation needed|date=May 2013}}
:<math>\mathbb{N}^0 = \mathbb{N}_0 = \{ 0, 1, 2, \ldots \}</math> :<math>\{0, 1, 2,\dots\} = \{x \in \mathbb Z : x \ge 0\}=\mathbb Z^{+}_{0}=\mathbb{Z}_ {\ge 0}</math>
:<math>\mathbb{N}^* = \mathbb{N}^+ = \mathbb{N}_1 = \mathbb{N}_{>0}= \{ 1, 2, \ldots \}. </math>


==Properties== ==Properties==
This section uses the convention <math>\mathbb{N}=\mathbb{N}_0=\mathbb{N}^*\cup\{0\}</math>.


===Addition=== ===Addition===
One can recursively define an ] on the natural numbers by setting {{nowrap|''a'' + 0 {{=}} ''a''}} and {{nowrap|''a'' + ''S''(''b'') {{=}} ''S''(''a'' + ''b'')}} for all ''a'', ''b''. Here ''S'' should be read as "successor". This turns the natural numbers ('''N''',&nbsp;+) into a ] ] with ]&nbsp;0, the so-called ] with one generator. This monoid satisfies the ] and can be embedded in a ] (in the mathematical sense of the word ''group''). The smallest group containing the natural numbers is the ]s. Given the set <math>\mathbb{N}</math> of natural numbers and the ] <math>S \colon \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N}</math> sending each natural number to the next one, one can define ] of natural numbers recursively by setting {{math|''a'' + 0 {{=}} ''a''}} and {{math|''a'' + ''S''(''b'') {{=}} ''S''(''a'' + ''b'')}} for all {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}}. Thus, {{math|''a'' + 1 {{=}} ''a'' + S(0) {{=}} S(''a''+0) {{=}} S(''a'')}}, {{math|''a'' + 2 {{=}} ''a'' + S(1) {{=}} S(''a''+1) {{=}} S(S(''a''))}}, and so on. The ] <math>(\mathbb{N}, +)</math> is a ] ] with ]&nbsp;0. It is a ] on one generator. This commutative monoid satisfies the ], so it can be embedded in a ]. The smallest group containing the natural numbers is the ]s.


If 1 is defined as ''S''(0), then {{nowrap|''b'' + 1 {{=}} ''b'' + ''S''(0) {{=}} ''S''(''b'' + 0) {{=}} ''S''(''b'')}}. That is, {{nowrap|''b'' + 1}} is simply the successor of ''b''. If 1 is defined as {{math|''S''(0)}}, then {{math|''b'' + 1 {{=}} ''b'' + ''S''(0) {{=}} ''S''(''b'' + 0) {{=}} ''S''(''b'')}}. That is, {{math|''b'' + 1}} is simply the successor of {{math|''b''}}.


===Multiplication=== ===Multiplication===
Analogously, given that addition has been defined, a ] × can be defined via {{nowrap|''a'' × 0 {{=}} 0}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × S(''b'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + ''a''}}. This turns ('''N'''<sup>*</sup>,&nbsp;×) into a free commutative monoid with identity element&nbsp;1; a generator set for this monoid is the set of ]s. Analogously, given that addition has been defined, a ] operator <math>\times</math> can be defined via {{math|''a'' × 0 {{=}} 0}} and {{math|''a'' × S(''b'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + ''a''}}. This turns <math>(\mathbb{N}^*, \times)</math> into a ] with identity element&nbsp;1; a generator set for this monoid is the set of ]s.


===Relationship between addition and multiplication=== ===Relationship between addition and multiplication===
Addition and multiplication are compatible, which is expressed in the ]: {{nowrap|''a'' × (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + (''a'' × ''c'')}}. These properties of addition and multiplication make the natural numbers an instance of a ] ]. Semirings are an algebraic generalization of the natural numbers where multiplication is not necessarily commutative. The lack of additive inverses, which is equivalent to the fact that '''N''' is not closed under subtraction, means that '''N''' is ''not'' a ]; instead it is a ] (also known as a ''rig''). Addition and multiplication are compatible, which is expressed in the ]: {{math|''a'' × (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + (''a'' × ''c'')}}. These properties of addition and multiplication make the natural numbers an instance of a ] ]. Semirings are an algebraic generalization of the natural numbers where multiplication is not necessarily commutative. The lack of additive inverses, which is equivalent to the fact that <math>\mathbb{N}</math> is not ] under subtraction (that is, subtracting one natural from another does not always result in another natural), means that <math>\mathbb{N}</math> is ''not'' a ]; instead it is a ] (also known as a ''rig'').


If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", the definitions of + and × are as above, except that they begin with {{nowrap|''a'' + 1 {{=}} ''S''(''a'')}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × 1 {{=}} ''a''}}. If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", the definitions of + and × are as above, except that they begin with {{math|''a'' + 1 {{=}} ''S''(''a'')}} and {{math|''a'' × 1 {{=}} ''a''}}. Furthermore, <math>(\mathbb{N^*}, +)</math> has no identity element.


===Order=== ===Order===
In this section, juxtaposed variables such as ''ab'' indicate the product ''a'' × ''b'', and the standard ] is assumed. In this section, juxtaposed variables such as {{math|''ab''}} indicate the product {{math|''a'' × ''b''}},<ref>{{Cite web |last=Weisstein |first=Eric W. |title=Multiplication |url=https://mathworld.wolfram.com/Multiplication.html |access-date=27 July 2020 |website=mathworld.wolfram.com |language=en}}</ref> and the standard ] is assumed.


A ] on the natural numbers is defined by letting {{nowrap|''a'' ≤ ''b''}} if and only if there exists another natural number ''c'' with {{nowrap|''a'' + ''c'' {{=}} ''b''}}. This order is compatible with the ] in the following sense: if ''a'', ''b'' and ''c'' are natural numbers and {{nowrap|''a'' ≤ ''b''}}, then {{nowrap|''a'' + ''c'' ≤ ''b'' + ''c''}} and {{nowrap|''ac'' ≤ ''bc''}}. An important property of the natural numbers is that they are ]ed: every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least element. The rank among well-ordered sets is expressed by an ]; for the natural numbers this is expressed as ''ω''. A ] on the natural numbers is defined by letting {{math|''a'' ≤ ''b''}} if and only if there exists another natural number {{math|''c''}} where {{math|''a'' + ''c'' {{=}} ''b''}}. This order is compatible with the ] in the following sense: if {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}} and {{math|''c''}} are natural numbers and {{math|''a'' ≤ ''b''}}, then {{math|''a'' + ''c'' ≤ ''b'' + ''c''}} and {{math|''ac'' ≤ ''bc''}}.
An important property of the natural numbers is that they are ]ed: every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least element. The rank among well-ordered sets is expressed by an ]; for the natural numbers, this is denoted as {{math|]}} (omega).


===Division=== ===Division===
In this section, juxtaposed variables such as ''ab'' indicate the product ''a'' × ''b'', and the standard ] is assumed. In this section, juxtaposed variables such as {{math|''ab''}} indicate the product {{math|''a'' × ''b''}}, and the standard ] is assumed.


While it is in general not possible to divide one natural number by another and get a natural number as result, the procedure of ''] with remainder'' is available as a substitute: for any two natural numbers ''a'' and ''b'' with {{nowrap|''b'' ≠ 0}} there are natural numbers ''q'' and ''r'' such that While it is in general not possible to divide one natural number by another and get a natural number as result, the procedure of ''division with remainder'' or ] is available as a substitute: for any two natural numbers {{math|''a''}} and {{math|''b''}} with {{math|''b'' ≠ 0}} there are natural numbers {{math|''q''}} and {{math|''r''}} such that
:''a'' = ''bq'' + ''r'' and ''r'' < ''b''. :<math>a = bq + r \text{ and } r < b. </math>


The number ''q'' is called the '']'' and ''r'' is called the '']'' of division of ''a'' by&nbsp;''b''. The numbers ''q'' and ''r'' are uniquely determined by ''a'' and&nbsp;''b''. This ] is key to several other properties (]), algorithms (such as the ]), and ideas in number theory. The number {{math|''q''}} is called the '']'' and {{math|''r''}} is called the '']'' of the division of {{math|''a''}} by&nbsp;{{math|''b''}}. The numbers {{math|''q''}} and {{math|''r''}} are uniquely determined by {{math|''a''}} and&nbsp;{{math|''b''}}. This Euclidean division is key to the several other properties (]), algorithms (such as the ]), and ideas in number theory.


===Algebraic properties satisfied by the natural numbers=== ===Algebraic properties satisfied by the natural numbers===
The addition (+) and multiplication (×) operations on natural numbers as defined above have several algebraic properties: The addition (+) and multiplication (×) operations on natural numbers as defined above have several algebraic properties:
* ] under addition and multiplication: for all natural numbers ''a'' and ''b'', both {{nowrap|''a'' + ''b''}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × ''b''}} are natural numbers. * ] under addition and multiplication: for all natural numbers {{math|''a''}} and {{math|''b''}}, both {{math|''a'' + ''b''}} and {{math|''a'' × ''b''}} are natural numbers.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Fletcher |first1=Harold |last2=Howell |first2=Arnold A. |date=9 May 2014 |title=Mathematics with Understanding |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=978-1-4832-8079-0 |page=116 |language=en |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7cPSBQAAQBAJ&q=Natural+numbers+closed&pg=PA116 |quote=...the set of natural numbers is closed under addition... set of natural numbers is closed under multiplication}}</ref>
* ]: for all natural numbers ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', {{nowrap|''a'' + (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' + ''b'') + ''c''}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × (''b'' × ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') × ''c''}}. * ]: for all natural numbers {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}}, and {{math|''c''}}, {{math|''a'' + (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' + ''b'') + ''c''}} and {{math|''a'' × (''b'' × ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') × ''c''}}.<ref>{{cite book |last=Davisson |first=Schuyler Colfax |title=College Algebra |date=1910 |publisher=Macmillian Company |page=2 |language=en |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E7oZAAAAYAAJ&q=Natural+numbers+associative&pg=PA2 |quote=Addition of natural numbers is associative.}}</ref>
* ]: for all natural numbers ''a'' and ''b'', {{nowrap|''a'' + ''b'' {{=}} ''b'' + ''a''}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × ''b'' {{=}} ''b'' × ''a''}}. * ]: for all natural numbers {{math|''a''}} and {{math|''b''}}, {{math|''a'' + ''b'' {{=}} ''b'' + ''a''}} and {{math|''a'' × ''b'' {{=}} ''b'' × ''a''}}.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Brandon |first1=Bertha (M.) |last2=Brown |first2=Kenneth E. |last3=Gundlach |first3=Bernard H. |last4=Cooke |first4=Ralph J. |date=1962 |title=Laidlaw mathematics series |publisher=Laidlaw Bros. |volume=8 |page=25 |language=en |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=xERMAQAAIAAJ&q=Natural+numbers+commutative}}</ref>
* Existence of ]s: for every natural number ''a'', {{nowrap|''a'' + 0 {{=}} ''a''}} and {{nowrap|''a'' × 1 {{=}} ''a''}}. * Existence of ]s: for every natural number {{Math|''a''}}, {{math|''a'' + 0 {{=}} ''a''}} and {{math|''a'' × 1 {{=}} ''a''}}.
** If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", then for every natural number {{Math|''a''}}, {{math|''a'' × 1 {{=}} ''a''}}. However, the "existence of additive identity element" property is not satisfied
* ] of multiplication over addition for all natural numbers ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'', {{nowrap|''a'' × (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + (''a'' × ''c'')}}.
* No nonzero ]s: if ''a'' and ''b'' are natural numbers such that {{nowrap|''a'' × ''b'' {{=}} 0}}, then {{nowrap|''a'' {{=}} 0}} or {{nowrap|''b'' {{=}} 0}}. * ] of multiplication over addition for all natural numbers {{math|''a''}}, {{math|''b''}}, and {{math|''c''}}, {{math|''a'' × (''b'' + ''c'') {{=}} (''a'' × ''b'') + (''a'' × ''c'')}}.
* No nonzero ]s: if {{math|''a''}} and {{math|''b''}} are natural numbers such that {{math|''a'' × ''b'' {{=}} 0}}, then {{math|''a'' {{=}} 0}} or {{math|''b'' {{=}} 0}} (or both).


==Generalizations== ==Generalizations==
Two generalizations of natural numbers arise from the two uses: Two important generalizations of natural numbers arise from the two uses of counting and ordering: ]s and ]s.
* A natural number can be used to express the size of a finite set; more generally a ] is a measure for the size of a set also suitable for infinite sets; this refers to a concept of "size" such that if there is a ] between two sets they have ]. The set of natural numbers itself and any other countably infinite set has ] ] (<math>\aleph_0</math>). * A natural number can be used to express the size of a finite set; more precisely, a cardinal number is a measure for the size of a set, which is even suitable for infinite sets. The numbering of cardinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the ] <math>\emptyset</math>. This concept of "size" relies on maps between sets, such that two sets have ], exactly if there exists a ] between them. The set of natural numbers itself, and any bijective image of it, is said to be '']'' and to have ] ] ({{math|{{not a typo|ℵ}}<sub>0</sub>}}).
* ] "first", "second", "third" can be assigned to the elements of a totally ordered finite set, and also to the elements of well-ordered countably infinite sets like the set of natural numbers itself. This can be generalized to ]s which describe the position of an element in a ] set in general. An ordinal number is also used to describe the "size" of a well-ordered set, in a sense different from cardinality: if there is an ] between two well-ordered sets they have the same ordinal number. The first ordinal number that is not a natural number is expressed as <math>\omega</math>; this is also the ordinal number of the set of natural numbers itself. * Natural numbers are also used as ]: "first", "second", "third", and so forth. The numbering of ordinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the order type of the ] <math>\emptyset</math>. This way they can be assigned to the elements of a totally ordered finite set, and also to the elements of any ]ed countably infinite set without ]. This assignment can be generalized to general well-orderings with a cardinality beyond countability, to yield the ordinal numbers. An ordinal number may also be used to describe the notion of "size" for a well-ordered set, in a sense different from cardinality: if there is an ] (more than a bijection) between two well-ordered sets, they have the same ordinal number. The first ordinal number that is not a natural number is expressed as {{math|ω}}; this is also the ordinal number of the set of natural numbers itself.


The least ordinal of cardinality {{math|{{not a typo|ℵ}}<sub>0</sub>}} (that is, the ] of {{math|{{not a typo|ℵ}}<sub>0</sub>}}) is {{math|ω}} but many well-ordered sets with cardinal number {{math|{{not a typo|ℵ}}<sub>0</sub>}} have an ordinal number greater than {{math|ω}}.
Many well-ordered sets with cardinal number <math>\aleph_0</math> have an ordinal number greater than <math>\omega</math> (the latter is the lowest possible). The least ordinal of cardinality <math>\aleph_0</math> (i.e., the ]) is <math>\omega</math>.


For ] well-ordered sets, there is one-to-one correspondence between ordinal and cardinal numbers; therefore they can both be expressed by the same natural number, the number of elements of the set. This number can also be used to describe the position of an element in a larger finite, or an infinite, ]. For ] well-ordered sets, there is a one-to-one correspondence between ordinal and cardinal numbers; therefore they can both be expressed by the same natural number, the number of elements of the set. This number can also be used to describe the position of an element in a larger finite, or an infinite, ].


A countable ] satisfying the Peano Arithmetic (i.e., the first-order Peano axioms) was developed by ] in 1933. The ] numbers are an uncountable model that can be constructed from the ordinary natural numbers via the ]. A countable ] satisfying the Peano Arithmetic (that is, the first-order Peano axioms) was developed by ] in 1933. The ] numbers are an uncountable model that can be constructed from the ordinary natural numbers via the ]. Other generalizations are discussed in {{section link|Number#Extensions of the concept}}.


] used to claim provocatively that ''The naïve integers don't fill up'' <math>\mathbb{N}</math>. Other generalizations are discussed in the article on ]s. ] used to claim provocatively that "The naïve integers don't fill up <math>\mathbb{N}</math>".<ref>{{cite journal |title=Approaches To Analysis With Infinitesimals Following Robinson, Nelson, And Others |journal=Real Analysis Exchange |date=2017 |volume=42 |issue=2 |pages=193–253 |doi=10.14321/realanalexch.42.2.0193|doi-access=free|arxiv=1703.00425 |last1=Fletcher |first1=Peter |last2=Hrbacek |first2=Karel |last3=Kanovei |first3=Vladimir |last4=Katz |first4=Mikhail G. |last5=Lobry |first5=Claude |last6=Sanders |first6=Sam }}</ref>


==Formal definitions== ==Formal definitions==

There are two standard methods for formally defining natural numbers. The first one, named for ], consists of an autonomous ] called ], based on few axioms called ].

The second definition is based on ]. It defines the natural numbers as specific ]s. More precisely, each natural number {{mvar|n}} is defined as an explicitly defined set, whose elements allow counting the elements of other sets, in the sense that the sentence "a set {{mvar|S}} has {{mvar|n}} elements" means that there exists a ] between the two sets {{mvar|n}} and {{mvar|S}}.

The sets used to define natural numbers satisfy Peano axioms. It follows that every ] that can be stated and proved in Peano arithmetic can also be proved in set theory. However, the two definitions are not equivalent, as there are theorems that can be stated in terms of Peano arithmetic and proved in set theory, which are not ''provable'' inside Peano arithmetic. A probable example is ].

The definition of the integers as sets satisfying Peano axioms provide a ] of Peano arithmetic inside set theory. An important consequence is that, if set theory is ] (as it is usually guessed), then Peano arithmetic is consistent. In other words, if a contradiction could be proved in Peano arithmetic, then set theory would be contradictory, and every theorem of set theory would be both true and wrong.


===Peano axioms=== ===Peano axioms===
{{Main|Peano axioms}} {{Main|Peano axioms}}


The five Peano axioms are the following:<ref>{{cite encyclopedia
Many properties of the natural numbers can be derived from the ].<ref>{{Citation
|editor-first=G.E. |editor-last=Mints
| url = http://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php/Peano_axioms
|title=Peano axioms
| author = G.E. Mints (originator)
|encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of Mathematics
| title = Peano axioms
|publisher=], in cooperation with the ]
| work = Encyclopedia of Mathematics
|url=http://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php/Peano_axioms
| publisher = ], in cooperation with the ]
| accessdate = 8 October 2014 |url-status=live |access-date=8 October 2014
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141013163028/http://www.encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php/Peano_axioms
}}
|archive-date=13 October 2014
</ref><ref>{{harvtxt|Hamilton|1988}} calls them "Peano's Postulates" and begins with "1.{{spaces|2}}0 is a natural number." (p. 117f)<br />
}}</ref>{{efn|{{harvtxt|Hamilton|1988|pages=117&nbsp;ff}} calls them "Peano's Postulates" and begins with "1.{{spaces|2}}0 is a natural number."<br/>
{{harvtxt|Halmos|1960}} uses the language of set theory instead of the language of arithmetic for his five axioms. He begins with "(I){{spaces|2}}<math>0 \in \omega</math> (where, of course, <math>0 = \varnothing</math>)" (<math>\omega</math> is the set of all natural numbers). (p. 46)<br />
{{harvtxt|Halmos|1960|page=46}} uses the language of set theory instead of the language of arithmetic for his five axioms. He begins with "(I){{spaces|2}}{{math|0 ∈ ω}} (where, of course, {{math|0 {{=}} ∅}}" ({{math|ω}} is the set of all natural numbers).<br/>
{{harvtxt|Morash|1991}} gives "a two-part axiom" in which the natural numbers begin with 1. (Section 10.1: ''An Axiomatization for the System of Positive Integers'') {{harvtxt|Morash|1991}} gives "a two-part axiom" in which the natural numbers begin with 1. (Section 10.1: ''An Axiomatization for the System of Positive Integers'')
}}
</ref>
* Axiom One: 0 is a natural number.
* Axiom Two: Every natural number has a successor.
* Axiom Three: 0 is not the successor of any natural number.
* Axiom Four: If the successor of x equals the successor of y, then x equals y.
* Axiom Five (the Axiom of ]): If a statement is true of 0, and if the truth of that statement for a number implies its truth for the successor of that number, then the statement is true for every natural number.


# 0 is a natural number.
These are not the original axioms published by Peano, but are named in his honor. Some forms of the Peano axioms have 1 in place of 0. In ordinary arithmetic, the successor of x is x + 1. Replacing Axiom Five by an axiom schema one obtains a (weaker) first-order theory called ''Peano Arithmetic.''
# Every natural number has a successor which is also a natural number.
# 0 is not the successor of any natural number.
# If the successor of <math> x </math> equals the successor of <math> y </math>, then <math> x</math> equals <math> y</math>.
# The ]: If a statement is true of 0, and if the truth of that statement for a number implies its truth for the successor of that number, then the statement is true for every natural number.


These are not the original axioms published by Peano, but are named in his honor. Some forms of the Peano axioms have 1 in place of 0. In ordinary arithmetic, the successor of <math> x</math> is <math> x + 1</math>.
===Constructions based on set theory===

===Set-theoretic definition===
{{Main|Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers}} {{Main|Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers}}
In the area of mathematics called ], a special case of the ] construction <ref name="von Neumann1923pp199-208">{{Harvnb|Von Neumann|1923}}</ref> defines the natural numbers as follows:
:Set 0 := {&nbsp;}, the ],
:and define ''S''(''a'') = ''a'' ∪ {''a''} for every set ''a''. ''S''(''a'') is the successor of ''a'', and ''S'' is called the ].
:By the ], there exists a set which contains 0 and is closed under the successor function. (Such sets are said to be `inductive'.) Then the intersection of all inductive sets is defined to be the set of natural numbers. It can be checked that the set of natural numbers satisfies the ].
:Each natural number is then equal to the set of all natural numbers less than it, so that
:*0 = {&nbsp;}
:*1 = {0} = {{&nbsp;}}
:*2 = {0, 1} = {0, {0}} = {{&nbsp;}, {{&nbsp;}}}
:*3 = {0, 1, 2} = {0, {0}, {0, {0}}} ={{&nbsp;}, {{&nbsp;}}, {{&nbsp;}, {{&nbsp;}}}}
:*''n'' = {0, 1, 2, ..., ''n''−2, ''n''−1} = {0, 1, 2, ..., ''n''−2} ∪ {''n''−1} = (''n''−1) ∪ {''n''−1} = ''S''(''n''−1)
:and so on.


Intuitively, the natural number {{mvar|n}} is the common property of all ]s that have {{mvar|n}} elements. So, it seems natural to define {{mvar|n}} as an ] under the relation "can be made in ]". This does not work in all ], as such an equivalence class would not be a set{{efn|In some set theories, e.g., ], a ] exists and Russel's paradox cannot be formulated.}} (because of ]). The standard solution is to define a particular set with {{mvar|n}} elements that will be called the natural number {{mvar|n}}.
With this definition, a natural number ''n'' is a particular set with ''n'' elements, and {{nowrap|''n'' ≤ ''m''}} if and only if ''n'' is a ] of ''m''.

The following definition was first published by ],<ref name="vonNeumann1923pp199-208">{{Harvp|von&nbsp;Neumann|1923}}</ref> although Levy attributes the idea to unpublished work of Zermelo in 1916.<ref name="Levy">{{harvp|Levy|1979|page=52}}</ref> As this definition extends to ] as a definition of ], the sets considered below are sometimes called ].

The definition proceeds as follows:
* Call {{math|0 {{=}} {{mset| }}}}, the ].
* Define the ''successor'' {{math|''S''(''a'')}} of any set {{mvar|a}} by {{math|''S''(''a'') {{=}} ''a'' ∪ {{mset|''a''}}}}.
* By the ], there exist sets which contain 0 and are ] under the successor function. Such sets are said to be ''inductive''. The intersection of all inductive sets is still an inductive set.
* This intersection is the set of the ''natural numbers''.

It follows that the natural numbers are defined iteratively as follows:
:*{{math|0 {{=}} {{mset| }}}},
:*{{math|1 {{=}} 0 ∪ {{mset|0}} {{=}} {{mset|0}} {{=}} {{mset|{{mset| }}}}}},
:*{{math|2 {{=}} 1 ∪ {{mset|1}} {{=}} {{mset|0, 1}} {{=}} {{mset|{{mset| }}, {{mset|{{mset| }}}}}}}},
:*{{math|3 {{=}} 2 ∪ {{mset|2}} {{=}} {{mset|0, 1, 2}}}} {{math|{{=}} {{mset|{{mset| }}, {{mset|{{mset| }}}}, {{mset|{{mset| }}, {{mset|{{mset| }}}}}}}}}},
:*{{math|''n'' {{=}} ''n''−1 ∪ {{mset|''n''−1}} {{=}} {{mset|0, 1, ..., ''n''−1}}}} {{math|{{=}} {{mset|{{mset| }}, {{mset|{{mset| }}}}, ..., {{mset|{{mset| }}, {{mset|{{mset| }}}}, ...}}}}}},
:* etc.

It can be checked that the natural numbers satisfy the ].

With this definition, given a natural number {{math|''n''}}, the sentence "a set {{mvar|S}} has {{mvar|n}} elements" can be formally defined as "there exists a ] from {{mvar|n}} to {{mvar|S}}." This formalizes the operation of ''counting'' the elements of {{mvar|S}}. Also, {{math|''n'' ≤ ''m''}} if and only if {{math|''n''}} is a ] of {{math|''m''}}. In other words, the ] defines the usual ] on the natural numbers. This order is a ].


It follows from the definition that each natural number is equal to the set of all natural numbers less than it. This definition, can be extended to the ] for defining all ]s, including the infinite ones: "each ordinal is the well-ordered set of all smaller ordinals."
Also, with this definition, different possible interpretations of notations like '''R'''<sup>''n''</sup> (''n-''tuples versus mappings of ''n'' into '''R''') coincide.


Even if one ] and therefore cannot accept that the set of all natural numbers exists, it is still possible to define any one of these sets. If one ], the natural numbers may not form a set. Nevertheless, the natural numbers can still be individually defined as above, and they still satisfy the Peano axioms.


There are other set theoretical constructions. In particular, ] provided a construction that is nowadays only of historical interest, and is sometimes referred to as '''{{vanchor|Zermelo ordinals}}'''.<ref name="Levy"/> It consists in defining {{math|0}} as the empty set, and {{math|''S''(''a'') {{=}} {{mset|''a''}}}}.
====Other constructions====
Although the standard construction is useful, it is not the only possible construction. ]'s construction goes as follows:
:one defines 0 = {{mset|&nbsp;}}
:and ''S''(''a'') = {{mset|''a''}},
:producing
:*0 = {{mset|&nbsp;}}
:*1 = {{mset|0}} ={{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}}}
:*2 = {{mset|1}} ={{mset|{{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}}}}}, etc.
:Each natural number is then equal to the set of the natural number preceding it.


With this definition each nonzero natural number is a ]. So, the property of the natural numbers to represent ] is not directly accessible; only the ordinal property (being the {{mvar|n}}th element of a sequence) is immediate. Unlike von Neumann's construction, the Zermelo ordinals do not extend to infinite ordinals.
It is also possible to define 0 = {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}}}
:and ''S''(''a'') = ''a'' ∪ {{mset|''a''}}
:producing
:*0 = {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}}}
:*1 = {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}, 0}} = {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}, {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}}}}}
:*2 = {{mset|{{mset|&nbsp;}}, 0, 1}}, etc.


==See also== ==See also==
{{Portal|Mathematics}} {{Portal|Mathematics}}
* {{annotated link|Canonical representation of a positive integer}}
* ]
* {{annotated link|Countable set}}
* ]
* ]&nbsp;– Function of the natural numbers in another set
* ]
* {{annotated link|Ordinal number}}
* ]
* {{annotated link|Cardinal number}}
* ]
* {{annotated link|Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers}}
* ] for other number systems (rational, real, complex etc.)
{{Classification of numbers}}


==Notes== ==Notes==
{{Reflist}} {{Notelist}}


==References== ==References==
{{refbegin}} {{Reflist|25em}}

* {{Citation |last=Bluman |first=Allan |year=2010 |title=Pre-Algebra DeMYSTiFieD |edition=Second |publisher=] |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=oRLc9r4bmSgC |accessdate= }}
==Bibliography==
* {{Citation |last=Carothers |first=N.L. |year=2000 |title=Real analysis |publisher=Cambridge University Press |publication-place= |isbn=0-521-49756-6 |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=4VFDVy1NFiAC&q=natural+numbers#v=onepage&q=%22natural%20numbers%22&f=false |accessdate= }}
{{refbegin|25em|small=yes}}
* {{Citation |last=Clapham |first=Christopher |last2=Nicholson |first2=James |year=2014 |title=The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics |publisher=Oxford University Press |edition=Fifth |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=c69GBAAAQBAJ |accessdate= }}
* {{cite book
* {{Citation |last=Dedekind |first=Richard |authorlink=Richard Dedekind |year=1963 |title=Essays on the Theory of Numbers |publisher=Dover |publication-place= |page= |isbn=0-486-21010-3 |url= |accessdate= }}
|last=Bluman |first=Allan
** {{Citation |last=Dedekind |first=Richard |authorlink=Richard Dedekind |year=2007 |title=Essays on the Theory of Numbers |publisher=Kessinger Publishing, LLC |publication-place= |page= |isbn=0-548-08985-X |url= |accessdate= }}
|year=2010 |edition=Second
* {{Citation |last=Eves |first=Howard |authorlink=Howard Eves |year=1990 |title=An Introduction to the History of Mathematics |edition=6th |publisher=Thomson |publication-place= |page= |isbn=978-0-03-029558-4 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=PXvwAAAAMAAJ |accessdate= }}
|title=Pre-Algebra DeMYSTiFieD
* {{Citation |last=Halmos |first=Paul |author-link=Paul Halmos |year=1960 |title=Naive Set Theory |edition= |publisher=Springer Science & Business Media |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=x6cZBQ9qtgoC&lpg=PP1&pg=PP1#v=onepage&q=peano%20axioms&f=false |accessdate= }}
|publisher=McGraw-Hill Professional
* {{Citation |last=Hamilton |first=A. G. |year=1988 |title=Logic for Mathematicians |edition=Revised |publisher=Cambridge University Press |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=TO098EjWT38C&q=peano%27s+postulates#v=snippet&q=peano%27s%20postulates&f=false |accessdate= }}
|isbn=978-0-07-174251-1
* {{Citation |last=James |first=Robert C. |last2=James |first2=Glenn |year=1992 |title=Mathematics Dictionary |edition=Fifth |publisher=Chapman & Hall |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=UyIfgBIwLMQC |accessdate= }}
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=oRLc9r4bmSgC
* {{Citation |last=Landau |first=Edmund |authorlink=Edmund Landau |year=1966 |title=Foundations of Analysis |edition=Third |publisher=Chelsea Pub Co |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=DvIJBAAAQBAJ |isbn=0-8218-2693-X|accessdate= }}
|via=Google Books
* {{Citation |last=Mac Lane |first=Saunders | author-link=Saunders Mac Lane |last2=Birkhoff |first2=Garrett |author-link2=Garrett Birkhoff |year=1999 |title=Algebra |edition=3rd |publisher=American Mathematical Society |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=L6FENd8GHIUC&lpg=PA15&vq=natural%20numbers&pg=PA15#v=onepage&q=%22the%20natural%20numbers%22&f=false |accessdate= }}
}}
* {{Citation |last=Mendelson |first=Elliott |authorlink=Elliott Mendelson |year=2008 |origyear=1973 |title=Number Systems and the Foundations of Analysis |publisher= |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=3domViIV7HMC |accessdate= }}
* {{cite book
* {{Citation |last=Morash |first=Ronald P. |year=1991 |title=Bridge to Abstract Mathematics: Mathematical Proof and Structures |edition=Second |publisher=Mcgraw-Hill College |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=fH9YAAAAYAAJ |accessdate= }}
|last=Carothers |first=N.L.
* {{Citation |last=Musser |first=Gary L. |last2=Peterson |first2=Blake E. |last3=Burger |first3=William F. |year=2013 |title=Mathematics for Elementary Teachers: A Contemporary Approach |edition=10th |publisher=] |publication-place= |page= |isbn=978-1118457443 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=b3dbAgAAQBAJ |accessdate= }}
|year=2000
* {{Citation |last=Szczepanski |first=Amy F. |last2=Kositsky |first2=Andrew P. |year=2008 |title=The Complete Idiot's Guide to Pre-algebra |publisher=] |publication-place= |page= |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=wLA2tlR_LYYC |accessdate= }}
|title=Real Analysis
* {{Citation |last=Thomson |first=Brian S. |last2=Bruckner |first2=Judith B. |last3=Bruckner |first3=Andrew M. |year=2008 |title=Elementary Real Analysis |publisher= |edition=Second |publication-place= |page= |isbn=9781434843678 |url=http://books.google.com/books?id=vA9d57GxCKgC |accessdate= }}
|publisher=Cambridge University Press
* {{Citation|last=Von Neumann|first=Johann|author-link=John von Neumann|year=1923|title=Zur Einführung der transfiniten Zahlen|journal=Acta litterarum ac scientiarum Ragiae Universitatis Hungaricae Francisco-Josephinae, Sectio scientiarum mathematicarum|publisher=|pages=199–208|volume=1|url=http://acta.fyx.hu/acta/showCustomerArticle.action?id=4981&dataObjectType=article&returnAction=showCustomerVolume&sessionDataSetId=39716d660ae98d02&style=}}
|isbn=978-0-521-49756-5
** {{Citation|last=Von Neumann|first=John|author-link=John von Neumann|editor=Jean van Heijenoort|origyear=1923|date=January 2002|title=From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931|chapter=On the introduction of transfinite numbers|edition=3rd|publisher=Harvard University Press|pages=346–354|isbn=0-674-32449-8|url=http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=9780674324497}} - English translation of {{Harvnb|von Neumann|1923}}.
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4VFDVy1NFiAC&q=%22natural+numbers%22
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=Clapham |first1=Christopher
|last2=Nicholson |first2=James
|year=2014 |edition=Fifth
|title=The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Mathematics
|publisher=Oxford University Press
|isbn=978-0-19-967959-1
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=c69GBAAAQBAJ
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Dedekind |first=Richard |author-link=Richard Dedekind
|translator-last=Beman |translator-first=Wooster Woodruff
|orig-year=1901 |year=1963 |edition=reprint
|title=Essays on the Theory of Numbers
|publisher=Dover Books
|isbn=978-0-486-21010-0
|via=Archive.org
|url=https://archive.org/details/essaysontheoryof0000dede
}}
** {{cite book
|author-first=Richard |author-last=Dedekind |author-link=Richard Dedekind
|translator-first=Wooster Woodruff |translator-last=Beman
|year=1901
|title=Essays on the Theory of Numbers
|publisher=Open Court Publishing Company
|place=Chicago, IL
|via=Project Gutenberg
|url=https://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/21016
|access-date=13 August 2020
}}
** {{cite book
|last=Dedekind |first=Richard |author-link=Richard Dedekind
|orig-year=1901 |year=2007
|title=Essays on the Theory of Numbers
|publisher=Kessinger Publishing, LLC
|isbn=978-0-548-08985-9
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Eves |first=Howard |author-link=Howard Eves
|year=1990 |edition=6th
|title=An Introduction to the History of Mathematics
|publisher=Thomson
|isbn=978-0-03-029558-4
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PXvwAAAAMAAJ
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Halmos |first=Paul |author-link=Paul Halmos
|year=1960
|title=Naive Set Theory
|publisher=Springer Science & Business Media
|isbn=978-0-387-90092-6
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=x6cZBQ9qtgoC&q=peano+axioms&pg=PP1
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Hamilton |first=A.G.
|year=1988 |edition=Revised
|title=Logic for Mathematicians
|publisher=Cambridge University Press
|isbn=978-0-521-36865-0
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TO098EjWT38C&q=peano%27s+postulates
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=James |first1=Robert C. |author-link1=Robert C. James
|last2=James |first2=Glenn
|year=1992 |edition=Fifth
|title=Mathematics Dictionary
|publisher=Chapman & Hall
|isbn=978-0-412-99041-0
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=UyIfgBIwLMQC
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Landau |first=Edmund |author-link=Edmund Landau
|year=1966 |edition=Third
|title=Foundations of Analysis
|publisher=Chelsea Publishing
|isbn=978-0-8218-2693-5
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DvIJBAAAQBAJ
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Levy |first=Azriel |author-link=Azriel Levy
|year=1979
|title=Basic Set Theory
|publisher=Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg
|isbn= 978-3-662-02310-5
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=Mac Lane |first1=Saunders |author1-link=Saunders Mac Lane
|last2=Birkhoff |first2=Garrett |author2-link=Garrett Birkhoff
|year=1999 |edition=3rd
|title=Algebra
|publisher=American Mathematical Society
|isbn=978-0-8218-1646-2
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L6FENd8GHIUC&q=%22the+natural+numbers%22&pg=PA15
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Mendelson |first=Elliott |author-link=Elliott Mendelson
|orig-year=1973 |year=2008
|title=Number Systems and the Foundations of Analysis
|publisher=Dover Publications
|isbn=978-0-486-45792-5
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3domViIV7HMC
}}
* {{cite book
|last=Morash |first=Ronald P.
|year=1991 |edition=Second
|title=Bridge to Abstract Mathematics: Mathematical proof and structures
|publisher=Mcgraw-Hill College
|isbn=978-0-07-043043-3
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=fH9YAAAAYAAJ
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=Musser |first1=Gary L.
|last2=Peterson |first2=Blake E.
|last3=Burger |first3=William F.
|year=2013 |edition=10th
|title=Mathematics for Elementary Teachers: A contemporary approach
|publisher=]
|isbn=978-1-118-45744-3
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=b3dbAgAAQBAJ
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=Szczepanski |first1=Amy F.
|last2=Kositsky |first2=Andrew P.
|year=2008
|title=The Complete Idiot's Guide to Pre-algebra
|publisher=Penguin Group
|isbn=978-1-59257-772-9
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wLA2tlR_LYYC
}}
* {{cite book
|last1=Thomson |first1=Brian S.
|last2=Bruckner |first2=Judith B.
|last3=Bruckner |first3=Andrew M.
|year=2008 |edition=Second
|title=Elementary Real Analysis
|publisher=ClassicalRealAnalysis.com
|isbn=978-1-4348-4367-8
|via=Google Books
|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vA9d57GxCKgC
}}
* {{cite journal
|last=von Neumann |first=John |author-link=John von Neumann
|year=1923
|title=Zur Einführung der transfiniten Zahlen
|trans-title=On the Introduction of the Transfinite Numbers
|journal=Acta Litterarum AC Scientiarum Ragiae Universitatis Hungaricae Francisco-Josephinae, Sectio Scientiarum Mathematicarum
|volume=1 |pages=199–208
|url=http://acta.fyx.hu/acta/showCustomerArticle.action?id=4981&dataObjectType=article&returnAction=showCustomerVolume&sessionDataSetId=39716d660ae98d02&style=
|url-status=dead |access-date=15 September 2013
|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141218090535/http://acta.fyx.hu/acta/showCustomerArticle.action?id=4981&dataObjectType=article&returnAction=showCustomerVolume&sessionDataSetId=39716d660ae98d02&style=
|archive-date=18 December 2014
}}
* {{cite book
|author-last=von&nbsp;Neumann |author-first=John |author-link=John von Neumann
|editor-first=Jean |editor-last=van Heijenoort
|orig-year=1923 |date=January 2002 |edition=3rd
|title=From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931
|chapter=On the introduction of transfinite numbers |pages=346–354
|isbn=978-0-674-32449-7
|publisher=Harvard University Press
|chapter-url=http://www.hup.harvard.edu/catalog.php?isbn=978-0674324497
}} – English translation of {{Harvnb|von&nbsp;Neumann|1923}}.
{{refend}} {{refend}}


==External links== ==External links==
{{Commons category|Natural numbers}}
* {{springer|title=Natural number|id=p/n066090}} * {{springer|title=Natural number|id=p/n066090}}
* {{cite web
*
|title=Axioms and construction of natural numbers
* by ] at ]
|website=apronus.com
|url=http://www.apronus.com/provenmath/naturalaxioms.htm
}}


{{Number Systems}} {{Number systems}}
{{Classes of natural numbers}}
{{Authority control}}


] ]
Line 233: Line 447:
] ]
] ]
] ]

Latest revision as of 18:43, 7 January 2025

Number used for counting

Natural numbers can be used for counting: one apple; two apples are one apple added to another apple, three apples are one apple added to two apples, ...

In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers 0, 1, 2, 3, ..., while others start with 1, defining them as the positive integers 1, 2, 3, ... . Some authors acknowledge both definitions whenever convenient. Sometimes, the whole numbers are the natural numbers plus zero. In other cases, the whole numbers refer to all of the integers, including negative integers. The counting numbers are another term for the natural numbers, particularly in primary school education, and are ambiguous as well although typically start at 1.

The natural numbers are used for counting things, like "there are six coins on the table", in which case they are called cardinal numbers. They are also used to put things in order, like "this is the third largest city in the country", which are called ordinal numbers. Natural numbers are also used as labels, like jersey numbers on a sports team, where they serve as nominal numbers and do not have mathematical properties.

The natural numbers form a set, commonly symbolized as a bold N or blackboard bold N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } ⁠. Many other number sets are built from the natural numbers. For example, the integers are made by adding 0 and negative numbers. The rational numbers add fractions, and the real numbers add infinite decimals. Complex numbers add the square root of −1. This chain of extensions canonically embeds the natural numbers in the other number systems.

Natural numbers are studied in different areas of math. Number theory looks at things like how numbers divide evenly (divisibility), or how prime numbers are spread out. Combinatorics studies counting and arranging numbered objects, such as partitions and enumerations.

History

Ancient roots

Further information: Prehistoric counting
The Ishango bone (on exhibition at the Royal Belgian Institute of Natural Sciences) is believed to have been used 20,000 years ago for natural number arithmetic.

The most primitive method of representing a natural number is to use one's fingers, as in finger counting. Putting down a tally mark for each object is another primitive method. Later, a set of objects could be tested for equality, excess or shortage—by striking out a mark and removing an object from the set.

The first major advance in abstraction was the use of numerals to represent numbers. This allowed systems to be developed for recording large numbers. The ancient Egyptians developed a powerful system of numerals with distinct hieroglyphs for 1, 10, and all powers of 10 up to over 1 million. A stone carving from Karnak, dating back from around 1500 BCE and now at the Louvre in Paris, depicts 276 as 2 hundreds, 7 tens, and 6 ones; and similarly for the number 4,622. The Babylonians had a place-value system based essentially on the numerals for 1 and 10, using base sixty, so that the symbol for sixty was the same as the symbol for one—its value being determined from context.

A much later advance was the development of the idea that 0 can be considered as a number, with its own numeral. The use of a 0 digit in place-value notation (within other numbers) dates back as early as 700 BCE by the Babylonians, who omitted such a digit when it would have been the last symbol in the number. The Olmec and Maya civilizations used 0 as a separate number as early as the 1st century BCE, but this usage did not spread beyond Mesoamerica. The use of a numeral 0 in modern times originated with the Indian mathematician Brahmagupta in 628 CE. However, 0 had been used as a number in the medieval computus (the calculation of the date of Easter), beginning with Dionysius Exiguus in 525 CE, without being denoted by a numeral. Standard Roman numerals do not have a symbol for 0; instead, nulla (or the genitive form nullae) from nullus, the Latin word for "none", was employed to denote a 0 value.

The first systematic study of numbers as abstractions is usually credited to the Greek philosophers Pythagoras and Archimedes. Some Greek mathematicians treated the number 1 differently than larger numbers, sometimes even not as a number at all. Euclid, for example, defined a unit first and then a number as a multitude of units, thus by his definition, a unit is not a number and there are no unique numbers (e.g., any two units from indefinitely many units is a 2). However, in the definition of perfect number which comes shortly afterward, Euclid treats 1 as a number like any other.

Independent studies on numbers also occurred at around the same time in India, China, and Mesoamerica.

Emergence as a term

Nicolas Chuquet used the term progression naturelle (natural progression) in 1484. The earliest known use of "natural number" as a complete English phrase is in 1763. The 1771 Encyclopaedia Britannica defines natural numbers in the logarithm article.

Starting at 0 or 1 has long been a matter of definition. In 1727, Bernard Le Bovier de Fontenelle wrote that his notions of distance and element led to defining the natural numbers as including or excluding 0. In 1889, Giuseppe Peano used N for the positive integers and started at 1, but he later changed to using N0 and N1. Historically, most definitions have excluded 0, but many mathematicians such as George A. Wentworth, Bertrand Russell, Nicolas Bourbaki, Paul Halmos, Stephen Cole Kleene, and John Horton Conway have preferred to include 0.

Mathematicians have noted tendencies in which definition is used, such as algebra texts including 0, number theory and analysis texts excluding 0, logic and set theory texts including 0, dictionaries excluding 0, school books (through high-school level) excluding 0, and upper-division college-level books including 0. There are exceptions to each of these tendencies and as of 2023 no formal survey has been conducted. Arguments raised include division by zero and the size of the empty set. Computer languages often start from zero when enumerating items like loop counters and string- or array-elements. Including 0 began to rise in popularity in the 1960s. The ISO 31-11 standard included 0 in the natural numbers in its first edition in 1978 and this has continued through its present edition as ISO 80000-2.

Formal construction

In 19th century Europe, there was mathematical and philosophical discussion about the exact nature of the natural numbers. Henri Poincaré stated that axioms can only be demonstrated in their finite application, and concluded that it is "the power of the mind" which allows conceiving of the indefinite repetition of the same act. Leopold Kronecker summarized his belief as "God made the integers, all else is the work of man".

The constructivists saw a need to improve upon the logical rigor in the foundations of mathematics. In the 1860s, Hermann Grassmann suggested a recursive definition for natural numbers, thus stating they were not really natural—but a consequence of definitions. Later, two classes of such formal definitions emerged, using set theory and Peano's axioms respectively. Later still, they were shown to be equivalent in most practical applications.

Set-theoretical definitions of natural numbers were initiated by Frege. He initially defined a natural number as the class of all sets that are in one-to-one correspondence with a particular set. However, this definition turned out to lead to paradoxes, including Russell's paradox. To avoid such paradoxes, the formalism was modified so that a natural number is defined as a particular set, and any set that can be put into one-to-one correspondence with that set is said to have that number of elements.

In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided the first axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic. In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a simplified version of Dedekind's axioms in his book The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method (Latin: Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita). This approach is now called Peano arithmetic. It is based on an axiomatization of the properties of ordinal numbers: each natural number has a successor and every non-zero natural number has a unique predecessor. Peano arithmetic is equiconsistent with several weak systems of set theory. One such system is ZFC with the axiom of infinity replaced by its negation. Theorems that can be proved in ZFC but cannot be proved using the Peano Axioms include Goodstein's theorem.

Notation

The set of all natural numbers is standardly denoted N or N . {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} .} Older texts have occasionally employed J as the symbol for this set.

Since natural numbers may contain 0 or not, it may be important to know which version is referred to. This is often specified by the context, but may also be done by using a subscript or a superscript in the notation, such as:

  • Naturals without zero: { 1 , 2 , . . . } = N = N + = N 0 { 0 } = N 1 {\displaystyle \{1,2,...\}=\mathbb {N} ^{*}=\mathbb {N} ^{+}=\mathbb {N} _{0}\smallsetminus \{0\}=\mathbb {N} _{1}}
  • Naturals with zero: { 0 , 1 , 2 , . . . } = N 0 = N 0 = N { 0 } {\displaystyle \;\{0,1,2,...\}=\mathbb {N} _{0}=\mathbb {N} ^{0}=\mathbb {N} ^{*}\cup \{0\}}

Alternatively, since the natural numbers naturally form a subset of the integers (often denoted Z {\displaystyle \mathbb {Z} } ), they may be referred to as the positive, or the non-negative integers, respectively. To be unambiguous about whether 0 is included or not, sometimes a superscript " {\displaystyle *} " or "+" is added in the former case, and a subscript (or superscript) "0" is added in the latter case:

{ 1 , 2 , 3 , } = { x Z : x > 0 } = Z + = Z > 0 {\displaystyle \{1,2,3,\dots \}=\{x\in \mathbb {Z} :x>0\}=\mathbb {Z} ^{+}=\mathbb {Z} _{>0}}
{ 0 , 1 , 2 , } = { x Z : x 0 } = Z 0 + = Z 0 {\displaystyle \{0,1,2,\dots \}=\{x\in \mathbb {Z} :x\geq 0\}=\mathbb {Z} _{0}^{+}=\mathbb {Z} _{\geq 0}}

Properties

This section uses the convention N = N 0 = N { 0 } {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} =\mathbb {N} _{0}=\mathbb {N} ^{*}\cup \{0\}} .

Addition

Given the set N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } of natural numbers and the successor function S : N N {\displaystyle S\colon \mathbb {N} \to \mathbb {N} } sending each natural number to the next one, one can define addition of natural numbers recursively by setting a + 0 = a and a + S(b) = S(a + b) for all a, b. Thus, a + 1 = a + S(0) = S(a+0) = S(a), a + 2 = a + S(1) = S(a+1) = S(S(a)), and so on. The algebraic structure ( N , + ) {\displaystyle (\mathbb {N} ,+)} is a commutative monoid with identity element 0. It is a free monoid on one generator. This commutative monoid satisfies the cancellation property, so it can be embedded in a group. The smallest group containing the natural numbers is the integers.

If 1 is defined as S(0), then b + 1 = b + S(0) = S(b + 0) = S(b). That is, b + 1 is simply the successor of b.

Multiplication

Analogously, given that addition has been defined, a multiplication operator × {\displaystyle \times } can be defined via a × 0 = 0 and a × S(b) = (a × b) + a. This turns ( N , × ) {\displaystyle (\mathbb {N} ^{*},\times )} into a free commutative monoid with identity element 1; a generator set for this monoid is the set of prime numbers.

Relationship between addition and multiplication

Addition and multiplication are compatible, which is expressed in the distribution law: a × (b + c) = (a × b) + (a × c). These properties of addition and multiplication make the natural numbers an instance of a commutative semiring. Semirings are an algebraic generalization of the natural numbers where multiplication is not necessarily commutative. The lack of additive inverses, which is equivalent to the fact that N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } is not closed under subtraction (that is, subtracting one natural from another does not always result in another natural), means that N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } is not a ring; instead it is a semiring (also known as a rig).

If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", the definitions of + and × are as above, except that they begin with a + 1 = S(a) and a × 1 = a. Furthermore, ( N , + ) {\displaystyle (\mathbb {N^{*}} ,+)} has no identity element.

Order

In this section, juxtaposed variables such as ab indicate the product a × b, and the standard order of operations is assumed.

A total order on the natural numbers is defined by letting ab if and only if there exists another natural number c where a + c = b. This order is compatible with the arithmetical operations in the following sense: if a, b and c are natural numbers and ab, then a + cb + c and acbc.

An important property of the natural numbers is that they are well-ordered: every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least element. The rank among well-ordered sets is expressed by an ordinal number; for the natural numbers, this is denoted as ω (omega).

Division

In this section, juxtaposed variables such as ab indicate the product a × b, and the standard order of operations is assumed.

While it is in general not possible to divide one natural number by another and get a natural number as result, the procedure of division with remainder or Euclidean division is available as a substitute: for any two natural numbers a and b with b ≠ 0 there are natural numbers q and r such that

a = b q + r  and  r < b . {\displaystyle a=bq+r{\text{ and }}r<b.}

The number q is called the quotient and r is called the remainder of the division of a by b. The numbers q and r are uniquely determined by a and b. This Euclidean division is key to the several other properties (divisibility), algorithms (such as the Euclidean algorithm), and ideas in number theory.

Algebraic properties satisfied by the natural numbers

The addition (+) and multiplication (×) operations on natural numbers as defined above have several algebraic properties:

  • Closure under addition and multiplication: for all natural numbers a and b, both a + b and a × b are natural numbers.
  • Associativity: for all natural numbers a, b, and c, a + (b + c) = (a + b) + c and a × (b × c) = (a × b) × c.
  • Commutativity: for all natural numbers a and b, a + b = b + a and a × b = b × a.
  • Existence of identity elements: for every natural number a, a + 0 = a and a × 1 = a.
    • If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", then for every natural number a, a × 1 = a. However, the "existence of additive identity element" property is not satisfied
  • Distributivity of multiplication over addition for all natural numbers a, b, and c, a × (b + c) = (a × b) + (a × c).
  • No nonzero zero divisors: if a and b are natural numbers such that a × b = 0, then a = 0 or b = 0 (or both).

Generalizations

Two important generalizations of natural numbers arise from the two uses of counting and ordering: cardinal numbers and ordinal numbers.

  • A natural number can be used to express the size of a finite set; more precisely, a cardinal number is a measure for the size of a set, which is even suitable for infinite sets. The numbering of cardinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the empty set {\displaystyle \emptyset } . This concept of "size" relies on maps between sets, such that two sets have the same size, exactly if there exists a bijection between them. The set of natural numbers itself, and any bijective image of it, is said to be countably infinite and to have cardinality aleph-null (ℵ0).
  • Natural numbers are also used as linguistic ordinal numbers: "first", "second", "third", and so forth. The numbering of ordinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the order type of the empty set {\displaystyle \emptyset } . This way they can be assigned to the elements of a totally ordered finite set, and also to the elements of any well-ordered countably infinite set without limit points. This assignment can be generalized to general well-orderings with a cardinality beyond countability, to yield the ordinal numbers. An ordinal number may also be used to describe the notion of "size" for a well-ordered set, in a sense different from cardinality: if there is an order isomorphism (more than a bijection) between two well-ordered sets, they have the same ordinal number. The first ordinal number that is not a natural number is expressed as ω; this is also the ordinal number of the set of natural numbers itself.

The least ordinal of cardinality ℵ0 (that is, the initial ordinal of ℵ0) is ω but many well-ordered sets with cardinal number ℵ0 have an ordinal number greater than ω.

For finite well-ordered sets, there is a one-to-one correspondence between ordinal and cardinal numbers; therefore they can both be expressed by the same natural number, the number of elements of the set. This number can also be used to describe the position of an element in a larger finite, or an infinite, sequence.

A countable non-standard model of arithmetic satisfying the Peano Arithmetic (that is, the first-order Peano axioms) was developed by Skolem in 1933. The hypernatural numbers are an uncountable model that can be constructed from the ordinary natural numbers via the ultrapower construction. Other generalizations are discussed in Number § Extensions of the concept.

Georges Reeb used to claim provocatively that "The naïve integers don't fill up N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } ".

Formal definitions

There are two standard methods for formally defining natural numbers. The first one, named for Giuseppe Peano, consists of an autonomous axiomatic theory called Peano arithmetic, based on few axioms called Peano axioms.

The second definition is based on set theory. It defines the natural numbers as specific sets. More precisely, each natural number n is defined as an explicitly defined set, whose elements allow counting the elements of other sets, in the sense that the sentence "a set S has n elements" means that there exists a one to one correspondence between the two sets n and S.

The sets used to define natural numbers satisfy Peano axioms. It follows that every theorem that can be stated and proved in Peano arithmetic can also be proved in set theory. However, the two definitions are not equivalent, as there are theorems that can be stated in terms of Peano arithmetic and proved in set theory, which are not provable inside Peano arithmetic. A probable example is Fermat's Last Theorem.

The definition of the integers as sets satisfying Peano axioms provide a model of Peano arithmetic inside set theory. An important consequence is that, if set theory is consistent (as it is usually guessed), then Peano arithmetic is consistent. In other words, if a contradiction could be proved in Peano arithmetic, then set theory would be contradictory, and every theorem of set theory would be both true and wrong.

Peano axioms

Main article: Peano axioms

The five Peano axioms are the following:

  1. 0 is a natural number.
  2. Every natural number has a successor which is also a natural number.
  3. 0 is not the successor of any natural number.
  4. If the successor of x {\displaystyle x} equals the successor of y {\displaystyle y} , then x {\displaystyle x} equals y {\displaystyle y} .
  5. The axiom of induction: If a statement is true of 0, and if the truth of that statement for a number implies its truth for the successor of that number, then the statement is true for every natural number.

These are not the original axioms published by Peano, but are named in his honor. Some forms of the Peano axioms have 1 in place of 0. In ordinary arithmetic, the successor of x {\displaystyle x} is x + 1 {\displaystyle x+1} .

Set-theoretic definition

Main article: Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers

Intuitively, the natural number n is the common property of all sets that have n elements. So, it seems natural to define n as an equivalence class under the relation "can be made in one to one correspondence". This does not work in all set theories, as such an equivalence class would not be a set (because of Russell's paradox). The standard solution is to define a particular set with n elements that will be called the natural number n.

The following definition was first published by John von Neumann, although Levy attributes the idea to unpublished work of Zermelo in 1916. As this definition extends to infinite set as a definition of ordinal number, the sets considered below are sometimes called von Neumann ordinals.

The definition proceeds as follows:

  • Call 0 = { }, the empty set.
  • Define the successor S(a) of any set a by S(a) = a ∪ {a}.
  • By the axiom of infinity, there exist sets which contain 0 and are closed under the successor function. Such sets are said to be inductive. The intersection of all inductive sets is still an inductive set.
  • This intersection is the set of the natural numbers.

It follows that the natural numbers are defined iteratively as follows:

  • 0 = { },
  • 1 = 0 ∪ {0} = {0} = {{ }},
  • 2 = 1 ∪ {1} = {0, 1} = {{ }, {{ }}},
  • 3 = 2 ∪ {2} = {0, 1, 2} = {{ }, {{ }}, {{ }, {{ }}}},
  • n = n−1 ∪ {n−1} = {0, 1, ..., n−1} = {{ }, {{ }}, ..., {{ }, {{ }}, ...}},
  • etc.

It can be checked that the natural numbers satisfy the Peano axioms.

With this definition, given a natural number n, the sentence "a set S has n elements" can be formally defined as "there exists a bijection from n to S." This formalizes the operation of counting the elements of S. Also, nm if and only if n is a subset of m. In other words, the set inclusion defines the usual total order on the natural numbers. This order is a well-order.

It follows from the definition that each natural number is equal to the set of all natural numbers less than it. This definition, can be extended to the von Neumann definition of ordinals for defining all ordinal numbers, including the infinite ones: "each ordinal is the well-ordered set of all smaller ordinals."

If one does not accept the axiom of infinity, the natural numbers may not form a set. Nevertheless, the natural numbers can still be individually defined as above, and they still satisfy the Peano axioms.

There are other set theoretical constructions. In particular, Ernst Zermelo provided a construction that is nowadays only of historical interest, and is sometimes referred to as Zermelo ordinals. It consists in defining 0 as the empty set, and S(a) = {a}.

With this definition each nonzero natural number is a singleton set. So, the property of the natural numbers to represent cardinalities is not directly accessible; only the ordinal property (being the nth element of a sequence) is immediate. Unlike von Neumann's construction, the Zermelo ordinals do not extend to infinite ordinals.

See also

Number systems
Complex : C {\displaystyle :\;\mathbb {C} }
Real : R {\displaystyle :\;\mathbb {R} }
Rational : Q {\displaystyle :\;\mathbb {Q} }
Integer : Z {\displaystyle :\;\mathbb {Z} }
Natural : N {\displaystyle :\;\mathbb {N} }
Zero: 0
One: 1
Prime numbers
Composite numbers
Negative integers
Fraction
Finite decimal
Dyadic (finite binary)
Repeating decimal
Irrational
Algebraic irrational
Irrational period
Transcendental
Imaginary

Notes

  1. See § Emergence as a term
  2. A tablet found at Kish ... thought to date from around 700 BC, uses three hooks to denote an empty place in the positional notation. Other tablets dated from around the same time use a single hook for an empty place.
  3. This convention is used, for example, in Euclid's Elements, see D. Joyce's web edition of Book VII.
  4. Mac Lane & Birkhoff (1999, p. 15) include zero in the natural numbers: 'Intuitively, the set N = { 0 , 1 , 2 , } {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} =\{0,1,2,\ldots \}} of all natural numbers may be described as follows: N {\displaystyle \mathbb {N} } contains an "initial" number 0; ...'. They follow that with their version of the Peano's axioms.
  5. The English translation is from Gray. In a footnote, Gray attributes the German quote to: "Weber 1891–1892, 19, quoting from a lecture of Kronecker's of 1886."
  6. "Much of the mathematical work of the twentieth century has been devoted to examining the logical foundations and structure of the subject." (Eves 1990, p. 606)
  7. Hamilton (1988, pp. 117 ff) calls them "Peano's Postulates" and begins with "1.  0 is a natural number."
    Halmos (1960, p. 46) uses the language of set theory instead of the language of arithmetic for his five axioms. He begins with "(I)  0 ∈ ω (where, of course, 0 = ∅" (ω is the set of all natural numbers).
    Morash (1991) gives "a two-part axiom" in which the natural numbers begin with 1. (Section 10.1: An Axiomatization for the System of Positive Integers)
  8. In some set theories, e.g., New Foundations, a universal set exists and Russel's paradox cannot be formulated.

References

  1. ^ Enderton, Herbert B. (1977). Elements of set theory. New York: Academic Press. p. 66. ISBN 0122384407.
  2. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Natural Number". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 11 August 2020.
  3. Ganssle, Jack G. & Barr, Michael (2003). "integer". Embedded Systems Dictionary. Taylor & Francis. pp. 138 (integer), 247 (signed integer), & 276 (unsigned integer). ISBN 978-1-57820-120-4. Archived from the original on 29 March 2017. Retrieved 28 March 2017 – via Google Books.
  4. Weisstein, Eric W. "Counting Number". MathWorld.
  5. Woodin, Greg; Winter, Bodo (2024). "Numbers in Context: Cardinals, Ordinals, and Nominals in American English". Cognitive Science. 48 (6) e13471. doi:10.1111/cogs.13471. PMC 11475258. PMID 38895756.
  6. Mendelson (2008, p. x) says: "The whole fantastic hierarchy of number systems is built up by purely set-theoretic means from a few simple assumptions about natural numbers."
  7. Bluman (2010, p. 1): "Numbers make up the foundation of mathematics."
  8. "Introduction". Ishango bone. Brussels, Belgium: Royal Belgian Institute of Natural Sciences. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016.
  9. "Flash presentation". Ishango bone. Brussels, Belgium: Royal Belgian Institute of Natural Sciences. Archived from the original on 27 May 2016.
  10. "The Ishango Bone, Democratic Republic of the Congo". UNESCO's Portal to the Heritage of Astronomy. Archived from the original on 10 November 2014., on permanent display at the Royal Belgian Institute of Natural Sciences, Brussels, Belgium.
  11. Ifrah, Georges (2000). The Universal History of Numbers. Wiley. ISBN 0-471-37568-3.
  12. "A history of Zero". MacTutor History of Mathematics. Archived from the original on 19 January 2013. Retrieved 23 January 2013.
  13. Mann, Charles C. (2005). 1491: New Revelations of the Americas before Columbus. Knopf. p. 19. ISBN 978-1-4000-4006-3. Archived from the original on 14 May 2015. Retrieved 3 February 2015 – via Google Books.
  14. Evans, Brian (2014). "Chapter 10. Pre-Columbian Mathematics: The Olmec, Maya, and Inca Civilizations". The Development of Mathematics Throughout the Centuries: A brief history in a cultural context. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-118-85397-9 – via Google Books.
  15. Deckers, Michael (25 August 2003). "Cyclus Decemnovennalis Dionysii – Nineteen year cycle of Dionysius". Hbar.phys.msu.ru. Archived from the original on 15 January 2019. Retrieved 13 February 2012.
  16. Euclid. "Book VII, definitions 1 and 2". In Joyce, D. (ed.). Elements. Clark University.
  17. Mueller, Ian (2006). Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid's Elements. Mineola, New York: Dover Publications. p. 58. ISBN 978-0-486-45300-2. OCLC 69792712.
  18. Euclid. "Book VII, definition 22". In Joyce, D. (ed.). Elements. Clark University. A perfect number is that which is equal to the sum of its own parts. In definition VII.3 a "part" was defined as a number, but here 1 is considered to be a part, so that for example 6 = 1 + 2 + 3 is a perfect number.
  19. Kline, Morris (1990) . Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-506135-7.
  20. Chuquet, Nicolas (1881) . Le Triparty en la science des nombres (in French).
  21. Emerson, William (1763). The method of increments. p. 113.
  22. ^ "Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (N)". Maths History.
  23. Fontenelle, Bernard de (1727). Eléments de la géométrie de l'infini (in French). p. 3.
  24. Arithmetices principia: nova methodo (in Latin). Fratres Bocca. 1889. p. 12.
  25. Peano, Giuseppe (1901). Formulaire des mathematiques (in French). Paris, Gauthier-Villars. p. 39.
  26. Fine, Henry Burchard (1904). A College Algebra. Ginn. p. 6.
  27. Advanced Algebra: A Study Guide to be Used with USAFI Course MC 166 Or CC166. United States Armed Forces Institute. 1958. p. 12.
  28. "Natural Number". archive.lib.msu.edu.
  29. ^ Křížek, Michal; Somer, Lawrence; Šolcová, Alena (21 September 2021). From Great Discoveries in Number Theory to Applications. Springer Nature. p. 6. ISBN 978-3-030-83899-7.
  30. See, for example, Carothers (2000, p. 3) or Thomson, Bruckner & Bruckner (2008, p. 2)
  31. Gowers, Timothy (2008). The Princeton companion to mathematics. Princeton: Princeton university press. p. 17. ISBN 978-0-691-11880-2.
  32. Bagaria, Joan (2017). Set Theory (Winter 2014 ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 14 March 2015. Retrieved 13 February 2015.
  33. Goldrei, Derek (1998). "3". Classic Set Theory: A guided independent study (1. ed., 1. print ed.). Boca Raton, Fla. : Chapman & Hall/CRC. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-412-60610-6.
  34. "natural number". Merriam-Webster.com. Merriam-Webster. Archived from the original on 13 December 2019. Retrieved 4 October 2014.
  35. Brown, Jim (1978). "In defense of index origin 0". ACM SIGAPL APL Quote Quad. 9 (2): 7. doi:10.1145/586050.586053. S2CID 40187000.
  36. Hui, Roger. "Is index origin 0 a hindrance?". jsoftware.com. Archived from the original on 20 October 2015. Retrieved 19 January 2015.
  37. ^ "Standard number sets and intervals" (PDF). ISO 80000-2:2019. International Organization for Standardization. 19 May 2020. p. 4.
  38. Poincaré, Henri (1905) . "On the nature of mathematical reasoning". La Science et l'hypothèse [Science and Hypothesis]. Translated by Greenstreet, William John. VI.
  39. Gray, Jeremy (2008). Plato's Ghost: The modernist transformation of mathematics. Princeton University Press. p. 153. ISBN 978-1-4008-2904-0. Archived from the original on 29 March 2017 – via Google Books.
  40. Weber, Heinrich L. (1891–1892). "Kronecker". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung [Annual report of the German Mathematicians Association]. pp. 2:5–23. (The quote is on p. 19). Archived from the original on 9 August 2018; "access to Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung". Archived from the original on 20 August 2017.
  41. Eves 1990, Chapter 15
  42. Peirce, C. S. (1881). "On the Logic of Number". American Journal of Mathematics. 4 (1): 85–95. doi:10.2307/2369151. JSTOR 2369151. MR 1507856.
  43. Shields, Paul (1997). "3. Peirce's Axiomatization of Arithmetic". In Houser, Nathan; Roberts, Don D.; Van Evra, James (eds.). Studies in the Logic of Charles Sanders Peirce. Indiana University Press. pp. 43–52. ISBN 0-253-33020-3.
  44. Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? (in German). F. Vieweg. 1893. 71–73.
  45. Baratella, Stefano; Ferro, Ruggero (1993). "A theory of sets with the negation of the axiom of infinity". Mathematical Logic Quarterly. 39 (3): 338–352. doi:10.1002/malq.19930390138. MR 1270381.
  46. Kirby, Laurie; Paris, Jeff (1982). "Accessible Independence Results for Peano Arithmetic". Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society. 14 (4). Wiley: 285–293. doi:10.1112/blms/14.4.285. ISSN 0024-6093.
  47. "Listing of the Mathematical Notations used in the Mathematical Functions Website: Numbers, variables, and functions". functions.wolfram.com. Retrieved 27 July 2020.
  48. Rudin, W. (1976). Principles of Mathematical Analysis. New York: McGraw-Hill. p. 25. ISBN 978-0-07-054235-8.
  49. Grimaldi, Ralph P. (2004). Discrete and Combinatorial Mathematics: An applied introduction (5th ed.). Pearson Addison Wesley. ISBN 978-0-201-72634-3.
  50. Grimaldi, Ralph P. (2003). A review of discrete and combinatorial mathematics (5th ed.). Boston: Addison-Wesley. p. 133. ISBN 978-0-201-72634-3.
  51. Weisstein, Eric W. "Multiplication". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 27 July 2020.
  52. Fletcher, Harold; Howell, Arnold A. (9 May 2014). Mathematics with Understanding. Elsevier. p. 116. ISBN 978-1-4832-8079-0. ...the set of natural numbers is closed under addition... set of natural numbers is closed under multiplication
  53. Davisson, Schuyler Colfax (1910). College Algebra. Macmillian Company. p. 2. Addition of natural numbers is associative.
  54. Brandon, Bertha (M.); Brown, Kenneth E.; Gundlach, Bernard H.; Cooke, Ralph J. (1962). Laidlaw mathematics series. Vol. 8. Laidlaw Bros. p. 25.
  55. Fletcher, Peter; Hrbacek, Karel; Kanovei, Vladimir; Katz, Mikhail G.; Lobry, Claude; Sanders, Sam (2017). "Approaches To Analysis With Infinitesimals Following Robinson, Nelson, And Others". Real Analysis Exchange. 42 (2): 193–253. arXiv:1703.00425. doi:10.14321/realanalexch.42.2.0193.
  56. Mints, G.E. (ed.). "Peano axioms". Encyclopedia of Mathematics. Springer, in cooperation with the European Mathematical Society. Archived from the original on 13 October 2014. Retrieved 8 October 2014.
  57. von Neumann (1923)
  58. ^ Levy (1979), p. 52

Bibliography

External links

Number systems
Sets of definable numbers
Composition algebras
Split
types
Other hypercomplex
Infinities and infinitesimals
Other types
Classes of natural numbers
Powers and related numbers
Of the form a × 2 ± 1
Other polynomial numbers
Recursively defined numbers
Possessing a specific set of other numbers
Expressible via specific sums
Figurate numbers
2-dimensional
centered
non-centered
3-dimensional
centered
non-centered
pyramidal
4-dimensional
non-centered
Combinatorial numbers
Primes
Pseudoprimes
Arithmetic functions and dynamics
Divisor functions
Prime omega functions
Euler's totient function
Aliquot sequences
Primorial
Other prime factor or divisor related numbers
Numeral system-dependent numbers
Arithmetic functions
and dynamics
Digit sum
Digit product
Coding-related
Other
P-adic numbers-related
Digit-composition related
Digit-permutation related
Divisor-related
Other
Binary numbers
Generated via a sieve
Sorting related
Natural language related
Graphemics related
Categories: